Enlightenment versus Romantic Thinking

Three Types of Political Theories

Modern Political Theory: Social Contract

Private Property

 

Enlightenment versus Romantic Thinking

 

You may already know that during the Enlightenment, there was unprecedented confidence in the ability of Reason, once it has been freed from all “irrational impediments” to solve any problem.  If only we could be “rational” and conquer our fears, our prejudices, our unreasoned emotional attachments to doctrines, our superstitions etc. there would be no problem we could not overcome.  There must be an rational explanation for whatever happens, and the wise “man of science” is committed to finding that explanation and using this knowledge to improve the human condition.  During this period, it was believed that what had impeded the progress of science and knowledge for the previous 1000 years or so was the lack of reason, or at least a sufficiently strong commitment to reason.  We had been too given to superstition, knowledge as received doctrine and blind faith.

 

For instance, Aristotle (384-322 BCE) had claimed that objects of differing weights fall at different rates of speed.  And this was taught thereafter for nearly two thousand years.  Do objects of differing weights fall at different rates of speed?  No.  Objects fall at the same rate of speed (when you account for wind resistance), but no one bothered to question that for nearly 2000 years!  Galileo (1564-1642  CE) did.  Legend has it that he dropped lead balls of different weights off the Leaning Tower of Pisa and discover the rate of free-fall is independent of weight.  The point is that the progress of knowledge had been impeded by unquestioned acceptance of Aristotle's (et alia) authority.  When we adopted this skeptical and critical mindset, we began to make comparatively swift progress where previously there was only stagnation.

 

Some of the important figures from the Enlightenment were champions of science and vocal critics of religion.  They tried to solve scientific, medical, navigational, commercial problems as well as moral, political, legal and even religious/theological problems by means of hyper-rational arguments and theories.  Even religion and theology would have to conform to rational modes of investigation and explanation.  Immanuel Kant (1724 - 1804) argues for Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and the rational necessity of God.  Gottfried Leibniz (1646 –1716) suggested that God’s existence can be demonstrated by the principle of sufficient reason.  But if argument fails to demonstrate the existence of God, or indeed, could demonstrate the nonexistence of God, then, continuing to believe was both irrational and immoral.  Doing so could only contribute to the gullibility of society, the very social ill responsible for so much lingering ignorance and unhappiness.  This was the theme of the French materialist philosopher Baron d'Holbach (1723 – - 1789) 1761 work Christianisme dévoilé ("Christianity Unveiled") in which he argued that Christianity and religion in general was an impediment to the advancement of humanity.  Enlightenment required jettisoning blind faith, it would seem.

 

But Enlightenment Thinking led to a starker, less friendly view of reality.  Instead of humans being the crowning glory of a magnificent creation fashioned by a good, loving, wise and powerful God, humanity was largely the accident and the universe was seen as slipshod draftsmanship at best by a third rate engineer, or perhaps, not the product of thoughtful creation at all.  The Earth was no longer seen as the mainstage on which the history of the entire cosmos was being played out, but rather an insignificant bit of dust in an insignificant corner of a really, really big place.  And it very much seems like what goes on in this little low-rent district of the cosmos matters to no one but us, and then only so long as we have the energy and memory to care.  Rather than looking forward to a blissful, eternal reward, where our every question is answered, our every illness healed, our sorrow comforted away, we have only to look forward to meaningless death and oblivion.

 

It don’t get no better than this.  How sad.

 

Little wonder that by the mid-1700’s Western Culture was looking for a change.  It had become disenchanted (so to speak) with Enlightenment thinking.  And it was followed by what is now known as “Romanticism.”  But what is at the heart of Romanticism?  The eerie warning “Beware, Reason does not, cannot reveal all!”  There are some things in this world that go beyond the ability of Reason to explain or even comprehend.  There is a “supra-rational” realm.  Think here of Blaise Pascal’s (1623-1662) perhaps anticipating Romanticism a bit, quote: : Le cœur a ses raisons que la raison ne connaît pas.”  And our only vehicle to this supra-rational realm, to commune with these items is through emotion, passion and imagination.

