The
Beauty Bias:
St. Augustine (A.D. 354 430)
On Christian
Doctrine[11]
On Christian Doctrine
I
Two things necessary to the treatment of the Scriptures
1. A way of discovering those things which are to be understood
2. A way of teaching what we have learned.
Discovery:
Augustine notes that all things of value issue from the source of values –not the Form of the Good in this case, but rather “God.”
On Christian Doctrine
II
Makes the distinction between signs and things.
On Christian Doctrine
III
Distinguishes among:
If we enjoy (and cling to with love) those things which should be used, our course (to blessedness) will be impeded and sometimes deflected.
“shackled by an inferior love”
On Christian Doctrine
IV
“But if the amenities of the journey and the motion of the vehicles itself delighted us, and we were led to enjoy those things which we should use, we should not wish to end our journey quickly, and, entangled in a perverse sweetness, we should he alienated from our country, whose sweetness would make us, blessed.”
Mortal life must not become “wandering from God”
On Christian Doctrine
V
The (only) things which are to be (genuinely) enjoyed are the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit, a single Trinity, (a certain supreme thing common to all who enjoy it)
On Christian Doctrine
VI
“I feel that I have done nothing but wish to speak”
This is the ineffable nature of the Divine.
But even calling God ineffable is problematic, as Augustine points out, because you are still “effing.”
“This contradiction is to be passed over in silence rather than re solved verbally.”
On Christian Doctrine
XXXV
The end of the Law and of all the sacred Scriptures is the love of a Being which is to be enjoyed.
(one might add, of all things that are to be used- Art/Beauty)
These next three I put in just because I thought they show a more ecumenical side to Augustine.
On Christian Doctrine
XXXVI
“Whoever, therefore, thinks that he understands the divine Scriptures or any part of them so that it does not build the double love of God and of our neighbor does not understand it at all.”
“Whoever finds a lesson there useful to the building of charity, even though he has not said what the author may be shown to have intended in that place, has not been deceived, nor is he lying in any way.”
On Christian Doctrine
XXXVI
“However, as I began to explain, if he is deceived in an interpretation which builds up charity, which is the end of the commandments, he is deceived in the same way as a man who leaves a road by mistake but passes through a field to the same place toward which the road itself leads. But he is to be corrected and shown that it is more useful not to leave the road, lest the habit of deviating force him to take a crossroad or a perverse way.”
On Christian Doctrine
XXX
“Indeed, if faith staggers, charity itself languishes. And if anyone should fall from faith, it follows that he falls also from charity, for a man cannot love that which he does not believe to exist. On the other hand, a man who both believes and loves, by doing well and by obeying the rules of good customs, may bring it about that he may hope to arrive at that which he loves. Thus there are these three things for which all knowledge and prophecy struggle: faith, hope, and charity.”
On Christian Doctrine XXXVIII
“Between temporal and eternal things there is this difference: a temporal thing is loved more before we have it, and it begins to grow worthless when we gain it, for it does not satisfy the soul, whose true and certain rest is eternity; but the eternal is more ardently loved when it is acquired than when it is merely desired.”[12]
Boethius b 480; died at
The Consolation of Philosophy
“When she saw that the Muses of poetry were present by my couch giving words to my lamenting, she was stirred a while; her eyes flashed fiercely as she said: “Who has suffered these seducing mummers to approach this sick man? Never have they nursed his sorrowings with any remedies, but rather fostered them with poisonous sweets. These are they who stifle the fruit-bearing harvest of reason with the barren briars of the passions; they do not free the minds of men from disease but accustom them thereto.
“I would think it less grievous if your allurements drew away from me some common man like those of the vulgar herd, seeing that in such a one my labors would be harmed not at all. But this man has been nurtured in the lore of Eleatics and Academics. Away with you, sirens, seductive even to perdition, and leave him to my Muses to be cared for and healed!”
We see what will become an institutional censoring, very similar to what Plato prescribed in the Republic, of Art and all things “beautiful” should the fall short of the “test” of true beauty.
(Also inherited is Plato suspicion of Theatre as Deliberate Deception.)
St. Thomas Aquinas
(A.D. 1225 1274)
St. Thomas Aquinas’ philosophy expresses this empirical mindset.
Aquinas's Conception of Beauty
a) "that which pleases when seen.'
b)"the beautiful is that which calms the desire, by being seen or known."
Thus related to desire.
Suggests three (objective) conditions:
1. perfection or unimpairedness
2. proportion or harmony
3. brightness or clarity
Suggest a (subjective) condition as well:
He combines both objective and subjective aspects.
But note that he combines both objective and subjective aspects. While the conditions of beauty are objective features, the idea of pleasing is a subjective element. (Being pleased is a property of a subject) This represents a significant step away from the objective Platonic conception of beauty toward a subjective conception.
Note further that “calming the desires” is an objectively verifiable effect of subjective experience.
Stresses the cognitive (knowing) aspect of the experience of beauty.
