Arthur Danto, “The Artworld”
The Search for Signs of Intelligent
Life in the Universe
Danto’s Answer to the Conundrum
Imitation
Theory and Reality Theory
The “is” of Artistic Identification
Arthur Danto, “The Artworld”, ABQ
Chapter 3, pp. 33-44
Arthur Coleman Danto (1924 – 2013)
Hamlet
ACT III SCENE IV
HAMLET: |
Do you see nothing there? |
QUEEN GERTRUDE |
Nothing at all; yet all that is I see. |
·
In
order that anything be art, a theory of art is necessary.
·
This
is revealed by the analysis of visually indiscernible things which are,
nevertheless, different items
·
They
are different because of the “theory” that constitutes them, not by any
intrinsic, visual property
“The Artworld”
In 1964, Danto
wrote “The Artworld”
This essay has
greatly influenced debates about aesthetics and art ever since. In it he was
responding to the monumental changes and innovations he was witnessing in this
and the previous 50 decades.
Preface: Danto
attacks Socrates and Plato’s view of art as imitation (mimesis0 or a mirror. He
calls this the “Imitation Theory” or “IT”. If this were correct, then any
mirror image would also be an artwork, which is obviously false. It’s true that
many artists both at that time and later did try to imitate nature in their
art. But the invention of photography put an end to this as the goal of art,
and showed that the mimesis or imitation view is false.
When he visited
Andy Warhol’s exhibition of Brillo Boxes at the Stable Gallery in New York he
asked himself a fundamental question:
What made Warhol’s Brillo Boxes different from commercial Brillo
boxes?
More
specifically, why are Warhol’s Boxes “Art” and the Brillo Company’s boxes are
not?
The Search for Signs of Intelligent Life in the Universe
The Artists: |
An
excerpt from the Play:
Here I am, I show'em
this can of Campbell's tomato soup. "This is
soup." "And this is
art." Then I shuffle the two
behind my back. Now what is this? No. I dread having to
explain tartar sauce! |
Danto’s Answer to the Conundrum
Danto’s answer to
this question, “What’s the difference” was “The Art World.”
This is a term he
coined to suggest that it is not possible to understand conceptual art without
the help of the artworld, that is, the community of art interpreters –art critics, art curators, artists, and art collectors
– within the network of galleries, museums and other art “institutions.”
Imitation Theory and Reality Theory
Arthur Danto
published “The Artworld” to explain this philosophical insight gained from artworks.
Dant points to
the need for Theory for something to exist as art. Theory provides us ways of looking at
paintings and regarding them as art. But
if our theories do not match our experiences, then we need new theories. This is analogous to development in the
history of science .
Theory –>
Deviations -> New theory
Danto contrasts
two concepts of “Imitation Theory” (IT) with “Reality Theory” (RT) Recall at this time there was still some
resistance to what was then “avant-garde,” that is to say, non-realistic and
not representational art. Previously, according
to IT, artworks were judged to be artworks only if they were an imitation of
reality.
(‘Imitation Theory’, also
mimesis: the idea that art is imitation of reality),
Danto contrasts
two concepts of “Imitation Theory” (IT) with “Reality Theory” (RT)
Roy Lichtenstein, American
(1923-1997). Ohhh…Alright…, 1964. Oil and Magna on
canvas. 91.4 x 96.5 cm (36 x 38 in). © Estate of Roy Lichtenstein. Private
Collection.
By contrast, RT
explains that art is something that is original and distinguishable. It can
look like an object that is not art, and therefore it cannot always be easily
recognized as an art object, yet it is easily and correctly recognized and
distinguished from non-art objects by those possessing the pertinent theory and
relevant facts. Danto says:
“According to it (RT), the artists in question were to be
understood not as unsuccessfully imitating real forms but as successfully
creating new ones, quite as real as the forms which the older art had been
thought, in its best examples, to be creditably imitating.”[2]
According to RT,
the acceptance of post-impressionist reveals that art objects are autonomous
things. IT ignores their
reality, concentrating instead on the “real objects” they represent. But for RT, the real painting (or other
object of art) are never ignored. RT
recognizes then canvases covered with paint as canvases covered
with paint. While consideration of the formal elements of
paintings was certainly involved in IT, under RT, it became acceptable to look
at paintings more on the basis of their formal properties, and less on the
basis of the quality of their imitation or representation. Contemporary art, Danto maintains, must be
understood in terms of RT. As an
illustration of how theory makes art possible, he points to Post-impressionist
painting. There could be no such thing
were it not for the RT. It simply would
not be considered art.
