Theories of Art: Formalism
Clive Bell and Aesthetic Emotion
Understanding
and Appreciating Music
Abstract Art and the Value of Form
Four Puzzling Facts About “Significant Form” (whatever it is)
Several Final Objections to this View
Theories of Art: Formalism
Clive Bell, from Art
Eduard Hanslick,
from On the Beautiful in Music
Leonard B. Meyer, "On
Rehearing Music"
Malcolm Bradbury and James
McFarlane, "The Name and Nature of Modernism"
No one has yet
been able to demonstrate that the representational as such either adds or takes
away from the merit of a picture or a statue.[1]
Clement Greenberg, Art and Culture
At a certain
point we begin to be told that there is only one thing, one thing alone, to be
looked for in art. [2]
Leo Steinberg, Other Criteria: Confrontations with Twentieth‑Century Art
It is necessary, therefore,
for me to put up a preliminary hypothesis of the existence of pure and impure
works of art....
Roger Fry, "Some Questions on Esthetics"
There is no such thing as a moral or an
immoral book. Books are well written, or badly written. That is all …The only
excuse for making a useless thing is that one admires it intensely. All art is
quite useless.
Oscar Wilde, The Picture of Dorian Gray
One of the chief goals of Formalism is to establish the
autonomy of art. That is, art is not
subservient to some social, educational or moral purpose. It is not to be utilitarian, or at least, to
judge is on those term is not to engage with it as art. Art is to
be judged as art on its own terms. But if that's true what are these terms? But
then:
·
What is art?
·
How is it to be judged?
·
Why is it valuable?
Mimetic Theory: reference
to subject matter & representation (accuracy). Thus, art is subordinate to truth
and morality.
·
Art is an autonomous realm, sufficient unto
itself.
·
Subordinate to nothing.
·
Judged by its own internal standards.
"Art for art’s sake,"
Monroe Beardsley (1915-1985) explains this slogan as
"the recognition of a work of art as an
object in its own right, intelligible and valuable as such, with intrinsic
properties, independent of its relations to other things and to its creator and
perceiver."
Autonomy = freedom
from having to conform to external rules or community standards.
Hegel claimed that “Freedom craves to be absolute.”
Formalism contends that “Artistic Value” and
significance is independent of representational qualities, moral values, (and perhaps
even any pleasure an audience derives from the work).
As William Gass claims, "goodness knows nothing of
beauty."
The 20th Century Formalist Roger Fry claimed
that
"All art depends upon cutting off the
practical responses to sensations of ordinary life, thereby setting free a pure
and, as it were, disembodied functioning of the spirit."
Formalism can be seen as a development out of one of
eighteenth‑century aesthetic theories. For instance, in The Critique of Judgment (1790),
Immanuel Kant asserts that aesthetic judgments, represented paradigmatically by
judgments of beauty, are logically independent of judgments of morality,
utility, and truth. For Kant, the pure
aesthetic judgment is one which he calls "non-conceptual," by which
he means that it is not made by
reference to any concepts of what the object being judged ought to be like. The
Aesthetic Response is an impersonal response.
Thus formalists like Fry claim that art is an "expression of the
imaginative life" with the absence of responsive action.
·
No moral responsibility
·
Life freed from the necessities of actual
existence.
This theory of art grants to art a near absolute freedom and autonomy
Two aspects to the idea that art is autonomous.
1.
Free from external considerations (relation
to things outside)
2.
Artworks must have an internal subject
matter that is sufficient unto itself (leads to the concept of “form”- the “perceptually
given”).
Form (Look
over notes on Elements and Principles of Visual Art
1.
Elements of Form: What individual members of
a given class of objects have in common.
(Platonic Universal) Formal properties of art must be universal
properties.
2.
Principles of Form: These are repeatable
principles which organize the elements of artworks, where, while each work has
its own unique form, it can share formal properties with other artworks (i.e.
iambic pentameter, visual symmetry, musical key or time signature).
Two ways of understanding "Form"
1.
In contrast to content. (The story of
Oedipus as the “content” but note that this same content can be presented in different
art forms (e.g. of a tragedy, a ballet, a movie).
