Logic and Categorical Claims

 

Categorical Statements

Standard Form Categorical Claims

Categorical Claims and Standard Form (Format)

Categorical Claims and Quantity: Universal vs Particular

Categorical Claims and Quality: Affirmative vs Negative

Categorical Claims and Unit Classes

Categorical Claims and Venn Diagrams

Categorical Claims and the Square of Opposition (Hypothetical View)

The Square of Opposition: Existential View

Categorical Claims and Distribution

Logical Relations

Fallacious Reasoning Regarding Contraries and Contradictories

 

Formal Logic and Categorical Claims

 

Let's move on to the topic of Categorical claims.  I would like to read a quote:

 

"Like Moliere's M Jourdain who found that he had long been speaking prose, I found that I had long been forming propositions.  `yes, I form propositions when my tongue does more than wag.  I form them out of terms.  I say something about something.  Therefore, I ought to be able, in serious talk, to pinpoint those two parts of proposition.  I ought to know exactly what I am talking about, and exactly what I am saying about it.’[1]

A.      A. Luce

 

The classical study of deduction is also called the Aristotelian study of deduction.  It was so names after the Greek philosopher Aristotle (384-322 b.c.) Aristotle and generations of logicians afterwards confined themselves primarily to the study of certain kinds of statements, Categorical statements, the relationships among these statements and arguments comprised entirely of these kinds of statements.  Aristotle and later writers found that mentally moving from one group of statements to a certain conclusion, when they are arranged in a particular way was good, correct, logical.  But certain mental movements with different arrangements of statements were not good, not correct, illogical.  They noticed patterns building up and the relations between the patterns.  This they formalized into rules.  These are the rules of the categorical syllogisms that we will be studying.

 

Categorical statements, claims, propositions, (I will be using these words interchangeably) are claims about classes of things, that is, sets or categories.  A class is a collection of objects that have specified characteristic in common.  There are various ways in which one class may be related to another.  If every member of one class is also a member of a second, the first class is said to be included or contained in the second.  For instance, the class of blue Toyotas is included in the class of cars.

 

However, if only some members of the first class are included in the second, the first is said to be partially contained in the second.  For example, the class of blue Toyotas is partially contained in the class of scratched cars.  (That is, some blue Toyotas are scratched, but not others.)  There are some pairs of sets that have no members in common.  These are disjoint sets, such as the set of all Toyotas and the set of all melons.  No Toyota is a melon and no melon is a Toyota.

 

Standard Form Categorical Claims

 

In ordinary informal language, we can express categorical claims in all sort of different ways.  (E.g. All men are mortal.  Every man is a mortal thing.  If it’s a man then it is mortal.  Each man is mortal. Etc.)

 

But there are just four standard forms of categorical propositions.  They exhaust the possible logical relations that may occur between any two sets of things.  They can be illustrated by the following claims:

 

                                1. All A-s are B-s.

                                2. No A-s are B-s.

                                3. Some A-s are B-s. (Where “some” has the technical meaning of “at least one.”)

                                4. Some A-s are not B-s. (Again, meaning “at least one.”)

 

Note that each of these categorical claims relate one category (in whole or part) as indicated by the  SUBJECT TERM (A-s) to another category, indicated by the PREDICATE TERM  (B-s) (either affirmatively or negatively).

 

Note further that the verb in a standard form categorical, claim is always ”are” and that both the subject and the predicate of a standard form categorical claim must be plural nouns or noun-phrases.

 

Pop Quiz:  The claim “No cats are friendly.” Is NOT a standard form categorical claim. 

 

Why?

 

How could it be rewritten to express the same content but be in standard form?

 

Categorical Claims and Quantity: Universal vs Particular

 

If a categorical claim makes a claim about the entire SUBJECT CLASS it is called a UNIVERSAL CATEGORICAL Claim.