It is important
to make a distinction here between:
1. ‘it would not be possible to paint
these images’,
2. ‘it would not be possible for these
paintings to exist qua paintings’.
Certainly such
images could exist, but no one would/could/should related to them
as paintings unless and until equipped with a suitable theoretical framework.
Though it is true of some paintings that they would
not have been made if it were not for the development of certain ideas about
painting, that development possibly motivated by earlier paintings which may or
may not have had an explicit theoretical basis prior to their painting, Danto is
talking about how such paintings are considered, and whether or not they are
taken up into the art world.
He further makes
his point he cites paradigmatic examples where art objects are
indistinguishable or nearly so from non-art objects. For example genuine beds from those made by
Robert Rauschenberg (an actual bed hung vertically streaked with paint) and
Claes Oldenburg.
The “is” of Artistic Identification
Danto asks how
one can mistake the art for real beds?
This is equivalent to asking what makes them artworks. A naïve person (“Testadura”, Danto calls him) might not realize this is art
and might think it’s just a really messy bed.
To answer his question, he introduces another new term: the “‘is’ of artistic identification.”[3] This ‘is’ is used in sentences like “That a
is b.” where a is some specific physical property or part of an object. It is a necessary condition for something to
be an artwork that is can be the subject of such a sentence. So when I point to a certain dark region of
color in a painting that I say, that is my mother as a small child.” I am using the “is” of artistic
identification.
•
Danto
talks about the “is” at work in works of art.
•
This
bed is an artwork” is like “This blob (in a child’s artwork) is my dog.”
•
It’s
also like saying, of the Brueghel painting “Fall of Icarus,” “This blob of
white paint is Icarus.”
•
Danto
also gives two imaginary examples (top p. 38) of abstract artworks that look
the same but represent two different laws of Newton.
•
Danto
calls the “is” in these examples “the ‘is’ of artistic identification”.
•
We
can’t help the poor naïve guy Testadura understand
why this is art until he “gets” it about this “is”.
Danto shows how
this can make a very big difference in the way one relates to paintings. For instance he imagines the viewing of two
identical paintings (each a white rectangle with a black line through the
center). A hardcore abstractionist might
refuse to identify his black-lined rectangle with anything – “there is nothing
there but white paint and black”. Testadura, who likewise believes that the line represents/
nothing, does not “see” the painting (as an painting) at all.
·
Testadura:
There is no artwork, all he sees is paint
·
The
artist: That black paint is black paint
Danto: “We cannot
help [Testadura] until he has mastered the is of
artistic identification and so constitutes it a work of art” (139)
“To see something as art requires ... an atmosphere of artistic
theory, a knowledge of the history of
art, an artworld.” (140)
“It is the theory that takes it up into the world of art and keeps
it from collapsing into the real object which it is ...
The
abstractionist is employing the ‘is’ of artistic identification, and the
philistine is not.
If someone with
no aesthetic education simply says, “All I see is paint,” it’s just shows that
he fails to grasp artistic identification which will allow him/her to
constitute it a work of art. In pure
abstraction the artist has achieved abstraction through rejection of artistic
identifications, but in fact when Danto says, “That black paint is black paint”
he is not just repeating the obvious but using artistic identification.
“What in the end makes the difference between a Brillo box and a
work of art consisting of a Brillo Box is a certain theory of art. It is the theory that takes it up into the
world of art and keeps it from collapsing into the real object which it is ...
Of course, without the theory, one is unlikely to see it as art ...”