But... it is difficult to maintain that content is independent of
form. The formal differences between
poetry and prose seem to change the kind of message (content) it can convey. One thinks for instance of the slogan. “The
medium is the Message.”[3]
Note the E. E. Cumming’s poem:
"anyone lived in a pretty how town":
anyone lived in a pretty how town
(with up so floating many bells down)
spring summer autumn winter
he sang his didn't he danced his did
2.
The organization of the "elements" of a work.
Note: Key to critical appreciation of a work of Art will be
determining what precisely are the Formal Elements and Formal
Principles of that work/medium. See Elements and Principles of Visual Art
Beardsley:
A formal description and this formal
critical examination of an object of art with in volve
1.
“Element Statements:” "those statements
that describe the local qualities of elements, and the regional qualities of
complexes, within a visual design or a musical composition,
2.
“Principle Statements” “those statements
that describe internal relations among the elements and among the complexes
within the object. These latter statements we may call ‘form‑statements’.
Elements and Principles of Art
http://www.slideshare.net/kpikuet/elements-and-principles-of-art-presentation?related=1
Formal Analysis of
Da Vinci’s “Last Supper”
http://www.slideshare.net/nichsara/formal-analysis-tutorial-2-d
“Everything Set to Medium”
http://stapletonkearns.blogspot.com/2009_07_01_archive.html
Form is any
relation between elements that figures in our appreciation of the work.
But... what level of analysis is correct to look for with
respect to the distinction between form and the elements (or constituents) of
the work? Formal properties can occur at
various levels as well. (Sound and visual aspect of poetry, complex aspect of
meanings.)
·
The relations of the sounds
·
The visual structure of the words on the
page
·
Patterns and structures of meaning,
considering not only the relation of words to each other but also relations
among larger structures, such as verses and stanzas.
Beardsley: "the point of view he chooses, or the
manner of transition from scene to scene, or the proportion of description to
dialogue."
Broad definition of form:
Understand (wrt literature,
plays, films, etc.) "form" in the arts as the contrast to the matter
or elements that the work organizes. This definition of form applies to every
type of artwork and probably best captures what formalism is all about.
Develops as a stand-alone theory of art in the early
twentieth century.
·
However, proper form had been a prominent
concern since the days of Ancient Greece.
·
Plato and Aristotle each talked about the
importance of from with respect to beauty (Harmony and “Organic Unity”)
·
Pythagoras had demonstrated the musical
harmonies correspond to geometric proportions:
1:2 (octave), 2:3 (harmonic fifth), and 3:4 (harmonic fourth).
EX: Polykleitos (5th century BC) ' "Kanon"
This ancient Greek sculptor of great renown dictated
that a statue should be composed of clearly definable parts related to one
another through a system of ideal mathematical proportions.
Doryphoros (Canon)After Polykleitos of Argos (Greek, ca.
480/475–415 BCE)
http://www.learner.org/courses/globalart/work/138/index.html
|
|
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=zojMBDSiNIU
Nevertheless, historically formal proportionality and
elements of “design” were regarded as subservient to mimetic goals of the work and
to the beauty of what is represented. In
contrast we are now being asked to attend to the purely formal beauty, or
beauty of form even if it has no representational goals. (EX: Baroque music). Denis Arnold remarks "these abstract
works of Bach's old age [such as the Art of Fugue] have puzzled musicians and
scholars." "Abstract
Works" were puzzling because they neither had a representational function
nor expressive. Before the early 20th
Century, no doctrine of the arts had been put forth which locates the very
nature and meaning of artworks in form. Formalism authorized artists to create
purely formal, nonrepresentational artworks (first in music, then in visual
arts and literature) whose sole value was to be derived in the aesthetic
contemplation of the formal arrangement of their elements.
On this view, a landscape was merely an “excuse” to
consider pure formal beauty.
Two
Formalist Theories:
1. Formalism
(proper)
2. Media
Formalism (we’ll deal with this
later)
We must distinguish between tow related ideas: "Formalism"
and “Modernism." The distinction is
blurry but essentially, "Formalism"
refers to a theory of art which could/should be applied to all works of art
irrespective of the actual historical situatedness of the work. It does not refer to a (historical) trend in
recent art. "Modernism," by contrast, is a vague, and unfortunately an
ambiguous term. We use the term to
locate historically a distinct stylistic, a phase of art history which is
ceasing or has ceased or sometimes to sum up a permanent modernizing state of
affairs.
