Real Beauty[1]
Eddy M. Zemach
MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY, XVI (1991)
1.
Argument
from Aesthetic Relativism/ Subjectivism[KH1]
·
By Analogy
from Common Stimuli
·
By Analogy
from Common Reaction
·
By Analogy
from Other Predicates
Aesthetic Anti-realism Is Not True
2. Standard Observation Conditions
3. Proofs from Scientific Realism
Are
Aesthetic Explanations Impotent?
·
Response
4. Proofs from Scientific Realism 2
5.
Proofs
for Metaphysical Realists
EDDY M. ZEMACH
Not all the predicates in our language designate properties of
things in the real world.
Ex: The fact that we say things
like “Peaches are delicious.” does NOT prove that there must be a property of
"deliciousness." It might
merely be that the sentence "Peaches are delicious." is the
linguistic equivalent of "Mmm, peaches!" If so the "delicious" doe not name
a predicate/property; it merely exists as a linguistic device for expressing
emotively.
Similarly, from the sentence “She danced a waltz.” we might
presume that there exists such a “thing” as a waltz. (It uses a transitive verb which takes
“waltz” as its direct object.) However,
we express the same meaning with the sentence: “She waltzed.” This is an intransitive verb, has no direct
object and thus does not commit us to the existence of “waltzes.”
Do aesthetic predicates designate “objective properties?” Or are they merely emotive devises? (e.g. “That painting is beautiful.” = “Yeah
that painting!”)
Zemach argues: Yes, aesthetic properties are real, objective,
mind-independent properties.
1)
Argument from Aesthetic
Relativism/ Subjectivism[KH2] (RELATIVISM)
Why do people doubt aesthetic realism and embrace aesthetic
relativism (subjectivism).
If ‘A’ is an aesthetic predicate, to utter a sentence of the form
‘X is A’ is to say that X appears A to one.
EX: Pretty: “X is pretty.” = “X
appears pretty to me.”
This leaves open the question as to whether "pretty" is
a property of X (objective) or merely the perception of X (subjective).
So far so good. But…
Even on the subjective account, we must be able to explain the
fact that we all seem to mean pretty much the same thing when we use the term
"pretty." After all, if al
call a young woman pretty and you call her ugly, I know you to have said
something insulting and I to have said something complementary- postmodernism
aside.
Like ‘It hurts.’ aesthetic judgments seem to refer to private
experience.
“If aesthetic terms apply to
private objects, then Jones has never examined anything to
which Smith ascribes any aesthetic predicate and vice versa. No one
can know what objects Jones calls ‘gaudy’"
If this is so, then one can never
know whether Jones (or anyone else) is applying the term rightly or even
consistently. Frankly, even Jones can’t
know what he means since he has only his unreliable memory to know whether that
private sensation that he previously names "pretty" is the same as or
anything like that private sensation he now names pretty.
(This is sort of an application of Wittgenstein’s private language
argument.)
But if this is really what it going on, it raises all sorts of
questions:
This is, of course, a Wittgensteinian
point. If the consequence of relativism (subjectivism) is that it makes
aesthetic predicates meaningless, then relativism (subjectivism) defeats its
own suggested solution.
The Defender of Aesthetic Relativism/ Subjectivism (the
Anti-realist) might argue that subjective terms can be and are learned
and have public shared meaning. There are three good ways to learn (understand
and use) predicates attributable to internal items.
By Analogy from Common Stimuli
e.g. I know what you mean when you
say "I stubbing my toe and it hurt." because I have stubbed my toe
and it hurt (me).
But…
If the same stimulus may cause radically
different aesthetic experiences in different people, then our use of
the same aesthetic term for the same stimulus object does not indicate that we
use it to convey the same meaning.
We can assume that by similar phonemes
we refer to the same property only if we tend to make similar aesthetic
judgments of similar objects. (most of the time). Yet relativists in aesthetics hold that they
same stimulus brings about aesthetically distinct internal states in people. Thus
no one can know what the others mean by any aesthetic term they use.
