Fallacies of Relevance (Red Herrings)

 

Formal and Informal Fallacies

Specific Fallacies:

1)      Argumentum ad Hominem

·         ad hominem tu quoque. (to the person- and you also)

·         ad hominem Abusive

·         ad hominem Circumstantial

·         Related ad hominem Fallacies

2)      Straw Man Fallacy

3)      False Dilemma

·         Related False Dilemma Fallacies

4)      Misplacing the Burden of Proof

5)      Begging the Questions

6)      Appeals to Emotion Fallacies

7)      Irrelevant Conclusion

 

Formal and Informal Fallacies

 

A fallacy is a “mistake in reasoning.”  Specifically, it's believing that you have been given warrant to accept the claim or to dismiss a claim when in fact you have not.  There are all kinds of different fallacies. 

 

1)      There a formal fallacies.  Here the mistake is taking a formally invalid argument as providing warrant for its conclusions when in fact the collection of premises is irrelevant to the conclusion.  These turn upon mistakes on formal logical structures.

 

E.g. #1

All spheres cast curved shadows.

The Earth casts a curved shadow.

Therefore:

The Earth is a sphere.

 

We have not covered this formal fallacy yet, but as we shall see in a matter of weeks, this argument form suffers from the flaw of an undistributed middle term.  But we need not get into the details of syllogistic logic to realize that, while spheres do indeed cast curved shadows, so do disks.  So the fact that the earth casts a curve shadow does not guarantee that the earth is a sphere.  It may be a disk (Just like Terry Pratchett thought.)

 

E.g. #2

If my theory “T” is true, then I will have experimental observation “O.”

I have experimental observation “O.”

Therefore:

My theory “T” is true.

 

But close attention to form shows that this is the fallacy of “Affirming the Consequence.”[1]   Notice if I said, “If you pass the final exam, you will pass the course.” and then you discovered that you passed the course, it would be a mistake for you to conclude that you passed the exam.  I did not say you will pass the course only if you pass the exam. I only said passing the exam is a way of passing the course, but not necessarily the only way.  You might have a passing average without actually passing the exam itself. But passing the exam would guarantee that you passed the course. That's what my initial conditional said. For more on standard formal fallacies, you may wish to revisit my notes on formal logic from earlier in the course.

 

2)      But in this module we are looking at informal fallacies.  These fallacies do not turn on an inappropriate formal relationship between the premises offered as warrant and the conclusion, but rather the fact that, while there may be a psychological connection or emotional connection between these items, there is in fact no logical connection between what is offered as warrant and what is presented as the conclusion.  These fallacies trick us (sometimes) into accepting the conclusion because the premises serve to distract us from the actual issue at hand.  These distractions are in fact irrelevant to the issue. For these reasons they are sometimes called “red herrings.”

 

Text Box: Relevance fallacies are also called red herrings. 

A herring is a smelly fish that, if dragged across the trail that a hound is tracking, might lead the hound on a wild goose chase; the fish is merely a distracting irrelevancy.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

We will look at several specific versions, but we could identify many more if we wished.  I think it is more helpful to focus on what these fallacies have in  common (i.e. they are fallacies of relevance) so as to recognize any member of this family of fallacies.

 

Specific Fallacies:

 

1.       Ad Hominem (tu quoque , abusive, circumstantial)

2.       Straw Man Fallacy

3.       False Dilemma Fallacies (also called a False Dichotomy)

4.       Fallacies involved in misplacing the burden of proof

5.       Begging the Question (also called circular reasoning)

6.       Appeals to emotion (fear, pity, anger)

7.       Fallacies involved in arriving at irrelevant conclusions

 

A fallacy is a mistake in reasoning, an argument that doesn't really support or prove the contention it is supposed to support or prove.

 

Here is an example of a fallacy:

 

You tell me it's dangerous to text when I'm driving, but I have seen YOU doing it.

 

The speaker is dismissing someone's claim that it's dangerous to drive and text.  However, the fact offered to support this contention, that the other person texts while he or she drives, has no bearing on whether texting while driving is dangerous.  It is irrelevant to the issue at hand.

 

If one offers this as a way of disputing the initial claim or argument, one is committed a fallacy - a mistake in reasoning.  (And if one accepts it, one has fallen for a fallacy.)  More precisely, this is a relevance fallacy, because the countercharge, “I have seen you doing it.” is not relevant to the question at issue. 

 

What’s the issue?

 

“Is texting while driving dangerous?”

 

What is being offered as a relevant fact to the issue.

 

“You do it.”

 

But “I have seen you doing it.” is NOT relevant to the issue in question (i.e. whether texting while driving is dangerous).

 

1)      Argumentum ad Hominem

 

The name translates as "argument to the person."