 

All  Toys…

No Fish…

All Bugs…

No people from Georgia…

 

If a categorical claim makes a claim about one or more members of the SUBJECT CLASS, but not every member of the subject class, it is called a PARTICULAR CATEGORICAL claim

 

Some Eggs…

Some men…

Some Lithuanians…

 

So all categorical claims are either: UNIVERSAL or PARTICULAR

 

We call this the QUANTITY of the proposition. And the words “All,”  “No” and “Some” are the “quantifiers.”

 

Categorical Claims and Quality: Affirmative vs Negative

 

When a categorical claim asserts the existence of a relationship between the Subject term and the Predicate term we say that the proposition is AFFIRMATIVE.

 

When a categorical claim denies the relationship between the Subject term and the Predicate term we say that the proposition is NEGATIVE

 

All categorical propositions are either: AFFIRMATIVE or NEGATIVE

 

We call this the QUALITY of the proposition.

 

AFFIRMATIVE

NEGATIVE

UNIVERSAL

(#1) ALL  As are Bs

(#2) NO As is Bs

PARTICULAR

(#3) SOME As are Bs

(#4) SOME As are not Bs

 

 

#1 is a universal affirmative proposition.  It is about two classes.  It claims that the first class is included in the second.

 

#2 is a universal negative proposition.  It denies that any A is a B. 

 

Both one and two are universal claims because they do claim something about each and every member of the subject class, or the “universe class”.

 

Now sometimes a person will define the universe they wish to talk about.  He may only be talking about the universe of married women, or of human car drivers or fish.  For clarity, we must determine specify the “universe of discourse” at issue. 

 

O. K.    We have gone over a universal affirmative and a universal negative.

 

#3 is an affirmative particular.  It does NOT state something about each and every member of the subject class, but rather it affirms something about some member of the subject class (and maybe only one member at that).

 

#4 is a negative particular.  It does NOT state something about each and every member of the subject class, but rather it denies something about some member of the subject class (and maybe only one member at that).

 

The four standard forms may be written schematically as follows where S is the subject class and P is the predicate class.

 

1. All S are P

2. No S are P

3. Some S are P

4. Some S are not P

 

If you are asked to translate an English sentence into a standard from categorical claim, It MUST conform to one of the four possible forms:

 

1. All ___ are ___.

2. No ___ are ___.

3. Some ___ are ___.

4. Some ___ are not ___.

 

And remember that only plural nouns (e.g. cats) or noun phrases (things that are friendly) go into the blanks.

 

Categorical Claims and Unit Classes

 

Sometimes the class of things being discusses is a unit class (only one member).  For instance, the sentence “Today is Monday.” In NOT a standard form categorical claim, but it can be rendered as a categorical claim.  How?  Well, I can convey the same information by saying “All things identical to today are things that are identical to Monday.”  Thus, I rendered the unit class claim as an universal, in this case affirmative.  Likewise, I can say “Socrates is not a banana.” or express the same information as a standard from categorical claim:  “No things identical to Socrates are things identical with bananas.”  Since “Socrates” names a unit class, we can treat this too as an universal claim.

 

From the time of its discoverer, Aristotle, until the nineteenth century, categorical logic was the only systematic logic.  However, many refinements were made to the basic theory during this period of over two thousand years.[2]  We will next be covering the basics of this system, but even the basics should prove helpful in our evaluation of arguments and allow us to do a lot of logic. 

 

Since logic is a skill, like playing chess or poker, I recommend that you practice diagraming categorical claims and check your own comprehension of the material.  If you have problems with it you are welcome to ask me if course.

 

Now, categorical logic is based on standard form categorical claims.  A standard form categorical claim is what results when you put the words or phrases that name the classes which you are talking about into the following structures:

 

1.       All ___________ are ___________.

2.       No  ___________ are ___________.

3.       Some __________ are ___________.

4.       Some __________ are not _______.

 

The Affirmative Universal is referred to as an “A” claim.

The Negative Universal is referred to as an “E” claim.

The Affirmative Particular is referred to as an “I” claim.

The Negative Particular is referred to as an “O” claim.