Richard Hertz regards historical art movement of modernism
as the valuing of the "ahistorical, scientific, self‑referential,
reductionistic" and as being committed to "exclusivity, purity and
removal from societal and cultural concerns" from art.
Alternatively, others have suggested that Modernism
is/was
"the movement towards sophistication and mannerism, towards
introversion, technical display, internal self‑scepticism,
has often been taken as a common base for a definition of Modernism."
Note: "Post‑
modernism" is at least as obscure as "modernism" is obscure.
Basic distinction between Modernism and Formalism is
that Modernism (like Abstract Expressionism) is a historical movement, whereas
Formalism, is a philosophy of art in general.
The latter is a theory of art which is thought to apply to all art,
including art of the past.
In his 1914 book Art[4],
Clive Bell proposed we understand Art as “Significant Form”
Bell argues that all art must have something in common.
For either all works of visual art have some
common quality, or when we speak of “works of art” we gibber. Everyone speaks
of “art,” making a mental classification by which he distinguishes the class
“works of art” from all other classes. What is the justification of this
classification? What is the quality common and peculiar to all members of this
class? Whatever it be, no doubt it is often found in company with other
qualities; but they are adventitious — it is essential. There must be some one quality without which a work of art cannot exist;
possessing which, in the least degree, no work is altogether worthless.[5]
Thus the hunt it on for that which all and only Works of
Art have in common, in virtue of which they are Works of Art. Classification is only justified if there is some essential quality that all artworks
share that we refer to when we use the term "art."
For the Formalist, formal relations are not merely
considered important in an artwork, but rather the formal properties of a work
are primary, and other concerns are secondary, wholly irrelevant or even a detraction.
"The starting point for all systems of aesthetics must be the
personal experience of a peculiar emotion. The objects that provoke this
emotion we call works of art."
Bell draws a distinction between two types of emotions
elicited by artworks:
·
"Aesthetic Emotion"
·
"Emotions of life"
"A painter too feeble to
create forms that provoke more than a little aesthetic emotion will try to eke
that little out by suggesting the emotions of life. To evoke the emotions of
life he must use representation. Thus a man will paint an execution, and
fearing to miss with his first barrel of significant form, will try to hit with
his second by raising an emotion of fear or pity."
"A good work of visual art carries a
person who is capable of appreciating it out of life into ecstasy: to use art
as a means to the emotions of life is to use a telescope of reading the news."
"We are all familiar with pictures that
interest us and excite our admiration, but do not move us as works of art. To
this class belongs what I call 'Descriptive
Painting' that is, painting in which forms are used not as objects of
emotion, but as a means suggesting emotion or conveying information."
With respect to music Bell claims that he does at times
"appreciate music as pure musical form,
as sounds combined according to the laws of a mysterious necessity, as pure art
with a tremendous significance of its own and no relation whatever to the significance
of life.”
It is this aesthetic emotion toward the object and thus
causes us to label it "art."
What is it that provokes the unique aesthetic
emotion? Only the formal properties
could do the trick.
What Bell calls “Significant Form.”
“Formal properties and nothing else are what makes
artifacts of the past art.”
Argues that what he calls "significant form" is the defining
quality of art .
·
Each artwork provokes its own particular
emotion, but each particular emotion is of this special type.
·
Bell claims that it is just this common
quality which causes the aesthetic emotion by which we know and experience
objects as works of art.
What is this "Something?" -- "Significant Form"
Bell regards his proposal as an empirical hypothesis based on, and intended to account for,
observations (our collective experience of artworks). Not unlike the 18th and 19th
century aestheticians, he is claiming that there is a unique set of experiences
and that these can only be explained by an appeal to objective formal
properties.
I shall not, however, be under the delusion
that I am rounding off my theory of aesthetics. For a discussion of aesthetics,
it need be agreed only that forms arranged and combined according to certain
unknown and mysterious laws do move us in a particular way, and that it is the
business of an artist so to combine and arrange them that they shall move us.
These moving combinations and arrangements I have called, for the sake of
convenience and for a reason that will appear later, “Significant Form.”
This peculiar emotion cannot be explained by
“Association of Ideas” theories because
1. The Aesthetic Emotion is not among the “Emotions of
Life”
Not everyone can feel this emotion, at least fully. And it cannot be explained.