 

Consider two Paradigms of Horror:

 

Frankenstein:

 

Mary Shelly’s Frankenstein could not epitomize the Romantic Revolt against the Enlightenment more.  (And I think we are all familiar with revolting Romantics.) Dr. Frankenstein is a “Man of Science” unlike those backward ignorant villagers.  He knows that death is not something to fear.  How will we ever conquer it if we persist in our irrational superstitions and taboos against working with dead bodies, etc.?  Death is simply an engineering problem, and approached from that perspective, may well admit of a rational solution.  He has initial success, but then what?  His creation turns into an irrational monster which he cannot understand or control.  This product of science grabs him by the throat.

 

Robert Le Diable

 

Probably the best known Romantic Ballets are La Selphide and Giselle and some of what I’m going to say applies to them as well, however, less well know is that what is considered the first Romantic Ballet.  It was the dance sequence from the Opera Robert Le Diable, entitled the “Ballet of the Nuns.”  The scene was set at midnight in the ruins of an abandon convent which was haunted by nuns who had been unfaithful to the vows.  OOOOOooooo! 

 

Keep in mind that it was one of the first theatrical productions which was able to use the new gas lighting technology to good effect. This was one of the first times that an audience was able to enter a darken theater and see displayed before them simulated moonlight and all sort of fantastic images.  And consider the subtext.  The ruins of an abandon convent- a faith of a bygone era, desolate and crumbling- yet haunted.  And haunted by whom?  By those who had lost faith, pining after what was no longer attainable.

 

Perhaps the most fundamental presumption of Horror movies is the triumph of un-reason, the Romantic. The character who say, “Oh there has to be a rational explanation.” is sure to be knocked off by the monster in the next scene.  Or, if some how he does survive the coming cataclysm, he will NEVER say THAT again.  No it’s the old ones who

remember the old ways (or the ever present Olde Prophecy or Grimorie) or it’s the elfin-

children, unjaded and in touch with the Spiritual Realm, who have the best chance of telling us how to make it through to the final credits.

 

Three Types of Political Theories:

 

From where do governments derive their just right to govern?

 

Classical Political Theory

 

What typifies Classical Political Theory is that the purpose of government was to create a noble citizenry.  In the political theories of Plato and Aristotle, but even in the thinking of the Roman Empire, you find that the mission of government was cultivating and civilizing the citizens.  Since the mission of government is to form the character of the governed, the government has broad authority to regulate the lives of the governed.  Authority must be commensurate with responsibility, so if the government has the responsibility to see that people turn out ok, governments must therefore have the authority to tell people what to do.  This is a very paternalistic model of government.  Note further that evaluation of government (a good government/ a bad government) turns on the effectiveness that the government demonstrates in realizing its ends (functional account of good).

 

Now, it would be an overstatement to say this was universally accepted in in Classical times.  One can see the Sophocles play “Antigone” as examining/questioning the relationship between the individual and the State.

 

Medieval Political Theory

 

Typical of Medieval Political Theory is the notion that the Universe is a Divine Monarchy with God as the ultimate source of authority.  While we all must be obedient to God, there is a “chain of command” so to speak.  Throughout the middle ages there was a debate about who, precisely, was “second in command.”  The Roman Catholic Church maintained that it was the bishop of Rome, the Pope (although there were some disputes about this within the church).  So, for instance, it was Pope Leo III who crowned Charlemagne Holy Roman Emperor on Christmas Day, in the year 800.  This was a very public way of demonstrating that the Pope is the one bestowing the title, and the Pope is in the position to bestow this title because his authority comes directly from God.  (And what the Pope giveth, the Pope can taketh away.)  As the papacy's power grew during the Middle Ages, Popes and emperors came into conflict.  In one such conflict  Holy Roman Emperor Henry IV was excommunicated by Pope Gregory VII.  As a show of penance, the story goes, Henry stood in the snow outside the gates of the castle where the Pope was staying for three days begging the pope to rescind the excommunication. 

 

Now this was not just because Henry wanted to once again resume his membership within the Church.  Loyalty was assured in the Universal Chain of Command by oaths of allegiance.  But these oaths need not be honored to one who was not part of the Church.  Once excommunicated, no one who had sworn an oath to Henry needed to honor that (including oaths to pay taxes, crops, use of land, military support, etc.)  Excommunicated, Henry was politically weaken and vulnerable to challenge.