 

To be sure, these are not the way you will find most categorical claims in everyday life.  But it is very helpful to standardize normal claims, to translate, so to speak, ordinary language categorical claims into standard form.  This makes them easier to deal with and make the logical relations between the claims more pronounced.

 

Sometimes the translation into standard form will be easy; other times more difficult.  But this is a regimentation that I want everyone to adhere to.  If I ask for an example of a categorical claim or argument, I want it in standard form, and I will deduct points on a tests or quiz if you don't present them in standard form.

 

The phrases that go in the blanks are called terms; the one that goes in the first blank is called the subject term and the one that goes in the second is called the predicate term.  Shades of eighth grade English class eh? 

 

Categorical Claims and Venn Diagrams

 

One way to view the "logical geography" of the standard-form categorical claims is to use diagrams invented by John Venn, a friend of Lewis Carroll.  Perhaps, you have been introduced to diagrams used in set theory; the Venn Diagrams are somewhat different.  Most descriptions of Venn Diagrams introduce the three symbols and the symbols are used to answer the question: “Anybody home?”[3]  That is, is the region empty or occupied?  The area inside the circle is used to provide information on the members of the class in question, if there are any. The area outside the circle represents all other individuals (the complementary class) if there are any.  Note that the label for the things names by the set is written outside the circle, even though "things” themselves, if there are any, would be inside the circle.

 

 

1.       A circle is used to represent a subject class or a predicate class and is generally so labeled with an S (subject) or a P (predicate).  Putting the name of the actual subject or predicate class next to the circle is preferred.  If the circle is BLANK, then we DO NOT KNOW is anything is in there or not (e.g. whether anyone is home.)

 

things.gif (1122 bytes)

 

2.       Shading (or sometimes many parallel lines) is used to indicate areas which are known to be EMPTY. I.e., there are no individuals existing in a shaded area (nobody home).  Be careful here.  Shading does NOT mean full.  It means EMPTY.

 

E.g., the diagram below represents the class of "Yeti."

 

shading.gif (1164 bytes)

 

3.       The third symbol used is an "X" which represents "at least one" or "some" individual exists in the area in which it is placed.  The diagram below indicates there is at least one member in this class, "some thing."  There is at least one member of this category.

 

things1.gif (1134 bytes)

 

Again, if the circle is blank, neither shaded nor containing an X then, for the purposes of this course, we shall interpret that as meaning that WE DO NOT KNOW IF THE SET HAS MEMBERSHIP OR NOT.[4]

 

Below are four figures which represent each of the four categorical claims.

 

Figure 1# All Philosophers are Idlers.

 

venn_a.gif (1566 bytes)

 

The region to the left of center (region 1) is empty.  That is, the region which would contain “philosophers” who are NOT idlers is empty.  Why is that?  Because the claim is that all philosophers (if there are any) are idlers (within the Idlers’ circle).

 

Figure #2 No Philosophers are Idlers.

 

venn_e.gif (1533 bytes)

 

Here the center region (region 2) is empty.  That is, the is region which would contain things that are BOTH philosophers and idlers is empty.  Why is that?  It is because the claim states at there are no things that are BOTH philosophers AND idlers.

 

Figure #3 Some Philosophers are Idlers.

 

venn_i.gif (1452 bytes)

Figure #4 Some Philosophers are not Idlers.

 

Here the center region (region 2) has at least one occupant. 

 

venn_o.gif (1466 bytes)

 

Here the region to the left of center (region 1) has at least one occupant.

 

Figures 1 through 4 show the four standard form categorical claims represented by Venn Diagrams, which are graphic illustrations of what the claims say.  In the diagram the circles represent the classes named by the terms, shaded areas represent areas that are empty, and area containing x's represent a region which contains at least one member.

 

Notice that he A-claim give us information about region 1 only, and no information about region 2 or region 3.

 

An E claim gives us information about region 2 but nothing about regions 1 or 3.

 

Likewise, I claims only tell us about region 2 and O claims only tell is about region 1.