 

One commits this fallacy if one thinks that by dismissing the person presenting a position, idea, proposal, claim, argument, etc., (or trying to at least), one simultaneously is dismissing the position itself.

 

There are three main types of ad hominem attack:

 

1.       Tu Quoque: more Latin (meaning "you too!"). You point to similar faults in your opponent when your actions or character is called into question. More generally: you point to a fault elsewhere to draw attention away from the fault being discussed.

2.       Abusive: you simply attack the character or rationality of your opponent (or a group to which the opponent belongs like "liberals" or "pro-lifers")

3.       Circumstantial: you point to circumstances which make your opponent to imply that your opponent is untrustworthy or suspect.

 

ad hominem tu quoque. (to the person- and you also)

 

The texting and driving example above is an ad hominem.  More specifically this is an ad hominem tu quoque.

 

Even if I went on to say:

 

Not only have I seen you drive and text, but just last week you were saying it isn't dangerous to do that.

 

This too is an argumentum ad hominem.

 

Instead of addressing whether it is dangerous to text and drive, I am still talking about the other person.

 

Accusations of one’s opponent doing a "flip-flop" are standard in political campaigns, despite the fact that a person's being inconsistent or changing his or her mind has no bearing on the wisdom of his or her position, either now or at any other time.

 

Now, if the issue happens to BE the consistency or uniformity in commitment to certain values, that is a different issue/question.  In that case, maybe a history of flipflopping is an important question.  But that is NOT what is at issue here.  Here the issue is whether texting while driving is dangerous.  And the person is merely changing the subject.  

 

ad hominem Abusive

 

Here is a different kind of example of argumentum ad hominem:

 

Q: What do you think about the president's proposal for expanding Medicaid?

A: It's ridiculous. He is a self-serving politician who just wants the votes of those with low incomes.

 

This is an ad hominem abusive.  Here, the speaker is just bad-mouthing the president, which doesn't tell us anything at all about the strengths or weaknesses of the president's proposal.  If the speaker wants to show that the president's proposal is ridiculous, the speaker needs to talk about the proposal, not the person making the proposal or what may or may not be his motivations.

 

ad hominem Circumstantial

 

Another slightly different example:

 

You need not take seriously Father Hennessey’s arguments to establish the moral impermissibility of abortion because Father Hennessey is a Catholic priest and priests are required to hold such views.

 

This is not an ad hominem abusive (unless you think calling someone a Catholic priest is an insult 😊), but rather an ad hominem circumstantial.  The speaker in this example isn't exactly bad-mouthing Father Hennessey, but he or she is still talking about the person offering the argument and isn't talking about what Father Hennessey actually said.  She or he is referencing a circumstance of Father Hennessey (i.e. being a Catholic priest).  If someone gave you this argument, you wouldn't have the faintest idea what Father Hennessey actually thinks the grounds for the impermissibility of abortion are, let alone what is wrong with his moral reasoning.

 

Related ad hominem Fallacies:

 

Poisoning the Well

 

Attacking the person's consistency or character or circumstances and by so doing, impugning their position.  Here one tries to undermine the validity of the claim being made by asserting it comes from a suspect source.  But, for instance, some have alleged that Hitler was a vegetarian.  What does this fact, even if true, have to do with the propriety of a vegetarian lifestyle?  Nothing.  If that’s the issue under discussion, it would be irrelevant.

 

Guilt by Association

 

Outside of logic classes, the phrase "guilt by association" refers to the concept that a person is judged by the company he or she keeps.  For example, if you hang out with unsavory people, then others may think that you too have unsavory qualities.  But here we have something else in mind.  Here we use the phrase to denote a very common version of the argumentum ad hominem. The fallacy Guilt by Association occurs when a speaker or writer tries to persuade us to dismiss a belief by telling us that someone we don't like has that belief.

 

For example:

 

You think waterboarding is torture? That sounds like something these left-wing, ivy tower college professors would say.

 

What is the speaker’s intent here?

 

For listeners to dismiss the idea that waterboarding is torture.

 

What “reason” has been offered?

 

That idea is associated with "left-wing, ivy tower college professors."

 

The argument isn't a straightforward argumentum ad hominem, because the speaker doesn't imply that "left-wing college professors" came up with the idea that waterboarding is torture.  He or she is just saying that they likely have that idea.  The fact that the idea is associated with such people is offered as a reason for dismissing it.  The belief is "guilty" by virtue of its alleged association with supposedly left-wing college professors.

 

Genetic Fallacy

 

Here the suggestion is criticized because of the circumstances of its origins.

 

God is just an idea people came up with way back before they had science.