 

Later in the Middle Ages arose the idea of the Divine Right of Kings.  This theory claims that kings receive their authority directly from God.  The thinking here was that if God did want the King to be the King, He (God) could/would remove him.  The fact that the King is King itself is evidence that it is God’s will.  Therefore kings were answerable only to God and it was therefore sinful for their subjects to resist them. Further, this put the king on equal footing with the pope.  James VI / I (1566 – 1625) upheld the doctrine in his speeches and writings. This theory was supported by his son Charles I and his chief adviser, William Laud, the Archbishop of Canterbury. Laud argued that the king had been appointed by God and people who disagreed with him were bad Christians.

 

Modern Political Theory:/ Social Contract

 

By the time the Enlightenment was underway, supernatural explanations of political power and systems seem unreasonable and no longer tenable.  What was sought instead were rational, scientific explanations of the rise of government and their just right to govern.  In a way they turned the medieval pyramid of power upside down.  Rather than claiming authority came from the top down, modern political theory suggests that authority comes from the bottom up, that governments derive their just right to govern from the consent of the governed.  We will look in some detail at the theories of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke.  As you will see, the political theories presented by these two philosophers were extremely influential in the founding of the Unites States.

 

Three terms both of these theories use:

 

Natural Law:  Laws which hold whether a government exists or not.

 

Social Contract: An agreement among people to share certain interests and to make certain compromises for good of them all.  The result of this contract may be the formation and legitimizing of a governing political body.

 

State of Nature:  The real or imagined situation where you have a community of people, but there is no government.

 

Thomas Hobbes:

 

Hobbes wrote the classic Leviathan where he considers the question of government and its justification.  One way to figure out why we have a government is to try to imagine what life would be like without one.  Hence he proceeds to consider the “State of Nature.”

 

What life would be like in the State of Nature, where humans are “governed” by nothing other than Natural Law?  Note, we would have prefect liberty to whatever we wanted whenever we wanted without fear of government interference.  This may sound like a good thing, even desirable.  But Hobbes doesn’t think so.  On the contrary, he claims that our ruthless competition with one another to satisfy individual desires and establish our own security will quickly lead to what Hobbes calls "the war of each against all," a "state of nature" in which life is "nasty, brutish, and short."

 

Why is this so?  Well in the State of Nature humans will only be subject to Natural Law.  Predicting their behavior in the State of Nature then requires a working from a concepts of “Human Nature,” that is, the natural laws that govern human behavior and motivations. We cannot imagine how the “natural” human will act (or collective of humans acts) unless we have an understanding of human nature.  Hobbes provides this.  He was both a Ethical Egoist, and a Psychological Egoist.  The first is a moral view about what makes right actions right.  The second is a psychological theory about what motivates human actions.  According to Hobbes then, human beings are primarily self-interested and desire-driven.  We are compelled by our nature to do what we believe to be in our own best interest.  This is the one thing you can count on whether in or out of the State of Nature. 

 

 

 

 

But why should life be so contentious in the State of Nature?  Why can’t we all “just get along?”   Well the biggest threat to my security is the liberty of my fellow humans  (you).  Conversely, I am the biggest threat to your security.  My security can only be had if I neutralize you as a threat, that is, I can harm you, but you cannot harm me.  But if I ever achieved that, that would destroy your security.  So you work constantly to see that that doesn’t happen and you can always harm me (which effectively undermines my security).  According to Hobbes, people are not naturally capable of virtue and wisdom. Concepts of “Virtue,” Wisdom” or “Justice” are not “natural” and do not arise until one leaves the State of Nature.  They cannot arise when life is a “war of all against all” and a daily struggle for self-preservation.  We are “at war” with each other in very much the same way that the US and the old USSR were in an arms race during the Cold War.  Each was a threat to the other’s security.  Each sought to have “first strike” capability without fear of retaliation.  Had either side achieved this, however, the security of the other would evaporate.  Neither side did and the “war” went on for decades.