By Analogy from Common Reaction
I know what you mean when you say
"I stubbing my toe and it hurt." Because you're holding your foot and
moaning just like I hold my foot and moan when I stub my toe.
But…
(if the relativist/subjectivist is
right then…t)he second way, using behavioral criteria, is also blocked, because
no aesthetic predicate has a specific behavior that is typical to it. One
cannot learn what ‘gaudy’ means from the way people behave with respect to
objects that they see as gaudy, for there is no seeing-as-gaudy behavior.
Behavior makes sense when related
to things we know; but relativism associates aesthetic reactions not with
public objects but with unknowable subjective items. Had it been so, we could
not make any sense of aesthetic reactions. Therefore, behavior cannot be used
by relativists to make sense of our aesthetic terms.
By Analogy from Other Predicates
I know what you mean when you say
you have a headache because you go on to say, "It like stubbing your toe,
only in your head.
The third way, analogy from other
predicates, is also closed to the relativist in aesthetics. One can learn what ‘gaudy’ means by
comparison with other aesthetic predicates.
(You have already got to
understand a set of analogous aesthetic predicates (via ways one or two) in
order to have pre-understood predicates with which to set up the analogy. Note I might tell you that pink lies
somewhere between red and white, but that will only work if your already understood
"red" and "white.")
To explain aesthetic terms by non-aesthetic
ones is like the proverbial explanation of colors by acoustic analogs.
Aesthetic Anti-realism Is Not True
Thus if relativism in aesthetics is correct;
To put this in the most simple terms:
If Aesthetic Anti-realism is true,
we could have no understanding of what anyone means when they use aesthetic
predicate (even one's self).
We DO have some understanding of
what people mean when they use aesthetic predicates.
Therefore:
Aesthetic Anti-realism is not
true.
There can be radical disagreement on the application of defined,
non-observational, predicates; but aesthetic predicates are
(relativists admit) observational, so there can be no radical disagreement about
them.
2. Standard Observation Conditions
“Red,” is a property whose standard observation conditions (SOC)
can be adopted by most people and require no instruments or special training.
By contrast Zemach suggests that aesthetic properties too have SOC’s
but that the conditions that are standard for observing aesthetic properties
involve experts[2].
“The
very notion of empirical data involves SOC, for the findings of observations or
measurements conducted under non standard conditions cannot be treated as data,
detached from the conditions in which they were observed.”
Observational properties must always be understood to involve
SOC: Some are specialized, but that is
true both in and out of science.
To have empirical data at all, one needs, consciously or
unconsciously to have in mind the SOC.
Thus one need always to ask what observation conditions are standard.
C are SOC for a family of
properties F iff for any member Fl of F, X would look
F1 under C iff F1(X).
If we justifiably believe that F1(X) we may
call the conditions C in which X appears F1 ‘standard’, but if X is not F1, C
are nonstandard after all. [KH3]
This sounds really complicated but all he is saying is that some
set of conditions are the proper standard observation conditions for some
family of observational properties if and only if an object with one of those
properties would appear to have that property and an object without that
property would not appear to have that property.
Let's try again: A set of
conditions is the SOC for color properties if and only if red object appear red
under the these conditions and non-red object do NOT appear red.
Some set of conditions as the SOC for observing “color” if and
only if for “red’ something (X) would appear red under that set of conditions
if and only if it (X) is red.
Nonstandard conditions are external and internal conditions that
induce illusion.
External Conditions: when a stick is half submerged in water, when
light is tinted or dim, etc.)
Internal Conditions: when the observer is sick, hypnotized,
hallucinating, etc.)
People understand each other only if there is general agreement on the
paradigm cases of observational predicates. Without such agreement ‘F’ can have
no sense, and the question whether ‘F(X)’ is true or not is strictly senseless.