 

The speaker is dismissing the idea of God because of its origin.  But keep in mind a lot of innovative scientific revolutions originated quite by accident.  Einstein allegedly came up with the idea of general relativity while riding on the trolley car and wondering what it would be like if he were riding on a beam of light.  The chemical structure of benzene occurred to Friedrich August Kekulé while he was dozing by the fire.  He claimed to have seemed to have seen serpents biting at their tails.  Penicillin was discovered by accident as well.  But the accuracy of the benzene molecular structure or the effectiveness of penicillin have nothing to do with the origins of these ideas.

 

Straw Man Fallacy[2]

 

This is an attempt to dismiss a contention by distorting or misrepresenting it in such a way as to make it appear absurd or otherwise easily defeated.

 

Q: Should we outlaw large ammunition clips?

A: Disarming everyone, leaving them weak and vulnerable to criminal armed attacks is ridiculous and dangerous.

 

Well, what A has said might very well be true, But that is not what is at issue here.  No one is proposing “disarming everyone,” at least not in this context.

 

You: I think we should legalize medical marijuana.

Your friend:  Maybe you think everyone should go around stoned, but I think that's absurd.

 

Straw Man:  So rather than defeat one’s actual opponent one attacks a “straw man,” easily defeated, in part, because he can't strike back.  Defeating the Straw Man leaves the actual opponent unscathed.

 

False Dilemma Fallacy (Ignoring other alternatives)

 

The False Dilemma (also called a false dichotomy) is a fallacy that happens when someone tries to establish a conclusion by offering it as the only alternative to something we will find unacceptable, unattainable, or implausible.

 

Premise 1: We must either completely eliminate Social Security or our country will go bankrupt.

Premise 2 : (Implied, but unstated premise)  We must not allow our country to go bankrupt.

Therefore:

We must eliminate Social Security completely.

 

This looks like a disjunctive syllogism and in fact it is.  There is nothing really wrong with the form of this argument.  It is a valid argument form:

 

Either A or B

Not B

Therefore

A

 

So it is not a formal fallacy.  However, it is an informal fallacy because the speaker is falsely suggesting that there are only two options, when in fact there are more than two.  Similarly:

 

Either we allow the oil companies to drill for oil in the Gulf of Mexico or we will be at the mercy of OPEC. Therefore, we shouldn't prevent the oil companies from drilling for oil in the Gulf.

 

Same fallacy here.  Are these really the only two alternatives?  (No.)

 

Related False Dilemma Fallacies:

 

The Perfectionist Fallacy & The Line-Drawing Fallacy

 

Two false dilemma arguments are so common that they have their own names. One is called the Perfectionist Fallacy.  The other is called the Line-Drawing Fallacy.

 

Perfectionist Fallacy

 

The fallacy is committed when a speaker or writer ignores options between "perfection" and "nothing." Here's an example:

 

Increasing restrictions on assault weapons will not end gun violence in this country.  So there's no reason to do it.

 

Though the proposal may not be perfect, this alone is no reason to suggest that it would not be effective and worthwhile to any degree.

 

Line-Drawing Fallacy

 

This fallacy occurs when a speaker or writer assumes that either a crystal-clear line can be drawn between two things, or else there is no difference between them. Here is an example:

 

It doesn't make sense to say that someone is rich. After all, nobody can say just how much money a person has to have in order to be "rich."

 

Even if there is no sharply drawn and universally agreed on line between state A and state B, that does not mean in and of itself that it is impossible to distinguish between state A and state B.  We have many vague, but perfectly serviceable, words (as we noted earlier in the course: e.g. twilight, bald, flat, etc.).  The fact that there is no precise line drawn between being bald and not being bald does not mean there is no difference between being bald and not being bald.  There are individuals who are clearly bald, others who are clearly not bald and then the borderline cases in the middle.

 

Misplacing the Burden of Proof

 

This fallacy occurs when people try to support or prove their own position by misplacing the burden of proof on those who reject it.  Here is an example:

 

There is no reason NOT to believe in the healing power of crystals since no one has conclusively shown they do not have healing powers.

 

The old debaters’ motto is: The one who asserts must prove.[3]  That’s fairly right. In general, if what I am asserting is something exceptional or conflicts with common sense, then the burden of proof falls to me.

 

Another example:

 

Guns should be outlawed.  Give me one good reason for thinking they shouldn't.

 

The speaker has incorrectly shifted the burden of proof to the listener, despite the fact that it is the speaker who is making the assertion.  In point of fact, the United States Constitution is interpreted as giving people the right to own a gun, so the burden of proof is on the speaker to explain why the right does not in fact exist or why the right should be removed.

 

Related fallacy: When someone asserts that we should believe a claim because nobody has proved it false, the fallacy is a version of misplacing the burden of proof known as Appeal to Ignorance.

