Critical Thinking About Questions
Nonsense
Questions:
Today
we see a distinct separation between the questions of Modern Science and Modern
Philosophy. Both inquiries use similar
rational methods, but they are different in terms of the sorts of questions
each seeks to answer.
·
Scientific questions ≠ Philosophical questions
What
is the nature of this difference? Science
seeks to answer questions that are empirical (observational) in nature. If one can answer a question by doing an
empirical investigation, then it is not a philosophical question; it is a
scientific question. (I am conceiving of Science very broadly so as to include
history and the social sciences.)
Empirical: Observational.
Refers to what can be known through sensory experience.
But
what about questions which cannot be answered by empirical investigation,
questions that no amount of science could hope to answer? Are all non-empirical questions necessarily
“Philosophical?”
No.
Some
non-empirical questions are simply nonsense questions.
Examples:
·
"How high is 'up'?"
·
"What is the color if love?"
·
"What is east of the moon?
Note,
that these are indeed properly formed questions in the English language. They commit no grammatical mistakes in term
of being interrogative sentences. And
note further that they are non-empirical questions; no amount of empirical
investigation could hope to answer them.
However…
The
only person who would seriously ask such a question and hope for an answer is
someone who literally doesn’t know what he or she is talking about. (My four-year-old nephew.) However, in these cases, at least, it is easy
to see that they are nonsense questions because any and all answers are equally
silly.
EX:
·
Q: “What is the color of love?”
·
A: “Mauve.”
All
answers would be equally ridiculous.
Nonsense
Questions and Category Mistakes
These
non-empirical questions can be labeled “category mistakes.” One is asking to know the height of something
that does not belong to the category of “Things with a Height” or to know the
color of something which does not belong to the category of “Colored Things.” The questions themselves presume category
membership that does not in fact obtain.
Some
philosophers would claim that many/most/all questions which cannot be answered
by science are literally non-sense.
Example:
·
What is the meaning of life?
Some
have argued that far from being a deep and important philosophical question,
this is in fact a nonsense question. It
too is a “category mistake.” “Life,” they
argue, does not belong to the category of “things with a meaning.” Words do; signs do, symbols do. But not life.
The
view that most philosophy questions (or non-empirical questions in general) are
simply nonsense questions and involve category mistakes gained wide acceptance,
even among philosophers, in the first part of the 20th century and
some philosophers hold this view today. The
proper response to such questions is not try to answer them, but rather to
explain why the questions is simply nonsense.
(I
am not one of these philosopher, for the record.)
However
this is NOT the traditional view within the discipline of philosophy. Traditionally, philosophy seeks to answer
non-empirical questions which are taken to be both meaningful and important and
which can and do admit of answers, some of which are better, more reasonable,
than others.
Example:
“Is there a God?”
Note
that, unlike obviously non-sense questions for which all answers are equally
ridiculous, the problem here seems to be there are TWO possible, perfectly meaningful
answers: “Yes” and “No.” What remains to
be seen is which, if either, of the perfectly sensible possible answers is true
(or can garner greater rational support).
Rhetorical
Questions
A
rhetorical question is a device used to persuade or subtly influence the
audience. It's a question asked not for the answer, but for the effect.
Oftentimes, a rhetorical question is used to emphasize a point or just to get
the audience thinking.
“Are
you stupid?”
“It’s
too hot today, isn’t it?“
Notice,
while these are technically question, according to the grammar, but they are
not genuine questions in the sense that an answer is not expected.
These
rhetorical questions are often asked to emphasize a point:
·
Is the pope Catholic?
·
Is rain wet?
·
You didn't think I would say yes to that, did you?
·
Do you want to be a failure for the rest of your life?
·
Does a bear poop in the woods?
·
Can fish swim?
·
Can birds fly?
·
Do dogs bark?
Writers
employ rhetorical questions for rhetorical effects, and we cannot easily
quantify the impact rendered by a rhetorical question. These are often employed in poetry and poetic
prose for literary affects.
JULIET:
” ’Tis but thy name that is my enemy.
Thou art thyself, though not a Montague.
What’s Montague? It is nor hand, nor foot,
Nor arm, nor face, nor any other part
Belonging to a man. O, be some other name!
What’s in a name? That which we call a rose
By any other name would smell as sweet.”
“If Winter comes, can Spring be far behind?”
Good
rhetorical questions can make hearers/ readers realize something that they
weren't previously aware of. They can
make them think and perhaps gain some insight. This alone will intrigue them
enough to keep reading. But this only
works if the rhetorical question is sharp and well crafted.
Rhetorical
Questions as Disguised Claims
However
what interests us the most here it when they are used to disguise
assertions. Recall the old debater’s
motto: “He who asserts much prove.” The idea is that, generally, the burden of
proof remains with the affirmative team.