Therefore the fact that we understand one another and seem to
disagree about the application of aesthetic predicates implies that there are
paradigm cases of these predicates.
Experts are those who, due to personal genius, proper training, or
possession of the right instruments, have those SOC; they are standard
observers. (Both in and out of science- think X-rays, sonograms, microscope
slides. Etc.)
The theory, art movement, or school that explains which objects
are F and why it is better to take the conditions under which these objects
appear to be F as standard trains experts, who determine, in accordance with
that theory, which objects are F and which are not.
Unless aesthetic terms are given realistic interpretations they
cannot be understood or be used in language.
Aesthetic terms obey DLL (i.e. division of linguistic labor ) They
operate in standard ways with respect to belief formation and revision.): that
is how they can have meaning despite the fact that distinct observers often
diverge when they apply them by direct observation.
Instead of general uniformity in observing aesthetic properties,
there are experts who have the SOC for them. Thus despite the (considerable,
but not radical) disagreement on the application of aesthetic terms, we can
learn them and teach them to others.
3. Proofs from Scientific Realism
In Sum: Scientific realists hold that if theory T is better than
its rivals, we are justified in believing T. It follows that under the
observation conditions C that T decrees standard, things appear as they are,
and hence if, under C, X appears A, then X is A. The theory that explains the
behavior of the artist, predicts how the experts will see X, and also the
observations of nonexperts (who see X as ugly, boring, messy, etc.) is worthy
of credence.
Scientific realists hold that we are justified in believing that
the best theory is true and its theoretical entities really exist.
We may say that Atomic Physics Theory is true because it’s the
best among its competitors. If that’s
correct then we are further justified in saying “atoms” refers to real mind
independent items and that “strong force”
is a real, mind independent property of things.
If Freudian Theory were the best theory of human psychology, we
would have justification for claiming that ”ego” refers to a real mind
independent property and that “neurotic” was a real, mind independent property
of things. Since there are better
competitors to Freudian Theory, we lack that justification.
“A theory is better than another
if it explains facts that the other cannot derive from general principles and
the antecedent conditions.”
Some (good) explanations of human behavior use aesthetic
predicates:
“S dislikes the A style of the
era; that is why her works are so anti-A
“S plays X in that way to make it
more A.”
“S will not like X because it is too
A.”
“Explanations and predictions such as these are derived from
full-fledged, or mini, theories that use A (aesthetic) terms. As their place in
everyday life as well as in the academia shows, these theories are successful
in doing what a theory should do.”
“A naturalistic theory that makes no use of aesthetic predicates
can neither explain nor predict what goes on in art. (“Art behavior.” Art history in general or the actions and
choices of individual artists, critics, etc. in particular.)
“It cannot explain why art exists at all.”
Even so, the question of which aesthetic theory one should adopt
remains.
A scientific realist should not only adopt the best aesthetic
theory, but also believe that, if it says that A(X), then probably X is really
A.
The best theory, the one most worthy of acceptance, would adopt
other SOC, saying that sticks are not seen as they really are when observed in
a state of half-submergence in water.
A theory that explains why some oratorio would seem boring to a
teenager who has had no musical education, even though it is not truly boring,
is methodologically superior to a theory according to which the said oratorio
is really boring.
The first theory
1. has greater explanatory power.
2. it is simpler
3. more concise
4. it connects with other good
theories better than its rival.
The alternative view ( that the oratorio is not really aesthetically
interesting) would have to show how a monotonous drone (as the work looks to
the said teenagers) causes an elaborate hallucination of fictitious (since
unperceivable by the teenagers) properties. It needs to expose the mechanism
that causes not otherwise delirious adults to be so deluded that they seem to
hear rich emotional and spiritual features in a dull drone.
By contrast, a theory that chooses as standard those conditions under
which Bach’s work appears aesthetically good can predict both that Bach would appear
aesthetically good under SOC and would look boring under
observation conditions that do not conform to SOV: e.g. an ability to follow a
melodic line, tonal variations, nuances, and spiritual meaning.