 

For the purposes of simplicity, logicians have adopted the custom of interpreting the categorical word ‘some’ as meaning ‘at least one’. (and so shall we.) 

 

What I would like to do now is take some examples of categorical claims and get some practice in translating and diagraming them.

 

                                1. Only Athletes are long distance runners.

                                2. Minors are not eligible.

                                3. Every salamander is a lizard.

                                4. Not every lizard is a salamander

                                5. Not all lizards are salamanders.

                                6. Only reptiles can be lizards.

                                7. Frogs are the only semiaquatic reptiles.

                                8. Frogs are not the only semiaquatic reptiles.

                                9. Wherever there are snakes there are frogs.

                                10. There are frogs wherever there ore snakes.

                                11. The guy who held up the bank is my next-door neighbor.

 

Categorical Claims and the Square of Opposition (Hypothetical View)

 

Now logicians love patterns.  They also love to classify.  One of the ways they love to set up the four categorical statement forms is in a square, and one of the classifications they like to note about the categorical claims is whether or not and which terms of the claim are distributed. 

 

First, let's set the categorical claims up in a square. 

 

 

Affirmative

 

Negative

 

 

Square of Opposition

 

Universal

(A) All S are P

 

(E) No S are P

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Particulars

(I) Some S are P

 

(O) Some S are not P

 

 

 

 

 

The Square of Opposition: Hypothetical View

 

This is a nice lead in to our next topic, the Square of Opposition.

 

The square of opposition is concerned with the relation between the various categorical claims.  It is set up in the way you see above.  Now the relations between the corresponding claims are dependent on the meanings of each of the claims, and what implications can logically be drawn from them if they were true.  But when are they true?  This is a very important question and the answer is, to some extent, dependent on the view point you adopt when you are evaluating the universal claims and what they mean.

 

Hypothetical View and lack of Existential Import

 

Take for example the claim, "All unicorns are horned creatures."  First things first, what kind of categorical statement is that?  Well, clearly this is an A claim.  An Universal Affirmative claim.  Now is this claim true or false?  For the moment, let's adopt the Hypothetical View of interpretative Universal Affirmative claims.  On this interpretation we would read the sentence as follows:

 

For all things in the universe, if it is a unicorn, then it is a horned creature.

 

This is call the Hypothetical View point because you are NOT claiming that there are in fact unicorns, but merely IF there are unicorns, then they are horned creatures.  This statement can be true whether or not there are any unicorns.  And given what we mean by unicorns, it in fact seems in fact to be true… under this Hypothetical View interpretation.

 

A and I Claims.

 

Let's assume that the statement is true.  If it is true that all unicorns are horned creatures (under this interpretation), what can we know about the corresponding I claim: "Some unicorns are horned creatures."? 

 

Well, actually, nothing.  It is possible for A to be true while I is false. Yes. This will happen in the case were there are no existing unicorns.  Remember what the I-claim states.  Since “some” means at least one existing thing, the I claim is saying that at least one existing thing is a unicorn and is a horned thing.  But there are no unicorn.  (Sorry.)  So then could A be true (If there were unicorns they would all be horned things.) while I is false?  Yes. 

 

And can the A claim be true while the l claim is true?  Yes.  If there were in fact unicorns (and all were horned creatures). 

 

Thus the truth of the A claim tells us nothing about corresponding the I claim.  The truth of A insures neither the truth not the falsity of I.  Likewise, that the A claim is false tells us nothing about whether the I claims is true or false.  Further, knowing the truth value of the I claim, tells us nothing about the truth value of A.

 

The same lack of relations holds for E and O statements.  On the hypothetical view, an E-claim is read, “for all things in the universe, if it is an S then it is not a P.  For our example, when I claim "No unicorns are winged creatures." I should be understood as meaning, "For all things, if it is a unicorn, then it is not a winged creature.”  The truth of the E claim is compatible with the truth or the falsity of the corresponding O claim.  Likewise the truth or the falsity of the O claim tell is nothing about the truth or the falsity of the corresponding E claim.  Therefore, knowing the truth value of one, tells us nothing about the truth value of the other. 