 

The Prisoners’ Dilemma:

 

Imagine the following scenario:

 

You and I commit some crime together.  The police do not have enough evidence to put either of us away for a very long time.  They really need to get at least one of us to confess.  So they devise a plan.  They keep us separated.  One officer comes to me with a deal.  She tells me that if I confess and you do not, I will get off scot free.  However, if I don’t confess and you do, I get 20 years.  If we BOTH confess, we will each get ten years.  (They don’t tell me this, but I know that if we both simply keep our mouths shut, we’ll each only get 6 months.)  Further, they tell me that they will be making the same deal with you.  I don’t know what you are going to do; I can’t talk to you, so I just have to guess.  Assuming I am rational and self-interested (as Hobbes supposes) what will I/ should I do?

 

Here a table of my options:

 

 

Things I cannot control

You confess.

You do not confess.

Things I can control

I confess.

I get 10 years

I get off with not time served

I do not confess.

I get 20 years

I get a 6 month sentence.

 

Well I’m gonna confess.  I have a shot at the best and I avoid the worst.  But of course, if you get the same deal, and you are just as rational and self-interested as I, you’ll do the same thing and the result is that we will both be going away for 10 years.

 

Now suppose the cops make a mistake.  Accidentally they allow us to sit together.  I quickly explain the deal I was offer and you tell me that you got the same deal.  “Well you know what we should do,” I say to you, “we should both keep our mouths shut.  I’ll promise you that I won’t confess if you promise not to confess as well.”  You agree and promise not to confess.

 

What should I do now?

 

CONFESS!

 

(and of course, so should you.)

 

This scenario is called The Prisoners' Dilemma.

 

The Prisoners' Dilemma: The hypothetical case used to illustrate Hobbes point that strictly pursuing one's own self-interest in an intelligent fashion results not in the best or even the second best possible situation.

 

It’s a dilemma because neither one of us is doing something stupid or irrational.  On the contrary, we are both acting rationally and pursuing our own best interests in an intelligent fashion.  Nevertheless I am not getting my best option or even my second best option, and neither are you.  People in the State of Nature are in the very same position, according to Hobbes.  They can’t escape the State of Nature simply by promising each other not to attack at the next opportunity.  The moment one of them lets his or her guard down the others would be compelled, by the law of human nature, to at advantage of the opportunity to attack.

 

Now, imagine our Prisoners’ Dilemma again, only this time we not only promise not to confess, but we contract a “promise-enforcer” and we tell this enforcer that he should kill either one of us if we defect from our agreement.  Both of us would have very good reason NOT to confess (the threat of death) and both of us would have the reasonable expectation that the other will also not confess.  Since it is in my best interest now to keep quiet I will, and so will you and we will have not the best option (0 time), but at least will get the second best (6 mons.)

 

Put another way, the best scenario for me would be for me to do whatever I want and get away with it and you can’t do anything about it.  But I can’t really have that so I am willing to compromise and reign in my behavior (no stealing, murdering, cheating, etc.) provided that everyone else to the same.[1]  And we hire an enforcer to make sure we all keep the social contract.  That’s the Sovereign.

 

This is how sovereign governments come to be and are justified, according to Hobbes.  We contract with one another to create a Sovereign enforcer who will enforce the “Social Contract.”  It will punish any who defect from the contract and fails to conform his or her behavior or threatens the security of fellow contractors.  Such a contract does not exist in paper. However, we are bound by it even if we never signed or saw such an agreement.  Living in society implies the acceptance of such contracts, its rules and obedience of its laws. Ignorance is not an excuse. Further, it is in my own best interest to support the Sovereign and the Social Contract since this is all the stands between me and the chaos of the State of Nature.  Anything I do to threaten or destabilize either is ultimately not in my own best interest.

 

The Social Contract, according to Hobbes, is an agreement of equal and self-interested  persons not to commit mutual murder.

 

Liberty:

 

By 'liberty' Hobbes means the absence of restraints or impediments on one's powers to act.  So in the State of Nature, where there is no government, the individual has “perfect liberty.”  Now initially that may seem like a good thing, even desirable, but Hobbes argues that in fact is not.

