PHI3800 Lecture 5: 20th and 21st Century Theories of Beauty –
Three Versions of the Aesthetic Attitude Theory
1.
The Aesthetic State: Psychical Distance
·
Problems
·
Pros
2.
Aesthetic Awareness: Disinterested Attention
·
Problems
·
Consider
Vivas's Contentions About Literature as Aesthetic Object
#3
Aesthetic Perception: "Seeing As" (Virgil Aldrich)
·
Pros
·
Problems
20th
and 21st Century Theories of Beauty –
History of the organizing
strain of aesthetics.
“Beauty ended with the introduction of the concept of the
aesthetic.”
Out of the tradition of Schopenhauer there developed
"aesthetic-attitude theories."
Aesthetic Attitude theories claims to give the correct account of the
nature of aesthetic criticism and aesthetic appreciation. One must identify the correct subjective
“attitude” to adopt in order to make possible and aesthetic experience. The object of criticism is held to be "the aesthetic object" and it is
the “phenomenal object” that appears (arises) when one adopts the aesthetic
attitude. (Think of Kant’s disinterested
viewing here.) The attitude theories
have been challenged by "metacriticism."
Note: If being an “aesthetic
object” merely means being the object of someone’s aesthetic attention, then
nearly any object could be an aesthetic object so long as it was attended to in
the right way by someone. Saying that an
object is aesthetic tells you nothing about the object itself (nothing
objective), but only how it is being viewed.
(The ugliest thing in the world can be an aesthetic object.)[2]
Three Versions of the Aesthetic Attitude Theory
1.
Edward Bullough (28 March 1880 – 17 September 1934)
2.
Jerome Stolnitz and Eliseo Vivas.
3.
Virgil Aldrichs
3.
Chapter 4 is devoted to a discussion
and criticism of Monroe Beardsley's metacritical
version of aesthetic object.
From the onset, it should be acknowledged that it is not
completely clear what "attitude" means. Are they for instance “deliberate acts of
conscious will?” Spontaneously arising psychological states of persons? All these views claim that a person can do something (“achieve psychical
distance,” “perceive disinterestedly,” or “see as”) that will change any object
perceived into an aesthetic object.
1.
The Aesthetic State: Psychical Distance
Edward Bullough introduces the concept of psychical distance by using as an example the appreciation of a
natural phenomenon rather than a work of art.
For instance fog at sea can be an aesthetic object.
“Distance is produced in the first
instance by putting the phenomenon, so to speak, out of gear with our
practical, actual self; by allowing it to stand outside the context of our
personal needs and ends—in short, by looking at it objectively," as it has
often been called, by permitting only such reactions on our part as emphasize
the "objective" features of the experience.”
Bullough's account here is reminiscent of Schopenhauer's theory of
the sublime. Schopenhauer speaks of the
forcible detachment of the will (roughly the desires) required for the
appreciation of a sublime and threatening object. Not further, adopting such a perspective
focuses on some qualtieis of the fof
(perhaps its mistiness or mysteriousness) and not
other (that it is very dangerous to be at sea if you can’t see what’s in front
of you.) An inhibition may be induced by
the perceiver or it may be a psychological state into which the perceiver is
induced. Once the state has occurred, an
object can be aesthetically appreciated.
Bullough suggest that there are two ways in which proper psychical
distance can be lost:
1 “under-distancing”
2. “over-distancing”
An example would be of a jealous
husband viewing Othello. He is pre-occupied with his own suspicions
about his wife, so much so, that he cannot aesthetically appreciate the play.
Sheila Dawson, gives as an example
of over-distancing the case in which a person is primarily interested in the
technical details of a performances.
(e.g. the skill of the dancer, or the technique employed by the
painter) This is similar to Alison’s
critique that art criticism can destroy aesthetic experience.
Do we need to postulate a special kind of action called "to
distance" and a special kind of psychological state called "being
distanced" to account for the fact that we can sometimes can appreciate
the aesthetic characteristics of otherwise threatening things? It seems more economical to explain this
phenomenon in terms of attention. You are just “attending” to the fog. There is no virtue in being theoretically
economical if one ignores actual facts, but is seems that we can give an
adequate account of the “facts” of these sorts of appreciations without
positing a special kind of psychological state. The issue presumably has to be settled
introspectively, but Bullough suggests that to view threatening cases
aesthetically requires a mental mechanism to block worries about personal
safety. Dickie grants that there is some
initial plausibility when invoked to dealing with threatening natural objects. But he claims that it has very little
plausibility when it is used to explain our relation to works of art.