It explains why performers do what they do and makes sense of
behavior that a rival theory describes as pathological: to make such a fuss
over dull noise! It can explain the relation of a given work to its
predecessors and ties it to historical movements and events. It uses art to
explain other cultural and sociological phenomena, and vice versa.
“One may hold that our admiration for Bach is due either to a
delusion, a hallucination, or else to a secret plot of a cabal, passing off
junk as a thing of great merit (as in Anderson’s The King’s New Clothes).
However, psychopathic behavior and the behavior of conniving crooks have
manifestations that are missing in the Bach case; these theories are therefore
weak.
Are
Aesthetic Explanations Impotent?
Objection: aesthetic properties are explanatorily impotent,
isolated, and odd.
J. L. Mackie argues that aesthetic and other value properties are
not “part of the fabric of the world,” in the sense that mass, velocity, charge
are part of it. Value predicates should be reduced to terms used in psychology
and physics.
Gilbert Harman concurs: “scientific principles can be justified
ultimately by their role in explaining observations.” Protons can be posited by
a good theory because “facts about protons can affect what you observe”; but
value properties should not be posited, for “there does not seem to be any way
in which the actual rightness or wrongness of a given situation can have any
effect on your perceptual apparatus.”
Value theory “completely irrelevant to our explanation of why the
theory in question was suggested whether the moral (and, I suppose, aesthetic)
theory judged to be true is true or not.”
1.There is no explanation of our value judgments in purely
physical and psychological terms.
Mackie and Harman might say that although no such explanation as
yet exists, future science may provide it. But how do they know this?
The supervenience of the aesthetic on the nonaesthetic does not
make the aesthetic property explanatorily redundant, for science gives no
explanation, none at all, neither in fact nor in principle, for why brain
events of kind K result in our making these specific phenomenal observations.
Why do we observe qualia? “patterns of cell spiking”
Whether we like it or not, the best explanation we have for our
having phenomenal experiences is still, as it was in the days of Aristotle,
that these are observations of properties of some entities. A Cartesian will
say that these entities are mental, not physical, but that does not change the
basic feature of the theory: intentionality. The intentional theory of
experience is not only the best we have; it is our only working theory. We
should accept, therefore, the reality of the properties posited by that theory.
The purported elimination of
sense-terms eliminates the core of science, its distinction between an
empirical observation and a mere opinion. It reduces science to a story, a
legend with no empirical content, for we lose the means to express the
difference between the two. Eliminating phenomenal terms is therefore
the end of science; the expurgated language cannot distinguish dogma, or
fairy-tale, from empirical data.
He agrees that moral theory and aesthetics are relatively isolated
from the physical sciences.
True; but so what? A theory that is successful in its field, but
only marginally interfaces with other theories, is not discarded and the said
field left unattended to until that day (which may never come) when a better
behaved theory comes along. (The (dis)unity of science)
But, …
4. Proofs from Scientific
Realism 2
Argument: If Scientific Realism is True, then Aesthetic Realism
must be true too.
Scientific realists hold that the
best theory is probably true. The best theory is one that passes all
methodological tests with flying colors: it is simple, powerful (has a wide
range) and dramatic (we prefer a theory T that has successfully predicted to a
theory T1 that has only postdicted: both explain the
data, but T is more dramatic).
These properties are aesthetic; thus theories have
aesthetic constraints, and these are their only constraints.
Theories cannot be refuted: incompatible data and prediction
failures make a theory less general and inelegant, that is, uglier, but not
false.
Thus, scientific realism comes down to this: ugly theories are
probably false.
A theory that is rich, powerful, dramatic, and simple, i.e.,
beautiful (Unity in Variety is the oldest definition of Beauty) is probably
true.
Scientific Realism requires that we have objective justification
for the preference of some scientific theories over others.
