Morality as Virtue: Aristotle

 

Virtue Ethics is a category of ethical theories which she actions as right or wrong depending on whether or not they flow from or are conducive to the formation of a good character. Central questions to any virtue ethics theory would be:

 

·         What is the good person?

·         What is the ideal person?

·         How do I achieve the Ideal?

·         What is “the good life” for a human being?

 

Summary of Aristotle’s Ethical Theory

 

Aristotle's Ethics is a systematic naturalistically justified version of ancient Greek ethical thinking.  Ancient Greek ethics stresses being virtuous- virtue ethics, as opposed to merely following moral rules (deontological ethics) or the consequences of actions (consequentialist ethics). 

 

Aristotle’s ethics is based on his definition of a “human[1]” as “The Rational Animal” and his teleological understanding of excellence (Functional Account of Good). Since the ability to reason (deliberate over courses of action and choose on the basis of those deliberations) is the one capacity or function which separates humans from other animals, being rational is our defining quality, our "final cause," our "telos."  The excellent human is the one who in actuality does reason well and choose his or her actions on the basis of reason.  (This is seen in my “Functional Account of Good” portion of these notes.)

 

Further, as creatures of habit, it is prudent (rational) to develop those good habits (Virtues) that contribute to successful living (eudemonia) evidenced in the lives lived by successful, thriving fellow humans (Virtuous Humans) through rationally enlightened practice.  (I cover this In my eudaimonia portion of these notes.)

 

The Ancient Greek Notion of: αρετη

 

Transliteration: arete or areté

Definition:        Virtue, excellence, moral excellence

Pronunciation:   ah-reh-'tay αρετη

 

 

Explanation

 

No English word or phrase captures the exact meaning of arete. The nearest equivalents are 'excellence' and 'virtue'. But there is something more to arete which cannot be expressed in words. There is something of the Divine in it. Perhaps the only true way to understand arete is to consider two or more examples of excellence and to contemplate what it is they share.

 

What does it mean when we say of an action, an artistic work, or some flawless athletic maneuver, that it is excellent? To behold what is excellent, in whatever form, brings us the same joy. We perform an action with excellence and say, "perfect!". In the moment of excellence, something transcends the mundane and touches the Ideal.

 

For Plato, arete is mainly associated with moral excellence. It is superordinate to specific moral virtues of Courage, Temperance, Justice, etc.; something they all share, a special, unnamed quality, their essence. It is clearly related to Goodness, but not the same thing.

 

For Aristotle, something is excellent when it manifests its unique purpose or telos. The unique, defining quality of human beings, for Aristotle, what makes them distinct from other creatures, is the capacity for rational thought. Human excellence, then, involves the correct use of reason, principally in connection with moral choice.[2]

 

Two Approaches to Aristotle: Telos

 

1. The Functional Account of Good

 

Aristotle tries to explain what “good” means in terms of function:

 

Functional Account of "Good"

 

            An account of good which claims that to say a thing is good is simply to say that it does what it is supposed to do and does it well (efficiently).  (Therefore a "good knife" is one which does what knives are supposed to do and does it well.)

 

X is good = X does what X's are supposed to do and does it well.

 

A thing is said to be good if it does what things of its kind are supposed to do.  This refocuses question of evaluation on questions of “proper function.”

 

Note: This is verifiable so long as one knows what X is supposed to do and this function can be specified and verified.  (As opposed to the function of a “phlogiston detector” for instance.).

 

Note: That means that if one does not know what something is supposed to do then one cannot evaluate it.

 

      Note: There are two curious, though perhaps reasonable, presumptions here.

 

u  That the world does, in part at least, break itself into “natural kinds”  (contra Nominalism)

u  And that these natural kinds distinguish themselves one from another in terms of function.

 

The Functional Account of Good works well and easily for human-created things because they are (most often) made for a specific purpose and we who made them (usually) know what that purpose is.

 

Note: When it comes to the products of human creations, for the most part this account of good seems perfectly reasonable (e.g. Consumer Reports can tell about good and poor toaster ovens or blow-dryers.), but we run into trouble in the case of art.  Aristotle would locate the source of our current difficulty in evaluating art NOT in the fact that we don’t know what “good” means, but rather in the fact that we do not have a clear universally agreed upon idea of what art is supposed to do.  He would explain our difficulty by claiming not that we are confused about the word “good,” but rather because we are confused about the word “art.”  We do not know the “final cause” or telos of art.

 

Aristotle had a teleological worldview.  This means that for Aristotle, to truly know what a thing is one must know is function or purpose.

 

Telos: Greek word for “end” or “purpose”.

 

Teleology: A system of ends and purposes./ The study of a system of ends or purposes.

 

Doctrine of the Four Causes:

 

Aristotelian Doctrine which holds that to truly know what a thing is, one must know four things about it.  That is, to explain what a thing is, why it is and behaves as it does one must know four things about it:

 

1. Material Cause: (What's it made of?)

2. Efficient Cause: (Who or what brought generated it.)

3. Formal Cause: (To what species and genus does it belong?)

4. Final Cause:  (What is it supposed to do?)

 

Imagine a thousand years from now someone is digging around in his backyard and comes across a curious object that he can see is very old, but he does not know what it is.  And he wants to find out.  So he takes it to his chemist friend.  “What is this?” he asks.  And his chemist friend replies, “Why I can tell you what it is: it is steel with some iron and chrome.  There is also a bit of rubber here.”