The husband who while watching a Othello, preoccupied with
his suspicions about his own wife is not failing to achieve the proper state by
“under-distancing.” Dickie we could more
economically account for this by saying he's simply not paying attention
to the play. One might explain
the audience member who mounts the stage to save the threatened heroine in the
play as one who has “lost psychical distance.”
But a better explanation would be that he has “lost his mind” or that he
is no longer mindful of the rules and conventions that govern theater
situations, in this case the rule that forbids spectators from interfering with
the actions of the actors.
Defenders see psychical distance as the first and key step of an
aesthetic theory, and it is held to have far-reaching implications. If an art work is such as to encourage the
loss of or inability to achieve psychical distance it is considered critically
flawed. Sheila Dawson and Susanne Langer
refer to the scene in “Peter Pan” in which Peter Pan turns to the audience and
asks them to clap their hands in order to save Tinkerbelle's life. They claim that Peter Pan's action destroys
psychical distance (or the necessary illusion).[3] Arlene Croce refused to view a work by
choreographer Bill T. Jones because, as is included many critically ill people
talking and dancing about the real-life illnesses, she claimed she was unable
to achieve a “psychical distance.”[4] For that reason, she maintained, the work was
not really art at all. It has
been crafted in such a way and advertised in such a way that made it impossible
for audience members to engage with it as a work of art.
1. Provides some basis for evaluating works of art.
2. A state of psychical distance
can reveal the properties of a work of
art that properly belong to the aesthetic object as a
aesthetic object (to which we ought
to direct our attention). An also what
properties we ought to screen off such as historical circumstances of the works
creation.
3. Provides substantive guidelines
for art criticism and appreciation.
(However. if no such state exists, it’s got problems)
2.
Aesthetic Awareness: Disinterested Attention
Jerome Stolnitz suggests that the
concept of “the aesthetic” can be defined in terms of disinterested attention. His
is an outgrowth of both the theory of psychical
distance and the notion of disinterestedness.
"psychical distance" names a special action or psychological
state.
"disinterested attention" names the ordinary action of
attending done in a special way.
Two
pairs of concepts:
1. interested/disinterested and
2. interested/ uninterested
The Former: financial interest, partiality and impartiality,
and/or selfishness verses unselfishness
The Latter: Notions of concern and attentiveness verses
indifferent and not attentive to it
If the distinction between the two pairs of notions is preserved,
it can be seen how a person can be both interested in something and be
disinterested concerning that same something at the same time. (For example, a
juror.) Similarly if I was reviewing a
piece of Real Estate and considering it as a possible investment this would not
be a disinterested viewing. This would be interested in the sense that I'm
considering practical game. On the other hand if I'm looking at it merely as an
example of landscape noting the trees the Hills the topography perhaps a patch
of wildflowers in the distance then I am viewing it disinterestedly not for
practical game but attending merely to its formal perceptual qualities and the
enjoyment such attention provides. But
note that I am not uninterested in this patch of real estate. I'm attending to
it closely..
Jerome Stolnitz's definition:
"disinterested (with no ulterior purpose) and sympathetic
attention to and contemplation of any object of awareness whatever, for its own
sake alone."
This is "intransitive" attention.
That is, there is no direct object of the action as the crucial mode of
attention.
If Ann is listening to some music in order to write an analysis of
it, then this is a “non-aesthetic ways of “attending to” etc. (Again, sort of
like Allison’s contention that criticism destroys aesthetic appreciation.) Accordingly, a work of art or a natural
object may or may not be an aesthetic object, depending on whether or not it is
attended
to disinterestedly. Central to
the theory is the notion that there are at least two distinguishable kinds
of attention and that the concept of “the aesthetic” can be defined in
terms of one of them.
But perhaps we can account for aesthetic phenomena more
economically with only one kind of attention.
Cases of alleged non-disinterested attention turn out to be cases of inattention according to Dickie. If so, then there is no reason to think that
there is more than one kind of attention involved. Also, while it is easy enough to see what it
means to have different motives for attending to an object, it is not
so easy to see how having different motives affects the nature of attention. Different motives may direct attention to
different aspects of the objects, but the activity of attention itself remains
the same.[5]
Another Issue arises: The question arises however as to whether a
fully disinterested attention can be conceptual or not. The application of concepts
such as that the auditory object of my attention is produced by an English horn
or a French Horm or that is a violin might one might say, be a interested
judgment rather than a disinterested appreciation. One might argue that a fully disinterested
appreciation of a phenomenological moment requires restricting one’s attention
to the immediately perceptible qualities without going on to make judgments
about what was the origins of those phenomenological qualities. But that in turn suggests that disinterested
awareness is very rare. It's not clear
how to separate listening to music and not interpreting the music as sourced by
particular musical instruments could be.