“… It means that his aesthetic emotions are
weak or, at any rate, imperfect. Before a work of art people who feel little or
no emotion for pure form find themselves at a loss. They are deaf men at a
concert. They know that they are in the presence of something great, but they
lack the power of apprehending it. They know that they ought to feel for it a
tremendous emotion, but it happens that the particular kind of emotion it can
raise is one that they can feel hardly or not at all.”
2. Emotional associations cannot explain the enduring
admiration we pay to great works of art across the centuries.
Emotional associations are dependent on specific
cultural contexts, as well as the specific meanings of subject matter, and thus
will be lost on observers from other times and cultures. They cannot explain the enduring admiration
great works of art receive. Indeed, Bell
suggests, in a manner similar to Hutchinson, that the association of ideas can
in fact distract us from what it of real significance in an artwork. For Bell, it is better that observers not
understand artworks; this makes their responses purer.
“Let no one imagine that representation is
bad in itself; a realistic form may be as significant, in its place as part of
the design, as an abstract. But if a representative form has value, it is as
form, not as representation. The representative element in a work of art may or
may not be harmful; always it is irrelevant. For, to appreciate a work of art
we need bring with us nothing from life, no knowledge of its ideas and affairs,
no familiarity with its emotions. Art transports us from the world of man’s
activity to a world of aesthetic exaltation. For a moment we are shut off from
human interests; our anticipations and memories are arrested; we are lifted
above the stream of life.”
3. Only Formal Properties can explain why we are moved
aesthetically.
Thus Bell Formalism is, allegedly, able to explain
otherwise unexplainable facts (great art's appeal to viewers of widely
divergent cultures and times). It is
form to which viewers are responding. (Seems initially plausible).
1. What is meant by "Significant Form?"
·
Are we to contrast this with “insignificant”
formF.
·
Which formal relations among which formal
elements are "significant," and why?
Bell's unhelpful answer: Something is significant form
if and only if it provokes aesthetic emotion.
·
Significant form is supposed to explain what
provokes our aesthetic emotions, but it is defined in terms of aesthetic
emotion. (Significant Form it that which causes that which only significant
form can cause.)
·
Subjectively fixing the causes prevents him
from given any objective characterization of which combinations of elements these are.
·
Could the stronger claim also be true; that
significant form is nothing but such color arrangements in all pictures?
(Connected to Bell's claim that we need apply no knowledge except that of three‑dimensional
space).
2. Is it true that "to appreciate a work of art we
need bring with us nothing but a sense of form and color and a knowledge of
three‑dimensional space? “
Roger Fry claims that attempting to explain the concept
of significant form adequately would take one to "the depths of
mysticism."
Formalism in music argues against the customary emphasis
in music on emotions.
Eduard Hanslick 1825-1904),
the most influential formalist theorist of music, insists that his theory of
music derives from a purely objective approach. His argument depends on the
conceptual connections between autonomy, objectivity, and form. Hanslick’s 1854 work On the Musically Beautiful argues
for a Formalist conception of aesthetic merit in music not unlike Bell’s.
http://www.cengage.com/music/book_content/049557273X_wrightSimms/assets/ITOW/7273X_58_ITOW.pdf
Hanslick rejects two ideas:
a. that the point of music, its meaning, is
ultimately to be understood in terms of emotional effects.
b. that the meaning of music is to be
understood in terms of its alleged ability to represent emotional states.
He attempts to develop an objective musical aesthetics
that deals with music in its own terms, that is, as an autonomous phenomenon.
Emotional responses to music come and go. (e.g. Stravinsky's
Rite of Spring) Our emotional
estimate of a piece of music varies too much, from context to context and
person to person, to be a valid basis for detecting and analyzing what is
beautiful in music. Thus he agrees with
Bell and other formalists that aspects to music do not possess sufficient attributes
of “inevitable-ness, exclusive‑ness and uniformity...” Pure instrumental music, commonly called
"absolute music" in music theory, is championed by Hanslick and other nineteenth‑ and twentieth‑century
theorists as the highest form of music.
"In the pure act of
listening we enjoy the music alone and do not think of importing into it any
extraneous matter. But the tendency to allow our feelings to be aroused implies
something extraneous to the music.” (not in whatever emotions or associations
we may connect to the music.)