 

Despite the fact that what the chemist has said is true, our discoverer is not satisfied.  “Yes, that’s fine, he says to himself, but what is it?”  So he takes it so another friend of his, this time an Economic Historian.  “What is it?” he asks.  “Oh my, that’s an artifact, that is.” she says.  “It was designed by Franz Wagner.  It was produced in Underwood factories in New York sometime in the very early 1900s.” 

 

Ok, so now this guy knows how it came to be and who made it, but still, “What is it?”  He sees a third friend, an archeologist this time. “Yes I’m certain I can help you.  I know precisely what it is. It is an Underwood number 5.  It is very similar to the Densmore, but differs from that kind in that it is a 4-bank frontstrike version.  It differs from the Daugherty in that it was less likely to have its keys jam.  Well now our discoverer understands the object’s type, that is, he can recognize another one of the same type when he sees it and he can distinguish it from things of a different type.  He knows that class of things it belongs to in that he knows its form, but there is a sense in which he still does not know what the thing is.

 

Finally he takes it to an expert on Religion and Culture from the early 20th Century.  “I understand your difficulty,” she says.  “You know what it is made of (Material Cause) and how it came to be (Efficient Cause) and the class of things it belongs to (Formal Cause), but what you what to know is ‘What is it supposed to do; what’s it for?’  (Final Cause).  Well I can help you there.  This was called a Typewriter.  This was a machine by which people in the early 20th Century communicated with their gods.  They would sit in front of it all day and use the keyboard to type messages of praise or petitions for help to the deities.“

 

Now another friend is walking by and overhears this and says, “What?  Don’t be ridiculous!  That was not the telos of this thing.  The telos of this machine was to make music.  It was a percussive instrument and people would use it to play all sorts of complicated rhythms throughout the day,  Note the little bell on the side.”

 

Figure 1 What is it?

 

Well. if our discoverer believed either one of these stories he would be wrong, of course, and there is a sense in which he would still not know what this thing is.  He would still not know what the telos of a typewriter was and thus his knowledge of the typewriter would consequently be incomplete, this despite the fact that he knew the material cause, the efficient cause, and the formal cause.  He would still not know the final cause of the object.  And of course, eh still could not tell a good one from a bad one.

 

The Function of Natural Living Things: 

 

For The Functional Account of Good to be applied to natural objects (and ultimately to humans too), it will be necessary to know what the function of these objects are first.  Now the question becomes “what are these Natural Objects ‘supposed to do’?’” What is the “Final Cause” of an apple tree, for example?

Aristotle believed that natural objects do have purposes or functions and that these are discoverable to humans by observation.

 

Two ways Aristotle could have responded, but did not:

 

1. To Serve Human Interests:  Apple trees are here to serve humans and those that serve human interests well are good apple trees and those that do not serve human interests are bad apple trees.  But Aristotle did not go this way because it is unjustifiably anthropocentric.  He thought apple trees could be excellent completely apart from their relationship to humans.  Further, this is not fine-grained enough to distinguish a good apple tree from, say, a good pear tree.  Though distinct species, they would have the same function according to this view.

 

2. To Serve God: One might claim that God created apple trees and those that do what God created them to do are good and those that don't are bad, but he did not go this route because he did not believe in a creating God. (Aristotle thought that the Universe always existed in pretty much the same way as it does now.)

 

The Function of Natural Living Things:

 

Aristotle claims that the only things that apple trees are supposed to do is BE APPLE TREES.  – Presumably be the BEST DARN APPLE TREES they can be.  But that just means, do all and only the “apple tree things” (i.e. fulfill apple tree nature).   Thus, for natural organisms, the nature of the organism’s species, that is, the thing’s formal cause, is also the goal of the thing, its final cause.

 

In order to know what apple trees are supposed to do, (what the “apple tree things” are- apple tree nature- the apple tree telos) one must engage in an empirical study of the species and see what they do do.  Through careful observation one will be able to distinguish the healthy, thriving apple tress from the sick, diseased, withering apple trees.  Studying the characteristic behavior of the healthy ones will reveal the “nature” and thus the function of the species.  (Thus the normative force is provided by health vs. disease: i.e. one ought to be healthy/ excellent, one ought not be sick/ pathetic.)

 

Suppose you, a native Floridian, move up to my hometown in Pennsylvania and you buy a house, in part, because of the big apple tree in the front yard.  However, in the middle of September, you notice that all the leaves are turning funny colors and start falling off.  “Oh no!” you think, “There’s something terribly wrong with my apple tree.”  You call me up in a panic and tell me what’s going on.  “Calm yourself.”  I would reassure you.  That’s how apple trees are supposed to behave.  It is natural for apple trees to lose their leaves in the autumn.”  However, if all the leaves start turning funny colors and falling off your tree in the middle of May, when then, yah, you got a problem.

 

Note: This makes Aristotle a Naturalist with regard to ethics- one who argues that normative claims can be reduced to empirically verifiable claims.

 

Note :He is not contrasting good and evil; he is contrasting good and bad, healthy and pathological, vigorous thriving and pathetic withering.

 

What is the Human Telos?

 

He applies exactly the same reasoning to human beings.  He locates what he believes to be our unique and defining function.[3]

 

1. NOT the vegetative functions (eat and grow/reproduce) These are the minimal function for living nature.  As such these are part of our nature, but not unique to humans.  They are rather functions we share with all living reality.  This is how he divides living (organic) reality and non‑living (inorganic) reality.