The properties that actual scientists most often to recommend one
theory over another turn out to be “aesthetic.”
If beauty (et alia) is not
a real property it can provide no objective justification for the preference of
a given theory and the preference of any theory would be unjustified. (That
would also entail the belief in the theoretical commitments of the theory is
also unjustified.)
Either Aesthetic Realism is true or we have no reason to suppose
that there are such things as electrons, protons, quarks, etc..
Once consequence of this is that aesthetic reduction is
impossible:
“We may believe that there are no aesthetic properties only if we
can establish that some theory T (the theory that says that there are no
aesthetic properties) is beautiful.”
5.
Proofs for Metaphysical Realists
Critics of scientific realism argue that methodological
excellence, that is, beauty, does not guarantee truth. The world in itself may
be ugly, so why believe an account that presents it as pretty? A beautiful
model may explain all that needs explaining, and yet be false, for the world
satisfies an uglier model. Thus the metaphysical realist thinks that beauty is
irrelevant to truth.
Non-realists such as Dummett and Putnam think that a
methodologically impeccable theory, say, one that would be accepted by ideally
rational beings, cannot be wrong.
These thinkers identify truth with justified assertabilily.
Metaphysical realists, on the other hand, insist on a distinction
between truth and justifies assertability
Given that position, can we know whether things in reality have
aesthetic properties?
Is it possible, that is, to be a metaphysical realist and a
realist in aesthetics?
Zemach: "Yes"
No description of reality can fail to include aesthetic
predicates.
"it cannot fail to be pretty or ugly, dramatic or monotonous,
dainty or sublime. "
It
is inconceivable that anything could be unamenable to aesthetic evaluation.
"If space is Einsteinian
nothing in it can be circular; if it is Newtonian nothing in it can be central.
But things can be gaudy in any manner of space. Under no circumstances is it a
category mistake to ascribe aesthetic properties to objects. "
Further phenomenal predicates can be satisfied in a world where no
perceivers exist
Argument:
Every possible world has features
Any arrangement of features
satisfies some aesthetic predicate.
Therefore
Every possible world has aesthetic
properties.
Claims we can put greater trust in aesthetic than in scientific
theories.
Inference to the best hypothesis does not guarantee truth if one
adopts a metaphysical realist notion of truth
But aesthetic theory need not rely on an inference to the best
hypothesis since there is an independent proof that our aesthetic views cannot
possibly be all wrong.
It is incoherent to maintain that we usually misapply the
aesthetic predicates.
our theoretical constraints are all aesthetic: we have no other
criteria of acceptability of hypotheses and theories.
To "refute" a theory, one must show that it is ugly (cumbersome,
narrow, devoid of dramatic power)
To deny the truthfulness of aesthetic judgements (that what we
believe to be lovely is in fact ugly) undercuts the standard but which theories
(all theories) are shown to be good or bad.
One is left with the position that even an atrociously bad theory
may not
be false
By doubting our ability to accurately distinguishing beauty
(adequate theories) from ugliness (inadequate theories) one simultaneously
doubts our ability to tell a good argument from a bad one.
Conversely, if we are to consider any theory, including the
skeptic’s and the metaphysical realist’s, we need to assume that we apply
aesthetic predicates correctly- aesthetic realism
"Any argument, including the
argument that our aesthetic judgments are wrong, that we misapply aesthetic
concepts, is worth considering only if we trust our ability to distinguish a
good argument from a bad one, that is, to apply aesthetic concepts and tell the
beautiful from the ugly. Thus our aesthetic theory cannot be coherently
conceived to be false."
Consider: Can I prove to
you –via logical argument- that you are utterly mad?
(This is similar to the stalemate that exists between the
philosopher and the mystic.)
It is pragmatically paradoxical to doubt our basic aesthetic
judgments, for if we do, we should doubt that that doubt itself is well
founded.