Hanslick thinks the imagination (an active organ of the mind) performs
the function of constructing experience to enable us to mentally grasp external
perceptual objects. To hear sounds as music is not to feel emotions or to
think of distant scenes, but to hear the sounds with our imagination, which can
represent the sounds as pure music. We contemplates
it with intelligence. So here he distinguishes
direct effect on imagination from indirect effect on emotions.
The only valid analysis of the beauty of music must
focus on the music itself, on what is in the music, not on the music's variable
and indirect effects. Like Bell and
other Formalists, Hanslick's argument thus shows that
a demand for complete autonomy for artworks (and I would argue coupled with a
demand for objectivity, necessity and universality) implies a rejection of
mimetic theories and expression theories of art in favor of the formal
'relation of elements within the artwork.
What remains after we put aside the emotional and
representational content is the musical content, the musical properties of sounds.
“The primordial element of music is euphony,
and rhythm is its soul. . . . The crude material which the composer has to
fashion ... is the entire scale of musical notes and their inherent
adaptability to an endless variety of melodies, harmonies, and rhythms. Melody
... is preeminently the source of musical beauty."
Note:
not only is he identifying the elements of music so as better to discern
musical formal properties, but also tacitly recommending a research project for
each artistic medium, i.e. to discover its own essential nature (Minimalism-
media formalism)
An “intellectual principle” implied, Hanslick
argues since it "as essential, for we would not apply the term
"beautiful" to anything wanting in intellectual beauty; and in
tracing the essential nature of beauty to a morphological source, we wish it to
be understood that the intellectual element is most intimately connected with
the sonorific forms, (Note the Pythagorean Theory of Beauty is here
quite explicit.)
beauty, is a temporal phenomenon
Two Formal
Concepts of Understanding and Appreciating Music
"On
Rehearing Music," Leonard Meyer distinguishes two different
formal concepts as to what it means to “Understand and Appreciate” music:
1. The
Non-temporal Approach: a musical event "must be complete, or virtually
so, before its formal design can be comprehended";
Such thinkers maintain that music is to be contemplated
as a completed whole structure.
2. The
Kinetic‑syntactic Approach: music "is a dynamic process.
(Understanding and enjoyment depend upon the perception of and response to
attributes such as tension and repose.... music is seen as a developing
process")
The primary example of music to be experienced in this
way is Western music from 1600‑1900, which is characterized by a kind of
harmonic development that requires modulation between keys and resolution of
harmonic tensions. This harmonic development, in conjunction with manipulation
of thematic material, gives such music a prospective and dramatic air, as Meyer
notes, a sense that the music is “always progressing forward.”
Kinetic position:
"The
significance of a musical event be it a tone, a motive, a phrase, or a section
lies in the fact that it leads a practiced listener to expect, consciously or
unconsciously, the arrival of a subsequent event or one of a number of
alternative subsequent events."
The degree of the probability of subsequent
events contributes to the sense of significance or meaning we feel when
the actual musical events happen. If a piece of music is very predictable (for
example, "Twinkle, Twinkle, Little Star"), it has little meaning; if,
however, our expectations are much more complex and the fulfillment is much
less probable (as in a Beethoven symphony), then the music has much more
significance, because the musical notes are surprising.
This analysis of music is clearly formalist. For Meyer, meaning
depends on syntactic or structural complexity, which in turn is
connected to enjoyment. He seems to understand this enjoyment as a
psychological process to be explained some day by a more advanced cognitive
science.
For Meyer value is the enjoyment it gives us.
Hanslick grounds his account on the more traditional concepts of
beauty as well as what pleases us. Hints
that form furnishes music with even more profound values.
Two Chief Formalist Points:
·
negative: formalists
claim that art is not about what it might appear to be about rather, it is
about form.
·
positive: form is to
be understood so that form is important for given reasons.
What is form?
What is the value of form?
What is the value of art if formalist theories of art
are correct?
Calls for a positive account of form and its value.
Not widely accepted account of the positive value of
form, and this is one of the weaknesses of formalism as a philosophy of art.
Further... Why do we value Significant Form?
A formalist would claim that
abstract images are merely purified versions of the formal values found in
representational art.