 

2. NOT basic animal functions (locomotion or sensitive capacities) These divide the living world between “two kingdoms.”  Plants eat and grow and reproduce, but animals have these additional functions. As such these are not unique to humans, but rather functions we share with all living animal reality.

 

3. NOT our capacity for emotions. (Aristotle does not address this explicitly, but I believe he would recognize that other animals have emotions.) Emotional functions we share with other higher animals. This being so, these are not unique to humans, but rather functions we share with all living higher animal reality.

 

The Human Telos

 

The unique function of Humans is that we can reason.  Thus, reason is at once our defining trait and our telos.  Being a "good human being" or being good as a human requires that we reason and reason well. 

 

But Aristotle is not talking about the mere Theoretical Reason-Sophia (our exercise of reason for itself or to come to know truth), but rather Practical Reason- Phronesis, the use of reason to govern and guide our actions. He means reason to be the ability to deliberate over choices and to choose on the basis of those deliberations; we have the ability to consider two courses of action in the abstract and choose between the two based on rational appraisal.

 

n  Note: Here we see some of the significance of Aristotle’s famous definition of Man as:

 

“The Rational Animal”

 

Only three words but note their significance:

 

1. THE:

(definite article)

 

2. RATIONAL:

(Human Telos/ Segregating Trait)

 

3. ANIMAL:

(Unlike the Platonic notion of a spirit imprisoned only for a time in a body, Aristotle claims we are essentially animals with animal natures, just not merely animal natures.)[4]

 

“The Rational Animal”

 

Non-human animals act on the basis on instincts or emotional responses. Thus, their choices are not motivated or guided by rational deliberation over abstract choices.  We could (and sometimes do) live our lives the same way, but this would be living the excellent life of a pig, NOT the excellent life of a human.  Acting virtuously (as one is supposed to) for humans is acting rationally, activity in accor­d with a rational principle.

 

Two Approaches to Aristotle: Virtues

 

2. Eudemonia and Moral Virtues

 

Aristotle arrives at his conception of the “good life” for a human (as a rational being) by asking, “What is the natural good for man?" that is, what all humans desire "for its own sake" and not "for the sake of anything else."[5]

 

Here it is helpful to distinguish two kinds of “value.”

 

Intrinsic Value: Something has intrinsic value if it is valuable for itself and not merely for some other reason.

 

Instrumental Value: Something has instrumental value if it is valuable as a means to some other end (ex. money).[6]

 

Aristotle points out that some things we value because they are means to other ends.  But it cannot be that everything is valued (or have value) for some other reason for that would lead to an infinite regress.[7]  Thus, if we value anything at all there must be something we value intrinsically.  And this thing (or things) of intrinsic value is what motivates all our actions.  This is a teleological view of human action.  The idea is that thoughtful, deliberate action is goal oriented.  But this system of goals cannot be an infinite series (infinite regress).  There must be a Summa Bonum, a Final End of human action(s).

 

Three qualities of the Ultimate Good (Summa Bonum)[8]

 

1. Intrinsically valuable

2. Proper to our nature/ unique human good

3. Realizable; Can be acquired largely independently of being given from outside

 

Our final good? Happiness.

 

Eudemonia:      Aristotle's term for happiness in the sense of a state a thriv­ing, health, actualized well-ness and full human develop­ment.

 

Aristotle's special notion of happiness is not our con­ception of "feeling happy" or euphoria.  These are only unsustainable sensations.  Rather Aristotle is thinking of a stable state, like that of being healthy.   Aristotle’s term Eudemonia means something closer to "living well" or “thriving.”  And it includes all the natural human capacities (social, political, economic, creative, familial) and virtuous acts as well as good feelings.  No matter how good one feels (about oneself, life etc.) one would not be happy in Aristotle's sense unless one were living a life fit for a human being, actively fulfilling your human potential, being fully human.[9]

 

Imagine the new father that tells you he has a wonderful life planned for his newly born son.  He has amassed a huge stock of illegal drugs an he plans on keeping his son high for his entire life.  The child will only experience pleasure (no difficulty, no strife, no challenge) his entire life.  Would you approve of such a father?  Of such a life plan?  Would you wish that life for your own child?  For yourself?  Certainly not, Aristotle thinks.  Even though a life of unending pleasure may seem appealing at first, we quickly realize there is far more to being fulfilled as a human being (eudemonia) than experiencing pleasure.   

 

Further, happiness as with all judgments of virtuous functioning generally, is not a matter of black and white.  Few people are perfectly happy (excellent) and few people are perfectly unhappy (having NO human excellences of any kind to any degree). 

 

Close observation of the species reveals that some are thriving more than others.  Further, there are certain kinds of characteristic behaviors (character traits) that are necessary for or contribute to being happy (or at least, as happy as one can be given life's ups and downs).  These character traits taken in sum are what Aristotle refers to as The Virtuous Character. He recommends we attempt to develop it in ourselves and others as much as possible.[10]

 

(Moral) Virtue:

 

            Aristotle's term for a good habit which is necessary for or con­tributes to successful living.

 

So what ARE these good habits and how do we acquire them?

 

Doctrine of the Golden Mean:

 

            The Aristotelian doctrine which holds that a moral virtue is always the middle ground between two vicious extremes.[11]

 

Examples of Virtues[12]

 

·         Courage (midway between Cowardice and Rashness)

·         Temperance (knowing when to say when. midway between lasciviousness and asceticism)

·         Pride (Midway between hubris and lack or self-respect; made him unattractive to Christians.)