I. The classical expositions of
that view are in three articles in W. Elton’s influential anthology, Aesthetics
and Language (Oxford, 1954): J. A. Passmore, “The Dreariness of Aesthetics,”
Arnold Isenberg, “Critical Communication,” and Stuart Hampshire, “Logic and
Appreciation.”
2. 1 have suggested a defense of
realism in aesthetics ba.sed on the notion of
standard observation conditions for aesthetic properties in my articles “A
Stitch in Time,” Journal of Value Inquiry 1 (1967—8): 223—42 and “Taste and
Time,” Iyyun 20 (1970): 79—104 and in my books,
Analytic Aesthetics (Tel Aviv, 1970), and Aesthetics (Tel Aviv, 1976). A more recent
defense of realism in aesthetics along similar lines is given in Philip Pettit,
“The Possibility of Aesthetic Realism,” Pleasure, Preference and Value, edited
by Eva Schaper (Cambridge, 1983).
3. 1 discussed that point in
“Seeing, ‘Seeing’, and Feeling,” Review of Metaphysics 23 (1969): 3—24.
4. J. J. C. Smart, “Sensation and
Brain Processes,” in The Philosophy of Mind, edited by V. C. Chappell
(Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1962), 166.
5. Hilary Putnam, “The Meaning of
‘Meaning’,” in his Mind, Language, and Reality (Cambridge, 1975).
6. J. L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing
Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth, 1977).
7. G. Harman, The Nature of
Morality (New York, 1977), 9.
8. Ibid., 8.
9. Ibid., 7.
10. Supervenience does not
jeopardize the ontological reality of aesthetic predicates. Take the pair of
particles that feature in the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen experiment. The
properties of each particle supervene on those of the other, for it is
impossible to affect one of them without the other being affected (the famous “collapse”).
That does not mean that only one of the particles is real and the other is
“reducible to it” (whatever that means); both are real. Indeed logical
relations between real things are unusual, but phenomenal-physical relations
are unusual in any case; we cannot expect them to follow the laws of classical
mechanics.
11. See Scientific Realism and the
Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge, 1979); Matter and Consciousness (Cambridge,
1988); “The Direct Introspection of Brain States,” Journal of Philosophy 35 (1985):
8—28.
12. In “Churchland, Introspection,
and Dualism,” Philosophia, forthcoming.
13. I have argued this point in my
“Truth and Beauty,” Philosophical Forum 18 (1986):
21—39.
14. “On the Very Idea of a
Conceptual Scheme,” in D. Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation
(Oxford, 1984), 223—42, and “A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge,” in
Truth and Interpretation, edited by E. LePore
(London, 1986).
15. Suppose that a spaceship lands
here; its nonhuman crew is obviously highly intelli
gent. They learn English in a matter of days and converse with us on a variety
of topics. However when we ask them to translate some of their writings into
English they explain that they cannot do so, for theirs is a language that we
cannot understand. The reason is that while we have six senses, they have
sixty. They show us the bodily organs for these senses and explain that the
simplest word in their language denotes a combination of deter minations of at least twenty different kinds of sensation.
Further, suppose that their children take a few hundred years to learn the
simplest logical formula expressible in their language (they live for a hundred
thousand years), and hence it is reasonable that there can be no English
translation of even the simplest expression in their language. Is that
impossible? But Davidson would have us believe that our galactic friends are no
more intelligent than trees, and that they cannot have a language!
[1] Zemach, Eddy M. “Real Beauty” Midwest Studies in Philosophy Volume 16, 1991 Philosophy and the Arts Pages 249-265 https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1991.tb00242.x
[2] JJ Smart’s defines the expert in terms of "sensitive to make more distinctions." Zemach criticizes this (while agreeing that experts observe more aesthetic distinctions than laymen), by pointing out that a person who makes myriad distinctions that all others find capricious is not the most normal percipient, who sets the standard for correct attribution of properties. He is merely mad.