 

Hobbes points out that in the “State of Nature” where there is no government nor governmental censorship we have perfect liberty, but it is useless.  “Free Speech” only takes on value within a civil society.  Therefore if censorship is required to safeguard that free speech, it is justified.  From Hobbes’s perspective, we have nothing to complain about if the sovereign chooses to limit free speech, even to limit it severely.  We had all the free speech we could stand in the State of Nature, but it did us no good.  We give up our liberty and invest it in the Sovereign and the return on this investment is a civil society more secure and predicable than the State of Nature.  It is in our own best interest then (and thus required by natural law) that we support the stability of the civil society and accept the restrictions on individual liberty imposed by the Sovereign,  when, in its view, these restrictions are required to maintain order.

 

Revolution and defying the Sovereign would only be in our own best interest (and thus permitted/ justified by Natural Law) if life under the sovereign is worse that life in the State of Nature.  But life it the State of Nature, according to Hobbes, was SO terrible, that one can hardly imagine a scenario where life under the Sovereign is worse.  The only one that Hobbes can imagine is where the sovereign has commanded you to certain death.  (At least in the State of Nature you have a fighting chance.)

 

With regard to "justice" Thomas Hobbes believed that when and where there is no government there is no such thing as justice.  What we call justice is a creation of government.

 

For Hobbes, the proper role of government to provide security to the citizen and prevent them from committing mutual murder.

 

John Locke

 

John Locke also employs the notions of Natural Law, State of Nature and Social Contract, but his account is strikingly different from Hobbes.  For one thing, he disagrees with Hobbes’s Psychological Egoism.  He believe that in addition to self-interest, we are also motivated beneficence and the Common Good.  We are therefore naturally disposed to cooperate and collaborate with our fellow humans.  Further, we have a natural appreciation of our own rights and by extension, the rights of others.  So life in the State of Nature is not that bad.  This paints a picture of a civil orderly collective.  Why bother with forming a government then?  Well, while we have natural appreciation of rights and justice, we inevitably enter into disputes where our personal bias prevents us from seeing clearly what the just resolution would be.  We want the just resolution, but find it difficult to see what that it.  We need a neutral third party to resolve such disputes.  So the Social Contract then is the agreement that the governed negotiates with the Sovereign.  We invest our liberty in the Sovereign in return that Sovereign ensures justice and rights protection.

 

This is the role of government then: to secure the justice and protect the rights which we had a natural appreciation of in the State of Nature, but which we could only imperfectly achieve on our own.  By no means to we give up our liberty or rights upon entering into a Civil Society; indeed is for our rights protection that we create the government in the first place.  For Locke governments arise and are justified by the natural impulse of humans to live and work together for their mutual benefit and social development seeking to protect their own and one another rights and justice.

 

This is the dominant thinking behind the Declaration of Independence.  Consider the opening lines:

 

When in the Course of human events it becomes necessary for one people to dissolve the political bands which have connected them with another and to assume among the powers of the earth, the separate and equal station to which the Laws of Nature and of Nature's God entitle them, a decent respect to the opinions of mankind requires that they should declare the causes which impel them to the separation.

 

We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness.--That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed, --That whenever any Form of Government becomes destructive of these ends, it is the Right of the People to alter or to abolish it, and to institute new Government, laying its foundation on such principles and organizing its powers in such form, as to them shall seem most likely to effect their Safety and Happiness

 

Prudence, indeed, will dictate that Governments long established should not be changed for light and transient causes; and accordingly all experience hath shewn, that mankind are more disposed to suffer, while evils are sufferable, than to right themselves by abolishing the forms to which they are accustomed.

 

But when a long train of abuses and usurpations, pursuing invariably the same Object evinces a design to reduce them under absolute Despotism, it is their right, it is their duty, to throw off such Government, and to provide new Guards for their future security.--Such has been the patient sufferance of these Colonies; and such is now the necessity which constrains them to alter their former Systems of Government.

 

The history of the present King of Great Britain is a history of repeated injuries and usurpations, all having in direct object the establishment of an absolute Tyranny over these States. To prove this, let Facts be submitted to a candid world.

 

In other word, we were telling King George III, in the words of Donald Trump, “You’re fired!”  (But we will explain why we’re firing you.)  The rest of the Declaration reads like a legal indictment.  Rather than protect our rights and ensure justice, King George trampled our rights, according to The Declaration, thereby providing us with the justification to “dissolve the political bands” which tied us to him and set up another government (presumably one that will do a better job).