·         Friendliness (social skills necessary for eudemonia)

o    I like to point out this is not unlike our modern notion of “EQ” a cognitive skill/ability in which some people are pathologically deficient. Midway between obsequiousness and belligerence)

 

 

Vice of Deficiency

Virtuous Mean

Vice of Excess

  1.  

Cowardice

Courage

Rashness

  1.  

Intemperance/ Lasciviousness

Temperance

Insensibility/ Asceticism

  1.  

Illiberality

Liberality

Prodigality

  1.  

Pettiness

Munificence

Vulgarity

  1.  

Humble-mindedness

High-mindedness

Vaingloriness

  1.  

Want of Ambition

Ambition

Over-ambition

  1.  

Spiritlessness

Good Temper

Irascibility

  1.  

Surliness

Friendliness

Obsequiousness

  1.  

Ironical Depreciation

Sincerity

Boastfulness

  1.  

Boorishness

Wittiness

Buffoonery

  1.  

Shamelessness

Modesty

Bashfulness

  1.  

Callousness

Just Resentment

Spitefulness

 

So how do we acquire the “virtues?”  (Same way you get to Carnegie Hall. Practice. :-) )[13]

 

According to Aristotle, being an excellent human being is just like being an excellent golfer.  One becomes that by practice.  And keep in mind that practice, if it is useful, is a rational affair.  First you need reason to identify the virtuous humans to serve as your models.  Second you must use reason to analyze their example and discern the virtues.  Finally, you need reason to develop the good habits yourself, requiring constant performance assessment and reassessment. Education should be structured so that it develops the bodily and mental faculties.[14]

 

Four Levels of Moral Development:

 

Virtuous Person

 

            The top level of moral development according to Ar­istotle.  Has already developed the "Good Habits." This person is living the good life.  Because his or her behavior is shaped largely by good habits, actions do not require rational deliberation on an action to action basis.

 

Continent Person

           

            The second best level of moral development according to Aristotle.  This person can usually do the right thing, but for him or her it is still a struggle requiring both reason and will-power.

 

Incontinent Person

 

            The level of moral development according to Aristotle that is characterized by the fact that the person knows what the wise/right thing to do is, but lacks the will-power and self-control to do it.  Has the theoretical knowledge, but not the practical skill.

 

Wretched Person

 

            The level of moral development according to Aristotle where the agent not only lacks the good habits necessary for successful living, but even the awareness that his own bad habits are the cause for his misery.

 

Three types of Lives

 

1.     life of enjoyment

2.     life of the statesman

3.     the contemplative life[15]

 

Many suppose the life of pleasure is “the good life.”  But Aristotle rejects this as insufficient and not proper to our nature, being only proper to brute beasts.  (Previously noted here.) 

 

As for the life devoted to the attainment of honor or glory, Aristotle claims that this is not the true, proper end of a virtuous life either.  He criticizes it as “too superficial.”  For one thing, it depends upon those who give honor rather than the individual himself or herself.  One can be virtuous, but be despised by his community.  Conversely one can be a despicable human being, but somehow be honored by his community.  But our true “good” is something that is peculiarly a person’s own which cannot be taken away.  Further, he believes that many who pursue honor do so to be assured of their own excellence.  But that only shows that virtue or excellence is better than honor; and for these individuals at least, excellence is if fact the true end at which they aim. 

 

The third kind of life is the life of contemplation.  This is the highest kind of life for a human.

 

Romantic Critique

 

Now one might accept the functional account of good (i.e. “X is good.” = “X does what Xs are supposed to do and does it well.”), but reject Aristotle's notion of the human telos is or purpose he towards which he thinks all humanity is directed. For instance if one thinks of Romanticism and romantic heroes we find that they pursue values very different from those that Aristotle’s “Virtuous Human: pursues.  The Romantic hero typically is not motivated by reason but rather is motivated by Passion. The point of life is not “activity within the bounds of rational principle,” but rather experiential:  to love the greatest love, to feel the greatest patriotism, to burn with the greatest desire.  This is the purpose of human life. One thinks of Thoreau “I wanted to live deep and suck out all the marrow of life,”[16]  (I've always found that rather disgusting image myself.), but nevertheless the encouragement to “live life to its fullest” seems to be an essential part of Romanticism and the Romantic Hero.

 

Now if this is the purpose of life, if this is “the good” we should pursue then we have different virtues to develop, far different from the cardinal virtues of Aristotle and different persons will populate our Pantheon of Heroes. So one might say the good human being is one who does what human beings are supposed to do (functional account of “good”), but come up with a completely different ethical system.

 

Thomas Aquinas’s Critique

 

Similarly one can see Aquinas as adopting Aristotle's functional account of good but rejecting Aristotle's notion of what our true end or telos is. Aquinas agrees with much of this, but believes that Aristotle was aiming too low as to what it is that humans desire for its own sake (the true summa bonum).  Aquinas is critical of Aristotle on this point.

 

1.       What we really seek is not finite happiness, but rather infinite, indefinite happiness Aquinas maintains. (It's not like I want to be happy for the next five years and after that I don't care anymore.)   Close attention reveals that what we truly want is unending, unlimited ongoing happiness and fulfillment.  So Aristotle's worldly eudaimonia is not the true end we seek, nor can his (worldly/ cardinal) virtues tell us how to achieve that genuine end we desire, that is, our true Summa Bonum.