Consider
Vivas's contentions about literature as aesthetic object:
Vivas claims that his conception of the “aesthetic appreciation”
posits "that The Brothers Karamazov
can hardly be read as art," probably because one can hardly avoid reading
it as social criticism to some extent, which is one of the ways that Vivas
mentions literature is attended to non-aesthetically.
But this seems a counter-example; any theory that claims this (i.e "that The
Brothers Karamazov can hardly be read as art.") must surely be
suspect. Now we might be willing to
accept a theory which has counter-intuitive results (such as claiming that The Brothers Karamazov can hardly be
read as art), but only if it were the only way to explain the facts of
art/aesthetic experience. This does not
seem to be the case here.
Another alleged example failing to have aesthetic attention would
be using a work of fiction to diagnose the author's neurosis. But this seems better described as a way of
being distracted from the work rather than failing to attend to it in
the right way.
Another alleged example failing to have aesthetic attention is
(mistakenly) reading a fictional work as, history. But Dickie
counters, “So?” The historical or
socially critical content, if any, of a literary work is a part of the work
(although only a part), and any attempt to say that it is somehow not a part of
the aesthetic object when other aspects of the work are, seems strange.
Therefore, Dickie maintains, there remains therefore serious doubt
that such a species of attention exists.
Alternative (more economical) explanations of alleged
Non-Disinterested Attention.
·
Ann's attention to the music turned out to be just like that of
any other listener.
·
Bob's "interested attention" to the painting turned out
to be a case of not attending.
·
Free associating and diagnosing the author's neurosis turned out
also to be cases of not attending.
·
Attending to historical or socially critical content turned out to
be simply attending to one aspect of literature.
#3
Aesthetic Perception: "Seeing As"
Virgil
Aldrich developed an aesthetic theory out of one of the central notions
of Ludwig Wittgenstein.
Claims it is something that a subject does or something that
happens to the subject that determines whether an object is an aesthetic object
or not. Aldrich's view concludes that
there is an aesthetic mode of perception.
Wittgenstein called attention to ambiguous figures.
Most famous is "the
duck-rabbit":
(see: http://faculty.ccri.edu/paleclerc/existentialism/perc_figure.shtml)
Three
things can be distinguished
1. the
design the lines make on paper
2. the
representation of, say, a duck
3. the
other representation of, say, a rabbit.
Note
this phenomenon requires a more complicated model of perception then is
commonly appreciated:
1 |
2 |
3 |
4 |
Object
(Distal
Stimulus) à |
Retinal
Image (Proximal
Stimulus) à |
Active
Mind à |
Percept
(Duck
or Rabbit, depending on #3; that's the only variable.) |
Note
that whether one sees a duck or a rabbit is the result of something the
perceiver does, consciously or unconsciously.
Three things can be distinguished in the case of such figures.
1. the design the lines make on paper
2. the perception of, say, a duck
3. the other perception of, say, a rabbit.
Aldrich claims that aesthetic
theory parallels the perceptual phenomenon of ambiguous figures. He argues that earlier theorists were
mistaken in thinking that there is only one mode of perception. There are two: the aesthetic mode of perception
and the
non-aesthetic mode of perception.
1. Non-aesthetic
("observation")
2. Aesthetic mode
("prehension")
Observation and its object ("physical object") parallel
the “seeing of, say, the duck.” Prehension
and its object ("aesthetic object") parallel the seeing of, say,
“seeing of the rabbit.” The parallel of
the ambiguous design made on the paper itself Aldrich calls a "material object."
Thus we have (paralleling the above):
1. Material Object
2. Physical Object (Observation and its subsequent perception)
3. Aesthetic Object (Prehension and its subsequent perception)
Thus a material object is seen as a physical object when observed
and as an aesthetic object when prehended.
A neat solution to the problem of aesthetic object.
1.
It avoids any commitment to disinterested attention or psychical
distance, which were seen to involve difficulties.
2.
It purports to be a development out of one of the most powerful
and influential philosophical movements of the twentieth century, the philosophy
of Wittgenstein.
True?
Is there any good evidence for his contention that there really
are two modes of perception? (There doesn’t seems to be.) The fact that a single design can function
alternatively as two representations gives no evidence for two modes of
perception. For example, the seeing of
the duck representation is exactly like the seeing of the rabbit representation
so far as “the seeing: is concerned.
The notion of “seeing as” may be useful
in providing an analysis of the concept of representation (interpretations),
but that is clearly another matter.
The only evidence that Aldrich gives is this alleged example:
a dark city and a pale western sky
at dusk, meeting at the sky line.