 

It is noteworthy that we see in Modern Political Theory the flow of political authority is reversed from that of Medieval Political Theory. Rather than flowing from the top down, it flows instead from the bottom up.  Executive authority is said to arise from the masses themselves.  This class captured succinctly in the following documentary:

 

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=rAaWvVFERVA

 

A final word about Private Property:

 

Most who defend the notion of private property being a right suggest that value is often created through work.  Since I have the "right" to self determination and to my body, I can do with it what I like (within certain limitations) and no one else has that right.  Likewise my labor is "mine" and the increased value created by my labor is mine.  I therefore have a right to that value and no one else does.  All this to say that defender of private property say that individuals have the right to determine what to do with their bodies, their labor and the fruits of their labor.  In short, I own what a make and I am free to keep it, sell it, trade it or give it away.  These are the free exchanges within the capitalist system

 

The Little Red Hen

 

 

However, note that Marx would critique this by pointing out that the factory owner is not the producer of the value, but rather the factory workers.  The owner of the factory can lay little claim on the value produced by the factory workers.  That value belongs mostly, if not entirely, to the laborers, Marx would claim.

 

Critics of Marx would claim that the owner invested risk capital for there to be a factory at all. They would also point out that the laborers negotiated to work for a agreed upon compensation package.

 

 

Adam Smith (1723-1790)

 

Smith seems to have agreed with David Hume that humans have a natural impulse to sympathy, and that helping one's fellow humans is inextricably bound to one's one happiness and success.  If so, then economic individualism (Capitalism) would naturally result in societal flourishing.  Smith wrote in The Theory of Moral Sentiments,

 

“How selfish soever man may be supposed, there are evidently some principles in his nature which interest him in the fortune of others and render their happiness necessary to him though he derives nothing from it except the pleasure of seeing it.”[2]

 

Accordingly, Smith approved of individual freely pursuing their “self-interest” since it was paradoxically "other directed."  Smith did not view compassion for others and individual self-interest as contradictory, but rather as complementary.

 

“Man has almost constant occasion for the help of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to expect it from their benevolence only,”[3]

 

Charity, government regulated and enforced or not, cannot sustain a vibrant and innovative economy or system of wealth distribution. Self-interested economic individualism (capitalism) can, he believed.  Said Smith:

 

“It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we can expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest” (ibid.).

 

 



[1] Interesting that Plato anticipates this line of argument in his Republic and argues against it.  The character Glaucon suggests that morality is only a social construction, a compromise because we can’t have what we really want (i.e. to do whatever we want whenever we want and get away with it.) But if ever we could avoid sanction there is nothing we would deem “immoral.”  He tells the story of the Myth of Gyges who discovers a magic ring that has the power to make him invisible.  While invisible he can do whatever he likes and avoid detection.  Even the gods don’t know what he’s doing when he is invisible.  (Remember the Greeks did not think their gods were omniscient or could read minds; they could only see what you were doing, assuming you were visible while doing it.)

 

Glaucon posits:

 

Suppose now that there were two such magic rings, and the just put on one of them and the unjust the other; no man can be imagined to be of such an iron nature that he would stand fast in justice. No man would keep his hands off what was not his own when he could safely take what he liked out of the market, or go into houses and lie with any one at his pleasure, or kill or release from prison whom he would, and in all respects be like a god among men. Then the actions of the just would be as the actions of the unjust; they would both come at last to the same point. And this we may truly affirm to be a great proof that a man is just, not willingly or because he thinks that justice is any good to him individually, but of necessity, for wherever anyone thinks that he can safely be unjust, there he is unjust. For all men believe in their hearts that injustice is far more profitable to the individual than justice, and he who argues as I have been supposing, will say that they are right. If you could imagine any one obtaining this power of becoming invisible, and never doing any wrong or touching what was another's, he would be thought by the lookers-on to be a most wretched idiot, although they would praise him to one another's faces, and keep up appearances with one another from a fear that they too might suffer injustice. — Plato's Republic, 360b-d (Jowett trans.)

[2] Smith 1759, part I, section I, chap. I, para. 1

[3] Wealth of Nations, Smith 1776, book I, chap. 2, para. 2;