 

Special Legal Burden of Proof

 

Of course, in a criminal court, the burden of proof always falls on the prosecution. The defense is not required to prove innocence of the accused.  To win the case, it must only prevent the prosecution from succeeding in its attempt to prove guilt beyond a reasonable doubt.

 

Begging the Question Fallacy (Begin my assuming what you are supposedly trying to prove)

 

In everyday language, to beg the question has lately come to mean simply to raise the question. However, traditionally, and in logic, Begging the Question means something else. A speaker or writer is guilty of begging the question logically when he or she tries to "support" a contention by offering as "evidence" what amounts to a repackaging of the very contention in question.  Were I to claim that it is morally wrong to engage in human cloning because human cloning is unethical, I am begging the question.  My conclusion here is that it is immoral to engage in human cloning.  My premise is that “It is unethical to engage in human cloning.”  But my “premise” assumes to be true what my conclusion states and is merely a restatement of it.

 

Incidentally, it might be worth noting that begging the question arguments are all formally valid. That is, if the premises are true, then the conclusion would have to be true.  Consider this argument.

 

Premise: Snow is white.

Therefore:

Conclusion: Snow is white.

 

If my premise is true, then my conclusion must be true, which is the very definition of a formally valid argument.  Nevertheless, this is a terrible argument given that the purpose of an argument is to persuade.  If you accept my premise, then you've already accepted my conclusion, and so I have not persuaded you.  On the other hand, if you don't accept my premise, then you won't accept my conclusion on the basis of that premise and therefore I have not persuaded you.  This is what makes begging the question such a terrible argument form.

 

Appeals to Emotion Fallacies

 

Here the person evokes an emotional response on the part of the listener so as to distract them from the fact that they have offered no actual reason to accept the conclusion. Here are a few (in no particular order):

 

·         Appeal to Pity

·         Argument from Outrage

·         Scare Tactics

·         Peer Pressure Fallacy.

·         Apple Polishing

·         Guilt Tripping

·         Appeal to Envy

·         Appeal to Jealousy

 

Appeal to Pity

 

I'll merely elaborate a little bit on the first one on our list, “appeals to emotions, in part because I get this one a lot.  Students will come to me at the end of the semester and tell me that I should award them a higher grade in my course because if they don't pass my course with a higher grade, they will lose their scholarships.  Clearly what such a student is trying to get me to do is to feel bad for him or her and award a grade sufficient to prevent losing the scholarship.  

 

However, if the issue is whether or not they earned the grade that I have calculated for them, the fact that they will lose their scholarship is irrelevant, an irrelevant appeal to my emotions, specifically to pity.  Sometimes lost on students is that, the reason they might lose their scholarship is because they really aren't very good students, as evidenced by their poor performance in my class. But that's another story.

 

Nevertheless, you get the idea here.  The nature of all these fallacies are to evoke in the hearer a kind of emotional response which makes the hearer sympathetic to the conclusion that the fallacious reasoner wants the hearer to support, be that emotion pity, anger, peer pressure, et cetera.

 

Keep in mind that one might use these fallacious devices along with more substantial logical arguments to bolster the arguments’ effectiveness.  In other words, I might appeal to emotions in order to make my conclusion more emotionally attractive to you and you might thereby accept an additional though very weak argument as compelling, one you would have otherwise rejected.

 

Irrelevant Conclusion

 

What we've looked at are some of the most common fallacies of relevance. These are patterns that occur with enough frequency that there is some usefulness to categorizing them and thus making them a bit easier to recognize.

 

However it would be impossible to enumerate categories sufficient that cover all of the fallacies that occur where conclusions are “supported” with irrelevant facts and there are diminishing returns to attempting to get too fine-grained.  These others we can simply refer to as “fallacies of irrelevant conclusion” as a generic umbrella term.

 

Epilogue:

 

Finally, if I pull a gun on you and tell you to give me your wallet, I'm not committing a fallacy; I'm mugging you.



[1] You may recall that this was precisely Karl Popper's criticism of the supposed use of “verification” in science. His claim is that science does not/ cannot proceed through verification, but rather only through falsification. Falsification, y contrast, is not premised on this formal fallacy, but rather on the logically valid form of reasoning of Modus Tollens: If P then Q. Not Q. Therefore Not P.

[2] Only recently, and I mean by that maybe the last 5 years or so, I have come to hear a phrase that must draw its origin from the Straw Man Fallacy. But it's sort of the exact opposite. It's called "Steel-manning One's Opponent."  In a discussion between people arguing for contradictory positions, they are each required to give the strongest version of their opponents' positions.  This is done to establish that each genuinely understands and does not mischaracterized the opposing position, and that even under its strongest faithful presentation, is subject to criticism.

[3] Onus probandi incumbit ei qui dicit, non ei qui negat.