If they are asserting “P” they are expected to prove “P.” And this is true in normal conversations/
exchanges as well where one individual is trying to persuade another. The person asserting is expected to support
the assertion. But one can sometimes use
a rhetorical question as a way of disguising a claim in such a way that it does
not immediately seem to need support or evidence. In fact, rhetorical questions can be crafted
in such a way to make the hearers believe they came to a conclusion themselves.
Therefore they can be a powerful rhetorical device used to persuade someone without providing reason to be persuaded.
For
instance, people don't like to be told what to do.
Let’s
say you want Randy to stop swearing in front of the children.
So
you tell him to stop:
You: "Randy please stop swearing in front of the
children."
Randy: "It's a free fuckin' country,"
However,
say instead you ask him the rhetorical question:
You: "Randy do you think swearing in front of the children is
the best thing to be doing?"
So, rather than simply asserting one’s point, one “leads” the
hearer to it. It feels more like a conversation and less like a lecture. Indeed, one may even convince the hearers
that they have come to this conclusion on their own.
Now had you merely boldly declared, “Swearing in front of the
children is the best thing to be doing.”
you may not be nearly convincing.
In fact, you may invite a challenge.
“How do you know?” Randy might
respond. In both cases you really are
making a claim. But when disguised as a
rhetorical questions, you may be able to slip the claim by without being
subject to critical review.
Consider:
·
Why would anyone buy anything else?
·
Have you ever met a more disgusting man?
·
Who in their right mind could support that proposal?
·
Does anyone really believe that America isn’t a racist country?
·
What could be better evidence for the failure of socialist models
of economic distribution than Venezuela?
Agreement to the presumed “answer” to the rhetorical question is
assented to by the hearer often because it is presented as required by “Common
Sense.” It is thought that a vast
consensus exists as to what the “right” answer within the “Universal Audience.” (This is related to Perelman &
Olbrecht-Tyteca’s “mind-adherence” concept.)
But of course this may not be true.
There may in fact be no such broad consensus and the claim disguised as
a question may well be controversial and in need of defense. This is why the critical thinker must be on
guard when confronted with a rhetorical question.
Complex
Questions
A complex question is a fallacy in
which the answer to a given question presupposes
a prior answer to a prior question. Also known as a loaded question, a trick question,
a leading question,
the fallacy of the false question, and the fallacy of many questions.
The
classic example of a complex question would be "Have you stopped beating
your wife?". Ralph Keyes has traced
this example back to a 1914 book of legal humor. Since
then, he says, it "has . . . become the standard allusion to any question
that can't be answered without self-incrimination" (I Love It When You Talk Retro, 2009).
Examples and Observations
"'Let's
talk about Glaucon. Where did you get the
poison you used on him?'
(Bruce Macbain, The Bull Slayer: A Plinius Secundus
Mystery. Poisoned Pen Press, 2013)
"He
was woken two hours later and presently a doctor examined him.
"'What drugs were you on?' he asked.
"Wilt stared at him blankly. 'I've never taken any drugs in my life,' he
muttered."
(Tom Sharpe, Wilt in Nowhere. Hutchinson, 2004)
The
Unjustified Presumption
"Plurium interrogationum, which translates as 'of many
questions,' is otherwise known as the fallacy of the complex question.
When several questions are combined into one, in such a way that a yes-or-no
answer is required, the person they are asked of has no chance to give separate
replies to each, and the fallacy of the complex question is committed...
·
Did the pollution you caused increase or decrease your profits?
·
Did your misleading claims result in you getting promoted?
·
Is your stupidity inborn?
·
Have you stopped beating your wife?
·
Did John ever give up his bad habits?
·
Are you still a heavy drinker?
All
of them contain an assumption that the concealed question has already been
answered affirmatively. It is this unjustified presumption which constitutes
the fallacy. In each of these questions
there lies an assumed answer to a previous (unasked) question. “Did John have bad habits?” is the unasked
question whose answer is assumed in question “Did John ever give up his bad
habits?”. We need to withhold any answer
to the complex question until this prior question has been resolved. In some instances of this fallacy,
considerable struggle may be necessary in order to liberate ourselves from the
misleading influence of a complex question.
"The complex question has to be broken into simpler ones; and
often the denial of the fact presumed invalidates the larger question
altogether."
(Madsen Pirie, How to Win Every Argument: The Use and
Abuse of Logic, 2nd ed. Bloomsbury, 2015)
"The
fallacy of complex question is the interrogative form
of the fallacy of begging the
question. Like the latter, it begs the question by assuming
the conclusion at
issue:
The serious consequences of complex questions can be appreciated by considering
these trick questions, which would be out of order in a court of law:
·
What did you use to wipe your fingerprints from the gun?