Clive Bell is sure that form is
the thrilling aspect of art and what makes something truly art. But he is less sure just why form is
important, less sure what the meaning of form is. He does not wish to base formalism on any
foundation as shallow as mere pleasure or enjoyment.
His metaphysical hypothesis: the
ecstasy explained in terms of
a. the communication of emotion between artist and viewer.;
viewers are moved not because the work is beautiful, but because they feel the
emotion that the artist feels.
b. The emotion that the artist feels is for the pure form of
reality.
c. the emotion is for things seen not as means but “ends in
themselves.”
Bell suggests that the significance of the work of art
is that it is inspired by the artist’s a vision of "Reality." We are moved by certain combinations of lines
and colors because the artist has used these to express an emotion felt for
ultimate reality, things in themselves, divorced from all associations. Cezanne, he claimed, discovered how to paint the
essence of things, exemplifying Bell's metaphysical/epistemological
hypothesis about the value of
form.
But this explanation seems to require that we look at
Cezanne's landscapes as about landscape, not just lines and patches of
color. To create a painting that captures
the essential form of something would seem to be quite a deep artistic
achievement, and this would explain the felt "significance" of the
forms, but is inconsistent with Bell's more radical claim that
"significant form" can be entirely separated from what the artwork
represents.
Problem: Bell cannot generalize the explanation that he gives in Cezanne's
case (that Cezanne portrays the essence of a landscape for forms that do not
derive from observation).
Hanslick,
too, is eager to link the beautiful in music with themes more profound than
pleasure (communication of emotion between artist and audience), with our
realization that the sounds which stimulate our imaginations are produced by
the composer's imagination.
The difference between a
kaleidoscope and music, he claims, is
"that
the musical kaleidoscope is the direct product of a creative mind, whereas the
optic one is but a cleverly constructed mechanical toy"
Note: This distinction is very much in jeopardy give “music writing
programs.”
Note as well: A
it is a clever mind that stands behind the any clever toy.
One wonders what he would say about AI generated music or art in general.
In Hanslick's
view, the composer is inspired by the structures of musical reality and the free
play of the imagination. He is
saying both that absolute music has value and also that listening to music in
this special way, that is, contemplating it, is valuable. When these two, the
proper object and the proper way of listening, come together, the result is a
refined form of experience and an exercise of our highest imaginative and
intellectual faculties.
Four puzzling facts about significant form (whatever it is):
1. SF is both the identity criterion for art
and the evaluative criterion for art.
Therefore, some art‑like artifacts lack significant form, even
though they surely have many formal properties.
But for Bell there could never be Bad art; only genuine art (w/ SF) and
non-art (w/o SF)
2. We would normally maintain that some
genuine artworks are better than others (as works of art). But for Bell, having SF does not admit of
degrees; therefore all genuine art is equal in value.
3. Bell, at places, seems to allow that
natural object can provoke “aesthetic emotion” and, if so, must possess
significant form. But either that means
that the creation of SF can be accidental, or it means that some mind is
responsible for the SF to be found in nature (or perhaps we cannot actually
have an aesthetic emotion response to natural objects. All of these options seem problematic.
4. To appreciate a work's significant form
we do not need any knowledge of what the work represents according to Bell. He
wants to contrast formal appreciation of works of art with awareness of their
representational content. However, some
formal qualities cannot be accessed until one knows the representational
content. (i.e. would not even be able to
pick out the special relations of the objects being depicted if we did not know
what
was being represented.
It seems absurd to say the aesthetic power
of the painting is due exclusively to non-representational elements. Part of the effect simulated
distance in a picture might be explained colors and perspective. But another
reason why we might focus the spatial quality could be the nature of the events
and the significance of what is being depicted.
1. Sometimes at least, the visual relations that seem
significant gain their significance because of the viewer's understanding the
things being represented.
2. Without knowledge of the things represented, the view
cannot perceive certain visual relations.
Greatest strength: universal applicability
to both abstract and expressive art, to contemporary as well as ancient art,
and to every culture of art, which, at least in the case of music, seem in part
supported by Cognitive Science.
Great weakness: perhaps
the most esoteric account of the value of art.
Crucial question: Why do we
demand/expect our visual art be representational, but not our music?
Francis Picabia “The laws
appreciating Non-representational visual art have as yet been hardly
formulated, but they will become gradually more defined.”