The sky is closer to the viewer
than are the dark areas of buildings.
This is the disposition of these
material things in aesthetic space.
The fact, however, that things look different and that visual
relations appear to alter under varying conditions of lighting is no reason for
thinking that there are two modes of perceiving that a person can switch off or
on. Aldrich writes that aesthetic perception "is, if you like, an
'impressionistic' way of looking, but still a mode of perception."
But, Dickie counters:
1.
Does it makes sense to speak of an “impressionistic way of
looking?”
2.
It is not the case that all the experiences we call aesthetic are
impressionistic, although perhaps some are. (What is impressionistic about
watching Hamlet?)
Another example: Watching illuminated snowflakes falling at night.
·
Does not serve as evidence for the theory that there are two ways
of perceiving.
·
Aldrich has given us no reasonable evidence for the truth of his
theory.
Aesthetic-attitude theories grew out of such nineteenth-century
theories with roots in
the eighteenth-century notion of disinterestedness and the view
that a psychological analysis aesthetic experience is the key to a correct
theory. But they reject the
eighteenth-century assumption that some particular feature of the world such as
uniformity in variety triggers the aesthetic, or taste, response. Instead, the aesthetic-attitude theories
share with the nineteenth-century aesthetic theories the view that any object
(with certain reservations about the obscene and the disgusting) can become an
object of aesthetic appreciation. Still,
they reject the nineteenth-century assumption that aesthetic theory must be
embedded in a comprehensive metaphysical system, (e.g., Schopenhauer's
philosophical system).
Theories of aesthetic attitude have three main goals.
1.
Isolate and describe the psychological factors constituting the
“aesthetic attitude.“’
2.
Develop a conception of aesthetic object as that which is the
object of the aesthetic attitude.
3.
Account for aesthetic experience by conceiving of it as “the
experience derived from an aesthetic object.”
Aesthetic-attitude theories held that these works of art contain
elements that are not only aesthetically irrelevant, but positively destructive
to aesthetic values. But to make this
case, they must define “aesthetic properties” (those relevant to aesthetic
appreciation) in a non-question begging way.
The danger is that they seem to be defining/explaining aesthetic
experience in terms of aesthetic properties in terms of aesthetic attitude in
terms of aesthetic experience.
(Viciously circular and, as such, pseudo-explanations.)
For these theories, an aesthetic object has the function of being
the proper locus of appreciation and criticism (with criticism understood as
including description, interpretation, and evaluation). But while this seems counterintuitive and
out of step with actual practice, they offer no compensating explanatory power.
Jerome Stolnitz
et al. attempt to explain the class of experiences referred to as “aesthetic”
by a certain frame of mind: the "aesthetic attitude." Stolnitz'
definition: the aesthetic attitude is "disinterested and sympathetic
attention to and contemplation of any object of awareness whatever, for its own
sake alone." "Disinterested" means "no concern for any
ulterior purpose," "sympathetic" means "accept the object
on its own terms to appreciate it," and "contemplation" means
"perception directed toward the object in its own right where the
spectator is not concerned to analyze it or ask questions about it."
But Dickie suggests that no successful argument has been given for
believing these accounts. It is not
clear that there really is any such thing or that the target experiences cannot
be explained without positing such.
Further, Dickie suggests that the very notion of “disinterested
attention” is incoherent. Once one
considers the motivations that exist is considered,,
there is no reason for suggesting that b the attending to a thing makes no perceptual
difference. An unique way of kind of
paying attention. But there's no reason to claim this. One of the other paying
attention or not and the elements to which one is paying attention might be
directed by certain motives or others but that doesn't suggest that there is a
unique way of paying attention to the object. The idea of "disinterested
attention" is only sensible if "interested attention" can be
distinguished from “disinterested attention.”
But it cannot Dickie maintains, because in all cases, "interested
attention" is not really a special kind of attention, but
rather, perception with different motivations or intentions>> The “attention” remains the same.
Thus Dickie argues against the idea of the aesthetic attitude in
all its forms.
Publisher : Oxford University Press; 1st edition
(January 9, 1997)
ISBN-10 : 0195113047
ISBN-13 : 978-0195113044
[2]This, it seems to me, is a reductio of the whole theory.
[3] Ironically, many have described that as one of the highlights of their experience of the movie.
[4] See Croce, Arlene “DISCUSSING THE UNDISCUSSABLE,” The New Yorker, December 18, 1994
[5] I would suggest that the properties of the object to which one attends can be specified in terms of motive. Some motives are aesthetic while others are not. If so, then understanding the motives may go some way towards identifying what properties are and what properties are not “aesthetic” and thus the proper object a aesthetic criticism.