How long had you contemplated this robbery before you carried it out?
Although
not an argument as
such, a complex question involves an implicit argument. This argument is usually intended to trap the
respondent into acknowledging something that he or she might otherwise not want
to acknowledge.
Contrast Questions
and Range of Answers
Two
types of contrast in explananda
It
is now commonly accepted that most or all explanations involve contrasts (see,
for example, Van Fraassen 1980 [28]; Hitchcock 1996 [46], 1999 [47]; Woodward
2003 [142]; Lipton 2004 [72]). These contrasts appear in the form of a ‘rather
than’ clause in the explanatory request, sometimes explicitly, often
implicitly.
Thus,
Van Fraassen 1980 ([28], p. 127) gives us the example:
·
Why did Adam eat the apple?
He
then notes that this explanatory request remains ambiguous until we make
explicit the intended contrast class. For instance, the questioner might have
meant any of the following:
·
Why did Adam, rather than someone else?
(e.g. Sam or many or Satan)
·
Why did Adam eat the apple, rather than doing
something else with it? (e.g. bake it into a pie)
·
Why did Adam eat the apple, rather than any of the other
fruits? (e.g. the papaya)
What
counts as a satisfactory answer to the initial question depends on which of the
more explicit questions is meant. “Because Adam was hungry” may be a good
answer to the second but not toe the others.
This feature of contrast questions is key to understanding explanation
and more specifically what sort of explanation is being sought or would be
found satisfactory. Technically, we can
say (with Van Fraassen) that an explanandum
consists of a fact embedded in a contrast class, that is, a set of alternative
possibilities that did not come true. We
call these alternative possibilities the “foils” of the fact. Very roughly, giving an explanation is showing
what picked out the actual fact from among all the possibilities in the
contrast class. It may be thought that
not all explananda have a contrastive
form however.
While
it is often it is easier to answer an unambiguous contrast questions than to
explain an ambiguous one this is not always the case. If one know that an individual has a preference
for contemporary plays rather than historical ones, that fact can explain why
he went to see “Jumpers” last night rather than “Candied.” But that fact alone does not suffice to
explain why he went to see “Jumpers” un-contrasted with alternative, that
is, why he went to see it at all. Yet, sometimes
it can be the other way around. We can
explain why Jones contracted the flu without explaining or being able to
explain why Jones contracted the flu rather than Smith.
Here
the un-contrasted questions seems easier to answer than the contrasted one.
When
asking the questions “What explains the fatal car accident last night?” Or, “Why did the fatal accident occur last
night? We see that these are ambiguous questions. Until I establish what the contrast is, the
facts and attending foils, I do not know what is being asked.
A car
crash always involves the convergence of numerous factors. For example, it may have involved faulty
brakes, insufficient roadway grading, inadequate signage, and alcohol. Any and
all of these factors may have contributed to the crash, and to varying
degrees. The extent to which any one of
these can be call “the” cause of the accident will require different sort of
causal explanations and causal chain and conceptual resources. (e.g. breaks and
the chain of physical factors, alcohol and biological and perceptual; factors,
etc.) One way of giving content to the
idea that there are different kinds of causes and causal relations is to view causal
relations as explanatory ones, and to view explanations as answers to certain
kinds of questions.
Aristotle
defended an account of causation and explanation along these lines.
A cause (aitia), he said, was an
answer to the question dia ti: ‘Why?’
or ‘On account of what?’ (Physics 194b16-20). Bas van Fraassen has made
a similar claim: ‘An explanation’, he says, ‘is an answer to
a why-question’ (1980: 134). Others
have suggested that it is not just with regard to why-questions but also how-questions
since many how-questions are requests for explanation as well (Jaworski 2009).
Examining the presupposed logic of why- and how-questions can expose what the range
of explanatory factors and relations are being sought. Sometimes these presuppositions exclude
equally good and potentially preferable explanatory accounts.
A similar
point comes out with how-questions. ‘How did Judith kill Holofernes?’
Answer
A: ‘With a mixture of revulsion and determination.’
Answer
B: ‘With a mixture of bile and snake venom.’
Answer
C: ‘With a mixture of seduction and cunning.’
The
first answer supplies the manner; the second supplies the method, and the third
supplies the means. Manners, methods,
and means are among the things we ask about with how-questions. We also ask
about mechanisms. How-questions of mechanism request what some philosophers of
neuroscience call mechanistic explanations (Bechtel 2007). They explain how
a system is able to perform an activity by describing how the activities
of its subsystems contribute to it. So on this view causes and causal relations
are explanatory. By examining the range of ways we explain things in our
pedestrian dealings and in our scientific practices we can start compiling an
inventory of the kinds of causes and causal relations there are.