 

2.       Further, Aquinas thought he could prove the existence of an all-powerful and all loving God philosophically.  So belief in such a being need not merely rely on faith but on certain proof.  (For those who do not come to believe this as a matter of philosophy there is also revelation.)  Thus both philosophy and faith direct us to seek and even expect the happiness commensurate to God’s power and love.  (That is to say, Infinite- just what we wanted.)

 

3.       Thus for Aquinas, our true end (telos) is in the knowledge, service and love of God and to be united with Him in the afterlife.

 

I like to point out how influential Aquinas and for that matter Aristotle continue to be in terms of our thinking on ethics and specifically on the claims of Roman Catholicism. As some of you might know, Catholic grade school children are catechized before receiving first Holy Communion, learning some of the teachings of the Catholic faith. A much used resource though, I believe it has been replaced these days, in the catechizing of these young Catholic children was a book called the Baltimore catechism. The catechism is arranged as a series of questions and answers and children are taught to memorize both the question and the answer.

 

The Baltimore Catechism:

 

Baltimore Catechism No. 1

LESSON FIRST: ON THE END OF MAN (Emphasis added.)

 

1. Q. Who made the world?

A. God made the world.

 

2. Q. Who is God?

A. God is the Creator of heaven and earth, and of all things.

 

3. Q. What is man?

A. Man is a creature composed of body and soul, and made to the image and likeness of God.

 

6. Q. Why did God make you?

A. God made me to know Him, to love Him, and to serve Him in this world, and to be happy with Him for ever in heaven.

 

Question #6 is particularly interesting I believe.  While this is a question that a grade schooler could understand (and that is the target audience of the Baltimore Catechism), it is profound in its depth.  This is asking “for what reason do I exist?”  “What is my purpose or telos?”  By extension it is asking “What is the good for humans?”  To what end are they directed and how are they to fully realize their latent, potential human nature?”  This is the fundamental questions driving Plato’s and Aristotle’s ethics and the catechism provides Aquinas’ answer, an answer not too far from the thinking of both of these ancient Greek philosophers.

 

It is also worth mentioning that Aquinas accepts Aristotle’s definition of human (i.e. Man is the Rational Animal)  Thus the only kind of eternal life and eternal happiness a human can have is as an animal/ body.  Ah! But that is precisely the eternal life the Christianity promises.  And precisely what Christians are right to hope for, with God's help.  The eternal life promised by Christianity is NOT one as a disembodied spirit (Plotinus’ assent of the soul), but rather human existence as resurrected bodies, the same sort of existence Christians understand Christ to enjoy now.  Aquinas saysAnima mea non est ego.”  And that this was anticipated, in a way, by the Pagan philosopher Aristotle.[17] Hence Philosophy shows the necessity of the resurrection of the body, just as promised by the Christian faith, for everlasting human life.

 

I answer that, Man is perfected by virtue, for those actions whereby he is directed to happiness, as was explained above (Question 5, Article 7). Now man's happiness is twofold, as was also stated above (Question 5, Article 5). One is proportionate to human nature, a happiness, to wit, which man can obtain by means of his natural principles. The other is a happiness surpassing man's nature, and which man can obtain by the power of God alone, by a kind of participation of the Godhead, about which it is written (2 Peter 1:4) that by Christ we are made "partakers of the Divine nature." And because such happiness surpasses the capacity of human nature, man's natural principles which enable him to act well according to his capacity, do not suffice to direct man to this same happiness. Hence it is necessary for man to receive from God some additional principles, whereby he may be directed to supernatural happiness, even as he is directed to his connatural end, by means of his natural principles, albeit not without Divine assistance. Such like principles are called "theological virtues": first, because their object is God, inasmuch as they direct us aright to God: secondly, because they are infused in us by God alone: thirdly, because these virtues are not made known to us, save by Divine revelation, contained in Holy Writ.[18]

 

We seek not only happiness, but unending and indefinite happiness.  Further, since we can prove philosophically the existence of a good and loving all-powerful God (or so he thought) the kind of happiness we should expect him to bestow in happiness proportional to his power and love, that is, infinite bliss.  Thirdly, note that Aquinas also incorporate Aristotle’s notion that happiness is to be achieved by developing virtues. The theological virtues are three: hope, love and charity.[19]  And the greatest of these is charity.

 

Existentialist Critique

 

Finally, we might consider Existentialism which simply rejects any notion of a fixed human nature. We'll have more to say on existentialism later, but let's at this point acknowledge that existentialists would claim that the phrase “what human beings are supposed to be” has no reference. One of the central claims of existentialism is that there is not human nature and thus each of us must choose what “Being Human” means for ourselves. Your choice or anyone else's about what it means to be human has absolutely no claim on me.  Rather I must choose for myself what it means to be this humanity. While we think in terms of common nouns (human/ cat/ apple tree) we must live our lives as individuals.

 

It's somewhat paradoxical in exactly the way that Plato suggested. We think in common nouns but we experience the world as individual moments, individuals encountering other individuals. So what we think (common noun like “cat” or “cat form”) we cannot see (since we only see individuals) and what we see (individual, particular cats) we cannot think (the generic concept of or abstract concept of “cat form”).  But where is Plato thought the forms have a greater degree of reality, existentialist assure us that the really real is the individual confronting the world individually on individual terms. So what matters is not what human nature is but what I choose to be for myself. Consequently, since there is no human nature, one cannot apply the functional account of good to evaluate humans.  This is not to suggest that the existentialist claims there are no criteria by which to assess our lives. The criterion is to honestly look at our lives and embrace what we see. One must take a sober and unvarnished look at one’s life, and making to excuses, ask oneself am I living up to my own values? While this is indeed a subjective test, to ask and answer this question honestly and authentically can be very convicting.