 

A and E Claims

 

What about the relationship of the A to the E on the hypothetical view?  What are the truth conditions, that is what does it take for the statement to be true?  For an A statement to be true means simply that if there are any unicorns, they must have horns.  They may or may not exist, but if they do then they have horns.  This statement is only false if there ARE unicorns, but they don't have horns.   That is the only time this statement is false if you adopt the hypothetical viewpoint.  So an A and E claims could both be true as the same time?  How? They are both true if there were no unicorns.

 

Could they both be false? Yes.  How? If there ARE unicorns and some of them have horns, but some of them do not.  In that case, they are both false.

 

And of course, if there are unicorns, one be true while the other is false.

 

So again, knowing the truth value of one of the pair tells us nothing about the truth value of the other.  There is no logical relation between them under the hypothetical view.

 

I and O Claims

 

What about the relation between I and O claims on the hypothetical viewpoint.  Could they both be true at the same time? Yes. False?  Yes. One true and the other false?  Yes.  So is there any relation going on here that allows us to draw information of bout the truth value of one if we know the truth value of the other? No.

 

A and O (and E and I) Claims

 

Now what set of statements have we not examined?  The relation between A claims and O claims and the relation between E claims and I claims.  Taking the first pair first, if I know that that the A claim is true, then I know that the O claim MUST be false.  If I know that, for all things in the universe, if it is a unicorn, then it is a horned creature (The A claim on the hypothetical view), then I know that it CANNOT be the case that at least one existing thing is a unicorn and it is NOT a horned thing (the O claim on the hypothetical view).

 

Likewise, if the O claim is true, then the A claim MUST be false.  That is it cannot be that all unicorns are horned creature AND that some unicorns are NOT horned creatures at the same time.  These claims cannot both be true at the same time not can they both be false at the same time; they MUST have opposite truth values.  This is the logical relation of contradiction.

 

The same relationship holds between E and I claims.  They are saying exactly the opposite tings.  (Contradiction)

 

The same logical relation of contradiction hold between E and I claims.

 

 

Affirmative

 

Negative

 

 

Square of Opposition

 

Universal

(A) All S are P

 

(E) No S are P

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Contradictions

 

Particulars

(I) Some S are P

 

(O) Some S are not P

 

 

 

 

 

The Square of Opposition: Existential View

 

Now suppose we change out interpretation from the modern, or Hypothetical View, to the Existential View.  This was the interpretation favored by Aristotle and his ancient and medieval logician followers, since they did not think it made a lot of sense to talk about the relations of one empty set (non-existing things) to another.  Truth conditions of the universal categorical claims say that they are true only when each class has at least one member.  This is called given universal categorical claims “Existential Import.”  Under this interpretation, the categorical statements within the square are related in numerous way.  All sorts of new logical relations pop up.  Let's us consider the square with the existential viewpoint.  From this point of view, this is how A and E claims should be diagrammed.  Note, these diagrams indicate that the subject class is not empty.  As such, the A claim implies the I claim and the E claim implies the O claim.    (See below.)

 

 

A and I Claims.

 

Let’s first look at corresponding A and I claims.  If it is the case that all unicorns are horned creature AND there is at least one unicorn, then it MUST be the case that some unicorns are horned animals.  Thus is the A claim is true, then the I claim MUST be true.  And note further that is the I claim is false, then the A claim MUST be false.  This is the logical relation of implication.

 

E and O Claims.

 

Let’s next look at corresponding E and O claims.  If it is the case that No unicorns are horned creature AND there is at least one unicorn, then it MUST be the case that some unicorns are NOT horned animals.  Thus is the E claim is true, then E claim MUST be true.  And note further that is the O claim is false, then the E claim MUST be false.  This is, again, the logical relation of implication.     

 

A and E Claims

 

Now let’s look at A & E claims.  Could they both be true at the same time?  No.  If there are unicorns and all of them are horned creatures, then it cannot be the case that there are unicorns and NONE are horned creature. 