According to Aquinas, in the experience of beauty, the mind grasps a Form that is embodied in the object of the experience. Mind grasps or abstracts the form that causes an object to be what it is. Thus the mind gains knowledge though the experience of beauty. (He is not Locke.)
But the grasping of a Form is not the only thing involved in the cognition of beauty.
This suggests that there may be no single Form or property of beauty that it is common to all beautiful things the possession of which makes them beautiful. Therefore, contra Plato, the object of such a cognitive experience is NOT the Form of Beauty.
Marsillio Ficino (1433-1499)
For Ficino the visual arts were especially important. Their function was to remind the soul of its origin in the divine world by creating, through art, resemblances to that world. Ficino's insistence on the importance of this with respect to painting has been credited with raising the status of the painter in Florentine society to that nearer the poet (rather than that of the carpenter, where it had been previously).
Plato asserted that in all things there is one truth, that is the light of the One itself, the light of Deity, which is poured into all minds and forms, presenting the forms to the minds and joining the minds to the forms. Whoever wishes to profess the study of Plato should therefore honour the one truth, which is the single ray of the one Deity.
This ray passes through angels, souls, the heavens and other bodies ... its splendour shines in every individual thing according to its nature and is called grace and beauty; and where it shines more clearly, it especially attracts the man who is watching, stimulates him who thinks, and catches and possesses him who draws near to it.
This ray compels him to revere its splendour more than all else, as if it were a divine spirit, and, once his former nature has been cast aside, to strive for nothing else but to become this splendour.
In the Platonic Theology he describes the first impulse in the creation of a painting.
He writes:
'The whole field appeared in a single moment to Apelles and aroused in him the desire to paint.‘[13]
(Note the echo of Plato’s assertion that artistic creativity comes as a sort of “Divine Madness” and not an acquired, rational, skill.)
Sandro Botticelli and Renaissance Florence
“The morality of art is in its very beauty.”
-Gustave Flaubert to Louis BonEnfant
Sandro Botticelli (c. 1445 – 1510) works embody the spirit of the Renaissance. By this point in Western history, traditional Medieval Christianity and its renunciation of the worldly (pleasures, interests, concerns) had lost much of its appeal, perhaps due in part to the disappointment of the 1st millennium and later the Crusades. The Ancient pagan ideals of beauty and “the good life” began to reassert themselves. Consider Primavera; this is a thoroughly Pagan picture, an exuberant revival of embodied natural forces in an era of total control by the Church. The style is reminiscent classical styles of art, similar is style to roman frescos.
Girolamo Savonarola
Calumny (http://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/8/85/Sandro_Botticelli_021.jpg)
The Spell of Plato
Even with
Even into contemporary times we see those who suppose “beauty” is a window to a different “higher” realm of reality.
[1] Thorndike, E.L. (1920). A constant error in physical ratings. Journal of Applied Psychology, 4, 25-29. http://en.citizendium.org/wiki/Halo-effect
[2] See also “Why Attractive Candidates Win” http://www.nytimes.com/2013/11/03/opinion/sunday/health-beauty-and-the-ballot.html?_r=0’
[3] This is the title of a book by Deborah Rhode in which she argues no only that there discrimination based on appearance, but that it rises to the level of civil rights violation and legal steps should be taken to redress it.
[4] “Sexually Selective Cognition: Beauty Captures the Mind of the Beholder” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology Copyright 2003 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 2003, Vol. 85, No. 6, 1107–1120 0022-3514/03/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/0022-3514.85.6.1107
http://www.psy.fsu.edu/faculty/maner/sexually%20selective%20cognition.pdf
[5] “Facial Diversity and Infant Preferences for Attractive Faces” Judith H. Langlois, Jean M. Ritter, Lori A. Roggman, and Lesley S. Vaughn. Developmental Psychology 1991, Vol. 27 No 1 79-84
http://www.psy.cmu.edu/~siegler/35langlois91.pdf
[6] Survival of the Prettiest: The Science of Beauty, Nancy Etcoff. New York: Doubleday 1999
[7] This raises a recurring problem for Plato’s general axiology. It is counter intuitive to say that the reason I love this painting has nothing to do with this particular painting per se, but only its connection with “general beauty.” We see this same sort of claim made about people, etc. We don’t love Socrates, but only the form of goodness which happens to be shining through him. There is nothing particular to Socrates which causes, explains or justifies our love for him.
[8] Aristotle formally introduces the concept of “organic unity” in which each part contribute to the good of the whole specifically to talk about literature. But the concepts can be more broadly applied as a general organizing formal principle of visual art and music as well.
[9] Introduction to Aesthetics: An Analytic Approach, by George Dickie. Oxford University Press 1997 P8
[10] Which no doubt keeps him up at night.
[12] As we shall see, Aquinas defines beauty as that which calms the desire by being seen or known.
[13] Apelles of Kos (/əˈpɛliːz/; Greek: Ἀπελλῆς; fl. 4th century BC) was a renowned painter of ancient Greece. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Apelles#mediaviewer/File:Battle_of_Issus.jpg