 



[1] Actually Aristotle would have said “Man is the rational animal.”  He was an avowed sexist.  But I shall be glossing over that fact in these notes.

[2] http://www.john-uebersax.com/plato/words/arete.htm

[3] This will best be gained, I think, by asking, What is the function of man?  For as the goodness and the excellence of a piper or a sculptor, or the practiser of any art, and generally of those who have any function of business to do, lies in that function, so man's good would seems to lie in his function, if he has one.  But can we suppose that, while a carpenter and a cobbler has a function and a business of his own, man has no business and no function assigned to him by nature?  Nay, surely as his several members, eye and hand and foot, plainly have each his own function, so we must suppose that man also has some function over and above all these.

 

What then is it?  Life evidently he has in common even with the plants, but we want that which is peculiar to him.  We must exclude therefore the life of mere nutrition and growth.  Next to this comes the life of sense; but this too he plainly shares with horses and cattle and all kinds of animals.  There remains then the life (activity- KH) whereby he acts- the life of his rational nature, with its two sides or divisions: one rational as obeying reason, the other rational as having and exercising reason.  But as this expression is ambiguous.  We must be understood to mean thereby the life that consists in the exercise of (not the mere possession of) or the faculties of reason; for this seems to be more properly entitled to the name.

 

[4] St. Thomas Aquinas, the medieval philosopher and theologian, agrees with much of Aristotle.  Further, Aquinas points out this being so, the only kind of immortality humans could hope to have (qua humans) is a corporeal immortality.  Hence Philosophy shows the necessity of the resurrection of the body, just as promised by the Christian faith, for everlasting human life.

 

[5]

“The practice of every art and every kind of inquiry, and likewise every intentional act and every purpose, seems to aim at some good; and so we may say that "The Good" is that at which everything aims.  But a difference is observable among these aims or ends.  What is aimed at is sometimes the exercise of a faculty, sometimes a certain result beyond that exercise.  And where there is an end beyond that act, there the result is better than the exercise of the faculty.  Now since there are many kinds of actions and many arts and sciences, it follows that there are many ends also; (e.g. health is the end of medicine, ships of shipbuilding, victory of the art of war, and wealth of economy.)  But when several of these are subordinated to some one art or science. -as the making of bridles and other trappings are to the art of horsemanship, and this in turn, along with all else that the soldier does, to the art of war, and so on, -then the end of the master art is always more desired then the end of the subordinate arts, since these are pursued for its sake.  And this is equally true whether the end in view be the mere exercise of a faculty or something beyond that, as in the above instances.

 

If then in what we do there be some end which we wish for on its own account, choosing all the others as a means to this (not every end without exception as a means to something else, for we should go on ad infinitum, and desire would be left void and objectless), -this evidently will be the good or the best of all things.

 

...  It seems that men, not unreasonably take their notions of the good or happiness from the lives actually led, and that the masses, who are the least refined, suppose it to be pleasure, which is the reason why they aim at nothing higher than a life of enjoyment.  For the most conspicuous kinds of life are three: this life of enjoyment, the life of the statesman, and, thirdly, the contemplative life.  The mass of men show themsel­ves utterly slavish in their preference for the life of brute beasts, but their views receive consideration because many of those in high places have the tastes of Sardanapalus.  Men of refinement with a practical turn prefer honor; for I suppose that we may say that honor is the aim of a statesman's life.  But this seems too superficial to be the good we are seeking: for it appears to depend upon those who give rather than upon those who receive it; while we have a presentiment that the good is something that is peculiar­ly a man's own and can scarce be taken away from him.  Moreover, these men seem to pursue honor in order that they may be assured of their own excellence.  It is plain, then, that is their view, at any rate, virtue or excellence is better than honor; and perhaps we should take this to be the end of a statesman's life, rather than honor.  But virtue or excellence also appears to be too incomplete to be what we want; for it seems that a man might have virtue and yet be asleep or inactive all his life, and, moreover, might meet with the greatest disasters and misfor­tunes; and no one would maintain that such a man is happy, except for argument's sake.  But we will not dwell on these matters now, for they are sufficiently discussed in the popular treatises.  The third kind of life is the life of contempla­tion: we will treat of it further on.  As for the money making life, it is something quite contrary to nature; and wealth is evidently not the good of which we are all in search, for it is merely useful as a means to something else.  So we might rather take pleasure and virtue or excellence to be the ends of wealth; for they are chosen on their own account.  But it seems that not even they are the end, though much breath has been wasted in attempts to show that they are.

 

[6] Some point out that there is distinction between valued and valuable.  The first is straightforward empirical claim, especially if valued means “object of value-behavior.”  The second is less clear.  It implies that this is the object of rational desire, but that may differ from person to person given different objectives. Some have argued that it is unclear whether anything can be valuable intrinsically. They prefer to say that something has intrinsic value if it is valued in and of itself and something has instrumental value if it is valuable as a means to some other end. I don’t not understand the terms this way however.

 

[7] If I value “1” because it is an efficient means to “2,” and I value “2” because it’s a means to “3” and so on, this “regress” must stop somewhere; it cannot be infinite.  There must be some card holding the house of cards up.  There must come a point where I value “N” simply because it is what it is and it has the properties it has, and not merely as a means to some other end.  In other words, in order to make sense of the whole “valuing” project, I must posit a thing of intrinsic value, and “final good” or what Aquinas would call a “Summa Bonum.”  In the end, if I value anything at all, I can be certain that there is a Summa Bonum.  The only question is: “What is it?”