 

Could they both be false at the same time?  Yes.  If there are unicorns, some of which are horned creatures, others of which are not.  This is the logical relation of contrariety.

 

I and O Claims

 

How about the relation between I and O statements?  Can the both be true?  Yes.  See above.  Can they both be false?  No.  If there actually are unicorns, then either at least one of them is a horned creature or it is not (since we are assuming there has to be at least one.)  This is the logical relation of sub-contrariety.

 

A and I and E and O claims?

 

The relationship of contradiction remains. 

 

 

Affirmative

 

Negative

 

 

Square of Opposition

 

Universal

(A) All S are P

   <- Contraries ->

(E) No S are P

 

Implies

 

 

Implies

 

 

 

 

Contradictions

 

 

 

 

 

Particulars

(I) Some S are P

<- Sub-contraries ->

(O) Some S are not P

 

 

 

 

 

Now, let me give you a set of definition:

 

Contradiction- a relation between two statements which holds when both statements cannot be true at the same time and cannot both be false at the same time.

 

Implies- One statement is said to imply a second when the truth of the first is sufficient to insure the truth of the second and the falsity of the second is sufficient to insure the falsity of the first.

 

Contrariety- a relation between two statements which holds when both statements cannot be true at the same time, though both may be false at the same time.

                               

Sub-contrariety- a relation between two statements which holds when both statements cannot be false at the same time, though both may be true at the same time.

 

Seeing the logical relation between the categorical statements will help us see what movements are licensed as what are not.  But as you can see, it is important to determine under what truth conditions an argument using categorical claims is being offered.  Are the subject and predicate categories assumed to be non-empty or not (Existential Import)?  This is important not only to determine the truth of the statements, but also to determine what conclusions we may validly draw from those statements.      

 

Moving Around the Existential Square

 

If we have the truth value of one of the four corresponding categorical claims, we can always know the truth value of its contradictory.  Many times we can know the truth value of the other corresponding claims by using the Existential Square of Opposition.  For instance if we know that "All aluminum cans are recyclable items."  We immediately know that its contradiction (O) is false.  We know that its contrary (E) is false and the contradiction of its contrary (I) is true.

 

However, on the Existential Square of Opposition we cannot always determine the truth value of the other three remaining claims.  For example if we begin by knowing only that the A-claim is false all we can infer is the truth value of the corresponding O-claim. (T)  Nothing follows about either the E-claim or the I-claim.  Since the A-claim and the E-claim can both be false, knowing that the A-claim is false does not tell us anything.  Since the I-claim and the O-claim can both be true, knowing the O is true does not tell us anything about the I claim.

 

Some exercises:

 

Determine as many truth values as you can using the Existential Square of Opposition.

 

                1. Some mice are short tailed animals. (T)

                2. No drugs are completely harmless substances. (T)

                3. Some evergreens are not softwoods. (F)

                4. All gardens are laborious projects. (F)

                5. No Muslims are Methodists. (F)

 

Categorical Claims and Distribution

 

Distribution is best thought of as a function of telling the reader or listener something about each member of entire class of things.  What classes?  Well, the classes referenced by the categorical claim (i.e. the subject class and/or the predicate class).  If something is told about the each member of the subject class, we say that the subject of the claim is “distributed.” 

 

And if something is told about each member of the entire predicate class, we say that the predicate of the claim is “distributed.”  Now if there is nothing being said about each member of the class, then we say that the class/term is “undistributed.”

 

A Claims: All S are P

 

What does an A-claim tell us?  It tells us something about each and every S: that each is a P.  So S (the subject) is distributed in an A claim.  But does the A claim tell us something about each and every P?  No. Thus the predicate is said to be “undistributed” in an A claim.

 

E Claims: No S are P

 

What does an E-claim tell us?  Well, first, it tells us something about each and every S: that each S is NOT a P.  So S (the subject) is distributed in an E claim.  However, does the E claim tell us something about each and every P?  Yes.  Each and very P is NOT an S.  Thus, the predicate is also said to be “distributed” in an E claim.