Developments in
modern art, especially post-impressionist paintings, challenged the IT, since
imitation just was not their goal. To explain or show why these new works were
art, a new theory of art was needed. The new theory also worked to make other
things start to count as art, such as masks and weapons from anthropological
museums. This new theory, the “Reality Theory,” or RT, didn’t pretend that
artworks were imitations, it almost threw it in your face that they were not,
since they didn’t look realistic, etc. Robert Rauschenberg’s bed is
BOTH, actual bed, which he hung vertically on a wall and streaked with paint
and an object of art. A naïve person (“Testadura”,
Danto calls him) might not realize this is art and might think it’s just a
really messy bed.
But Testadura’s error is a philosophical one. He thinks the bed
is just a bed, but it’s an artwork. There’s some theory that makes the ordinary
thing into an artwork, just like being alive makes a person into more than
simply their body.
Is of artistic identification
”This bed is an
artwork” is like “This blob (in a child’s artwork) is my dog.” Danto tries to
explain and understand the “is” in these sentences. It’s also like saying, of
the Brueghel painting “Fall of Icarus,” “This blob of white paint is Icarus.”
Danto also gives two imaginary examples (top p. 38) of abstract artworks that
look the same but represent two different laws of Newton. In one painting, the
line in the middle “is” the path of a particle. In the other painting, the two
squares “are” forces pressing against each other. Danto calls the “is” in these
examples “the ‘is’ of artistic identification”. We can’t help the poor naïve
guy Testadura understand why this is art until he
“gets” it about this “is”.
Thus Andy
Warhol’s “Brillo Boxes” look just like actual, ordinary ones. Why are they art?
Each Warhol box “is” more than a regular box; it ‘is’ an artwork, using this
new theory of art. “What in the end makes the difference between a Brillo box
and a work of art consisting of a Brillo Box is a certain theory of art” (p.
41). This couldn’t be art without a lot of both theory and history.
We have a valid
argument
If we have a work of art, then we have theory.
We have no theory.
Therefore
We have no work of art.
His claim is that
it is the work of art (the practice) that implies the theory, not the theory
that implies the work of art.
Danto coined the
term Artworld to suggest that it is not possible to understand conceptual art
without the help of the Artworld. The Artworld is defined in its cultural
context of the definition of art, or as an atmosphere of artistic theory. The
artworld both holds the IT and the RT, but mostly creates
itself in the RT. It created the notion that art is imitation of real objects
yet not objects themselves, also create the ability to discern art from that
which should be considered/ is art that should not be considered
art.
Here Danto
constructs what he calls the “style matrix” for art.
Representational Expressionist
+ + Artwork
is
both Fauvism
+ - Representational,
not expressionist Ingres
- + Epressionist,
not
representational Pollock
- - Artwork
is
neither Pure
Abstraction
Danto’s idea is
that whenever you give a list of the kinds of features or styles that art can
be made in, you also open up the option that someone will just reject those
features. (This is a lot like what Kant meant when he discussed how a genius is
someone who breaks the rules of art, and sets new rules by example.)
For instance, up until the 20th century most
painters thought of a painting as something done on a flat surface. But then
some artists (like Frank Stella) started to make canvases that were shaped or
curved and stuck out of the wall. And others made canvases in zig-zag shapes.
Or, one feature of art used to be that it involved or was made on an object,
like a canvas. But some artists began to make art out of light, so that the
light made shapes and designs. An example is James Turrell with his light
tunnel here in Houston at our Museum of Fine Arts. Another is the
displays of neon lights by Dan Flavin—you can see some at the Menil Collection’s Richmond Center which is in around the
1300 block of Richmond, across from El Pueblito Place
restaurant.
1.
Or,
the avant-garde composer John Cage made musical works that were just periods of
silence, where the musicians would sit there and not move!
Or the avant-garde playwright Peter Handke wrote a play called
“Insulting the Audience” in which the actors came on-stage and did just
that—insulted the audience!
Danto’s point here is that for almost any feature you can think of that seems
to belong to art, some artist is likely to come along and reject it at some
time, for some reason. This can only be true if somehow the artist
is helping create and advance in our theory of the relevant kind of art.