 

[8] ...  Let us return once more to the question, what this good can be of which we are in search.  It seems to be different in different kinds of actions and in different arts,- one thing in medicine and another in war, and so on.  What then is the good in each of these cases?  Surely that for the sake of which all else is done.  And that in medicine is health, in war is victory, in building is a house, -a different thing in each case, but always, in whatever we do and in whatever we choose, the end.  For it is always for the sake of the end that all else is done.  If then there be one end for all that man does, this end will be the realizable good, _or these ends, if there be more than one.

 

By this generalization our argument is brought to the same point as before.  This point we must try to explain more clearly.  We see that there are many ends.  But some of these are chosen only as means, as wealth, flutes, the whole class of instruments.  And so it is plain that not all ends are final;.  But the best of all things must, we conceive, be something final.  If there be only one final end, this will be what we are seeking, -or if there be more then one, then the most final of them .  Now that which is pursued as an end in itself is more final then that which is pursued as a means to something else, and that which is never chosen as a means then that which is chosen both as an end in itself and as means, and that is strictly final which is always chosen as an end in itself and never as a means.

 

[9] Note that this will also include, to some extent, living in a good community (since we are naturally communal animals).  So politics and ethics complement one another.  Being a good human requires living in a good community and the existence of good communities of humans is necessarily dependent upon there being good individuals.

 

[10]

Happiness seems more than anything else to answer this description: for we always choose it for itself, and never for the sake of something else; while honour and pleasure and reason, and all virtue and excellence, we choose partly indeed for themselves (for, apart from any result, we should choose each of them), but partly also for the sake of happiness, supposing that they will help to make us happy.  But no one chooses happiness for the sake of these things, or as a means to anything else at all.  We seems to be led to the same conclusion when we start from the notion of self-sufficiency.  The final good is thought to be self-sufficing (or all suffic­ing).  In applying this term we do not regard a man as an individual leading a solitary life, but we also take account of parents, children, wife, and in short, friends and fellow-citizens generally, since man is naturally a social being.  Some limit must indeed be set to this; for if you go on to parents and decendents and friends of friends, you will never come to a stop.  But this we will consider further on: for the present we will take self-sufficing to mean what by itself makes life desirable and in want of nothing.  And happiness is believed to answer this description.  And, further, happiness is believed to be the most desirable thing in the world, and that not merely as one among other good things: if it were merely one among other good things (so that other things could be added to it), it is plain that the addition of the least of other goods must make it more desirable; for the addition becomes a surplus of good, and of the two goods the greater is always more desirable.  Thus is seems that happiness is final and self-sufficing, and is the end of all that man does.

 

...  But perhaps the reader thinks that though no one will dispute the statement that happiness is the best thing in the world, yet a still more precise definition is needed. 

 

The function of man, then, it the exercise of his vital faculties (or soul) on one side in obedience to reason, and on the other side with reason.  But what is called the function of a man in any profession and the function of a man who is good in that profession are, generally the same, e.g. of a harper and of a good harper; and this holds in all cases without exception, only that in the case of the latter his superior excellence at his work is added; for we say a harper's function is to harp, and a good harper's function to harp well.  Man's function then being, as we say, a kind of life- that is to say, exercise of his faculties and action of various kinds with reason- the good man's function is to do this well and beauti­fully (or nobly).  But the function of anything is done well when it is done in accordance with the proper excellence of that thing.  If this be so the result is that the good of man is the exercise of his faculties in accordance with excellence or virtue, or, if there be more than one, in accordance with the best or most complete virtue.  But there must also be a full term of years for this exercise; for one swallow or one fine day does not make a spring, nor does one day or any small space of time make a blessed or happy man.

 

[11]

...  Excellence, then, being of these two kinds, intellectual and moral, intellectual excellence owes its birth and growth mainly to instruction, and so requires time and experience, while moral excellence is the result of habit or custom and has accordingly in our language received a name formed by a slight change from the word for custom.  From this it is plain that none of the moral excellences or virtues is implanted in us by nature; for that which is by nature cannot be altered by training.  For instance, a stone naturally tends to fall downwards, and you could not train it to rise upwards, though you tried to do so by throwing it up ten thousand times, nor could you train fire to move downwards, nor accustom anything which naturally behaves in one way to behave in any other way.  The virtues, then, neither come by nature nor against nature, but nature gives the capacity for acquiring them, and this is developed by training.

 

Again, where we do things by nature we get the power first, and put this power forth in act afterwards: as we plainly see in the case of senses; for it is not by constantly seeing and hearing that we acquire those faculties, but, on the contrary, we had the power first and then used it, instead of acquiring the power by the use.  But the virtues we acquire by doing the acts, as is the case with the arts too.  We learn an art by doing that which we wish to do when we have learned it; we become builders by building and harpers by harping.  And so by doing just acts, we become just, and by doing act of temperance and courage we become temperate and courageous....

 

[12] Historically, this list have been shortened to four “Cardinal Virtues” in classical and medieval philosophy as well as contemporary Catholic moral teaching.