 

I Claims: Some S are P

 

What does the I claim tell us?  Does it tell us something about each and every S?  No.  Does it tell us something about each and every P?  No.  Thus NOTHING (neither the subject nor the predicate) is distributed in an I claim.

 

O Claims: Some S are not P

 

So far so good.  This is all fairly straightforward. 

 

A claim:                subject is distributed, predicate is not.

E claim:                 subject is distributed AND predicate is distributed.

I claim: neither the subject nor the predicate is distributed.

 

But we run into some trouble with O-claims.  It is fairly easy to see why A-claims have distributed subject terms.  They clearly tell us something about every member of the subject class.  Since they do not tell us anything about the entire predicate class, we say that they have an undistributed predicate term. 

 

E-claims are relatively easy to understand as well.  They something about each and every member of the subject class as well as something about each and every member of the predicate class.  In fact, if we were to Venn diagram the reverse of the claim, "No apples are oranges." that is, if we were to Venn diagram the claim, "No oranges are apples." we would end up with pretty much the same diagram.

 

I-claims do not give us much trouble either.  It doesn't take much time to realize that these statements tell us neither something about the entire subject class nor something about the entire predicate class.  So then, neither the subject term nor the predicate term is distributed in an I-claim.

 

O-claims may give us some difficulty.  I don't know about you, I had a little difficulty getting clear on this initially.  What does an O-claim state?  Some S are not P.  Now, not surprisingly, the subject term in an O claim is undistributed.  But, spoiler alert, the predicate terms of O claims is said to be distributed. But why? 

 

At first it might be difficult to see what, if anything, the O claim has to say about each and every member of the class of P.  But consider this.  If you knew that “Some saints were not men,” and this was the only thing you knew, what is the one thing you could tell me about each and every man?

 

There is one thing you could tell me.  Albeit, it is a minimal fact.  The set of men is does not fully include the set of all saints.  That is, for each member of the set, for each man, there is some saint to which that man is not identical.  But since this is something we can know about each and every man, the predicate is distributed in the O claim.

 

Does this mean that NO saints are men?  Not necessarily.  If the O claim is true, the E claim might be true, but it might be false as well.  The I-claim might be true or it might be false as well.

 

This certainly does seem to correspond with our intuition about these claims.  A universal claim says a lot.  Hence the name.  It only makes sense that when it is true, many things should follow from it.  So too, a particular claim only intends to say something small, weak, negligible.  When it is true it does just that, and few things follow from it.  But when it is false, that is, when it doesn't even say the little it meant to, this, in a negative sort of way, tell us something large.

 

But to be clear, the predicate term in an O claim is said to be distributed.

 

Distribution Chart

 

 

Subject Distributed?

Predicate Distributed

A Claim

Yes

No

E Claim

Yes

Yes

I Claim

No

No

O Claim

No

Yes

 

Logical Relations:

 

Implication, Entailment, Contradiction, Contraries and Sub-contraries Chart:

 

Could they both be true at the same time?

Could they both be false at the same time?

 

No

No

Contradictions

No

Yes

Contraries

Yes

No

Sub Contraries

Yes

Yes

None of the Above

 

Implication Chart

 

If the first one is true, could the second one be false?

If the second one is true, could the first one be false?

 

No

Yes

The first one implies the second one.

Yes

No

The second one implies the first one.

Yes

Yes

No Implication at all.

No

No

Each implies the other.  They are (logically) equivalent

 

Four More Logical Relations: Transitivity, Symmetricity, Reflexivity and Equivalence

 

Transitivity

 

A relation R is transitive if and only if (henceforth abbreviated “iff”), if x is related by R to y, and y is related by R to z, then x is related by R to z.

 

For example, being taller than is a transitive relation: if John is taller than Bill, and Bill is taller than Fred, then it is a logical consequence of the fact that “taller than” is transitive that John is taller than Fred.