Facilitated an easy formalist reading of abstract art,
but not everyone is happy with Formalism, even as an account of Abstract Visual
Art:
e.g. Maurice Tuchman:
Los Angeles County Museum of Art 1986 organized
"The Spiritual in Art: Abstract Painting 1890‑1985.
“Abstract art remains misunderstood never an outright dismissal of
meaning draws upon deeper levels of meaning genesis and development of abstract
art were inextricably tied to spiritual ideas to express spiritual, Utopian, or
metaphysical ideas that cannot be expressed in traditional pictorial terms.”
This suggests that Tuchman holds something like a
mimetic theory of visual art that abstract art has meaning if and only if it
represents some ideas. Further she seems
to be implying that the major difference between traditional representational
art and abstract art would involve the subject matter.
·
Traditional art: natural world
·
Abstract art: spiritual world (abstract art
lacking such esoteric subject matter would be meaningless).
Tuchman criticizes formalist interpretations of the
history of abstract art; "aesthetic interpretations" have made the
art meaningless.
What is important in painting, for Georgia O'Keeffe, is
not representation per se but getting at the emotional essence of form:
"I had to create an equivalent for what I felt about what I
was looking at, not copy it."
Modrian:
"Hence as matter becomes redundant, the representation of
matter becomes redundant. We arrive at the representation of other things such
as the laws which hold matter together. These are the great generalities, which
do not change."
Newman rejected what he called the
objective approach to painting:
"The present feeling seems to be that the artist is concerned
with form, color and spatial arrangement. This objective approach to art
reduces it to a kind of ornament."
Instead, Newman held that the
painter was concerned
"with the penetration into the world mystery. His imagination
is therefore attempting to dig into metaphysical secrets....”
Donald Kuspit
notes:
"For Reinhardt the square, cruciform, unified absolutely
clean mandala shape he utilized in his famous 'black,' or negative paintings
serves the same purpose as Rothko's 'disembodied chromatic sensations,' namely
to preserve the spiritual atmosphere."
Reinhardt "a long tradition
of negative theology in which the essence of religion, and in my case the
essence of art, is protected ... from being pinned down or vulgarized or
exploited."
Bruce Nauman's Window or Wall Sign (1967), which says
in neon words: "The true artist helps the world by revealing mystic
truths.” The lack of visual illusion, the use of light as a medium, the use of
geometric form (the spiral recalling Duchamp's fascination with spirals in his
art), the self‑referential nature of its message, all work to give this
piece a mysterious sense of exemplifying
what it asserts.
It is now widely acknowledged that Cubist works do
have content, that they are about something.
However, Formalists might counter that this position
falls into the old idea that an artwork has meaning if and only if it has
content.
Several Final Objections to this View:
a. If we were to maintain this position, we
would have to say that abstract artists who reject spiritualism produce
paintings that are literally meaningless and have no content. Why say this
about paintings, but not about instrumental music?
b. Tuchman's position also places a
disproportionate weight on artists' intentions and even on their amateur interests,
for example, theosophy and so‑called sacred geometry. ("This is
guilty of the “intentional fallacy" i.e. ascribing an interpretation to a work based on properties
of the artist.)
c. No one has ever proposed that there are
no ideas behind abstract artworks and that such artworks are literally without
meaning and point. Formalists insist that the meaning or content is contained
within the formal properties, or at any rate that the viewer can understand the
meaning of the work without attributing referents to the images in the work.
d. Two obvious traditional answers to the
question of what meaning abstract works have.
i. attribution of beauty
ii. expressions of emotional states and
attitudes
[1]
Greenberg, Clement Art and
Culture Beacon Press Book, 1961 p133
[2] Steinberg,
Leo: Other Criteria: Confrontations with
Twentieth‑Century Art, University of
Chicago Press, 2007 p60
[3]
"The
medium is the message" is a phrase coined by the Canadian communication
theorist Marshall McLuhan and the name of the first chapter in his Understanding
Media: The Extensions of Man, published in 1964.[2][3] McLuhan proposes
that a communication medium itself, not the messages it carries, should be the
primary focus of study. He showed that
artifacts such as media affect any society by their characteristics, or
content.[4]
[4] Clive Bell, Art (London: Chatto & Windus, 1914).
[5] Bell, Clive Art (London: Chatto & Windus, 1914) p5.