 

Plato identified the four cardinal virtues with the classes of the city described in The Republic, each corresponding likewise to a distinct human faculty.  In the description of “a good city” he says

 

“Clearly, then, it will be wise, brave, temperate [literally: healthy-minded], and just.” (427e; see also 435b) Temperance was common to all classes, but primarily associated with the producing classes, the farmers and craftsmen, and with the animal appetites, to whom no special virtue was assigned; fortitude was assigned to the warrior class and to the spirited element in man; prudence to the rulers and to reason. Justice stands outside the class system and divisions of man, and rules the proper relationship among the three of them.”

 

In Aristotle's Rhetoric we find an expanded list “The forms of Virtue are justice, courage, temperance, magnificence, magnanimity, liberality, gentleness, prudence, wisdom.” (Rhetoric 1366b1)

 

The Roman philosopher and statesman Cicero (106-43 BC), like Plato, limits the list to four virtues:

 

“Virtue may be defined as a habit of mind (animi) in harmony with reason and the order of nature. It has four parts: wisdom (prudentiam), justice, courage, temperance.” (De Inventione, II, LIII [2])

 

Cicero discusses these further in De Officiis (I, V and following).

 

The cardinal virtues are listed in the Bible. The deuterocanonical book Wisdom of Solomon 8:7 reads, "She [Wisdom] teaches temperance, and prudence, and justice, and fortitude, which are such things as men can have nothing more profitable in life."

 

They are also found in the Biblical apocrypha. 4 Maccabees 1:18-19 relates: “Now the kinds of wisdom are right judgment, justice, courage, and self-control. Right judgment is supreme over all of these since by means of it reason rules over the emotions.”

 

Catholic moral philosophy drew from all of these sources when developing its reflections on the virtues.

[13] ...  Again, both the moral virtue and the corresponding vices result from and are formed by the same acts; and this is the case with the arts also.  It is by harping that good harpers and bad harpers alike are produced: and so with builders and the rest; by building well they will become good builders, and bad builders by building badly.  Indeed, if it were not so, they would not want anybody to teach them, but would all be born either good or bad at their trades.  And it is just the same with the virtues also.  It is by our conduct in our intercourse with other men that we become just or unjust, and by acting in circumstances of danger, and training ourselves to feel fear or confidence, that we become courageous or cowardly.  So, too, with our animal appetites and the passion of anger; for by behaving in this way or in that on the occasions with which these passions are concerned, some become temperate and gentle, and others profligate and ill-tempered.  In a word, acts of any kind produce habits or characters of the same kind.  Hence we ought to make sue that our act be of a certain kind; for the resulting character varies as they vary.  It makes no small difference, therefore, whether a man be trained from his youth up in this way or that, but a great difference, or rather all the difference.

 

[14]

Children should during their earliest years be carefully protected from all injurious associations, and be introduced to such amusements as will prepare them for the serious duties of life. Their literary education should begin in their seventh year, and continue to their twenty-first year. This period is divided into two courses of training, one from age seven to puberty, and the other from puberty to age twenty-one. Such education should not be left to private enterprise, but should be undertaken by the state. There are four main branches of education: reading and writing, Gymnastics, music, and painting. They should not be studied to achieve a specific aim, but in the liberal spirit which creates true freemen. Thus, for example, gymnastics should not be pursued by itself exclusively, or it will result in a harsh savage type of character. Painting must not be studied merely to prevent people from being cheated in pictures, but to make them attend to physical beauty. Music must not be studied merely for amusement, but for the moral influence which it exerts on the feelings. Indeed all true education is, as Plato saw, a training of our sympathies so that we may love and hate in a right manner.

 

[15]

...  It seems that men, not unreasonably take their notions of the good or happiness from the lives actually led, and that the masses, who are the least refined, suppose it to be pleasure, which is the reason why they aim at nothing higher than a life of enjoyment.  For the most conspicuous kinds of life are three: this life of enjoyment, the life of the statesman, and, thirdly, the contemplative life.  The mass of men show themsel­ves utterly slavish in their preference for the life of brute beasts, but their views receive consideration because many of those in high places have the tastes of Sardanapalus.  Men of refinement with a practical turn prefer honor; for I suppose that we may say that honor is the aim of a statesman's life.  But this seems too superficial to be the good we are seeking: for it appears to depend upon those who give rather than upon those who receive it; while we have a presentiment that the good is something that is peculiar­ly a man's own and can scarce be taken away from him.  Moreover, these men seem to pursue honor in order that they may be assured of their own excellence.  It is plain, then, that is their view, at any rate, virtue or excellence is better than honor; and perhaps we should take this to be the end of a statesman's life, rather than honor.  But virtue or excellence also appears to be too incomplete to be what we want; for it seems that a man might have virtue and yet be asleep or inactive all his life, and, moreover, might meet with the greatest disasters and misfor­tunes; and no one would maintain that such a man is happy, except for argument's sake.  But we will not dwell on these matters now, for they are sufficiently discussed in the popular treatises.

 

The third kind of life is the life of contempla­tion: we will treat of it further on.  As for the money making life, it is something quite contrary to nature; and wealth is evidently not the good of which we are all in search, for it is merely useful as a means to something else.  So we might rather take pleasure and virtue or excellence to be the ends of wealth; for they are chosen on their own account.  But it seems that not even they are the end, though much breath has been wasted in attempts to show that they are.

 

[16] Thoreau, Henry David. Walden Chapter 2 #16

[17] Well, actually no.  It is not clear at all the Aristotle thought there was a personal immortality.

[18] Aquinas, Thomas Summa Theologica Question 62, Article 1

[19] 1 Corinthians 13:13