 

A relation R is intransitive iff, if x is related by R to y, and y is related by R to z, then x is not related by R to z.

 

For example, being next in line to is an intransitive relation:  if John is next in line to Bill, and Bill is next in line to Fred, then it is a logical consequence of “being next in line” is an intransitive relation, that John is not next in line to Fred.

 

A relation R is non-transitive iff it is neither transitive nor intransitive.

 

For example, likes is a non-transitive relation: if John likes Bill, and Bill likes Fred, then, as a consequence of “likes” being non-transitive, there is no logical consequence concerning John liking Fred.

 

Symmetricity

 

A relation R is symmetric iff, if x is related by R to y, then y is related by R to x.

 

For example, being a cousin of is a symmetric relation: if John is a cousin of Bill, then it is a logical consequence of “being a cousin of” being a symmetric relation, that Bill is a cousin of John.

 

A relation R is asymmetric iff, if x is related by R to y, then y is not related by R to x.

 

For example, being the father of is an asymmetric relation: if John is the father of Bill, then it is a logical consequence of “being a the father of” being an asymmetric relation, that Bill is not the father of John.

 

A relation R is non-symmetric iff it is neither symmetric nor asymmetric.

 

 

For example, loves is a non-symmetric relation: if John loves Mary, then, alas, there is no logical consequence concerning Mary loving John.

 

Reflexivity

 

A relation R is reflexive iff, everything bears R to itself.

 

For example, being the same height as is a reflexive relation: everything is the same height as itself.

 

A relation R is irreflexive iff, nothing bears R to itself.

 

For example, being taller than is an irreflexive relation: nothing is taller than itself.

 

A relation R is non-reflexive iff it is neither reflexive nor irreflexive.

 

For example, loves is a non-reflexive relation: there is no logical reason to infer that somebody loves herself or does not love herself.

 

Equivalence

 

A relation R is an equivalence iff R is transitive, symmetric and reflexive.

 

For example, identical is an equivalence relation: if x is identical to y, and y is identical to z, then x is identical to z; if x is identical to y then y is identical to x; and x is identical to x.

 

Fallacious Reasoning Regarding Contraries and Contradictories

 

No rocks are alive.  Therefore, it follows that all rocks are dead.

 

But this does not follow.  That is because “alive” and “dead: are contraries, not contradictories. A failure to distinguish between the two can lead to any number of logical errors in arguments.

 

If two statements are contraries, then it is impossible for both of them to be true, but it is possible for both to be false.  However, if two statements are contradictories, however, it is impossible for them to both be true and it impossible for them to both be false.

The terms “alive” and “lifeless” are contradictories because everything either has life (is alive) or lacks life (is lifeless), and thus nothing is both alive and lifeless.  The terms alive and dead are contraries because nothing can be both alive and dead (cannot both be true of a thing at the same time), but some things might be neither (can both be false of thing at the same time).  Dead implies that it was once alive, but now it is not. Thus, the correct formulation of initial statement would be:

 

No rocks are alive, therefore all rocks are lifeless.

 

Because of the technical and specialized nature of the fallacy, it is unlikely that you will encounter it too often. If you do find this fallacy being used in a real-world argument, please send it to me as an example.

 

 



[1] Quoted in A.A. Luce, Logic

[2] For instance, they named all 24 of the valid categorical syllogisms.

 

Names of the 24 valid categorical syllogisms

 

Figure1

Figure2

Figure3

Figure 4

Barbara

Cesare

Datisi

Calemes

Celarent

Camestres

Disamis

Dimatis

Darii

Festino

Ferison

Fresison

Ferio

Baroco

Bocardo

Calemos*

Barbari*

Cesaro*

Felapton*

Fesapo*

Celaront*

Camestros*

Darapti*

Bamalip*

 

* Commits the existential assumption.

[3] One thinks The Who’s “Comfortably Numb” (i.e.  “Is anybody in there?”)

[4] This raises the issue of universal categorical claims and whether they carry existential import.  More on this later.