Two Dogmas of Empiricism

 

The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and Reductionism

Quines goals

            Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact and truths which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience…One effect of abandoning them is…a blurring of the supposed boundary between speculative metaphysics and natural science. Another effect is a shift toward pragmatism.

 

         Negative: trashing the two dogmas of logical positivism

     the analytic/synthetic distinction

     reductionism 

         Positive: naturalizing philosophy

     Understanding ontology as a matter of pragmatic decision, comparable to the natural sciences

Quines plan

         Debunk the two central dogmas of Logical Positivism (Empiricism) using circularity arguments to show that we cant come up with an adequate non-question-begging account of analyticity is, so out go:

     The analytic/synthetic distinction

     Reductionism: the belief that each meaningful [factual] statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience.

         Naturalizing philosophy

     by blurring the supposed boundary between speculative metaphysics and natural science which reflects the distinction between analytic and synthetic sentences where

     the former are supposed to be the business of philosophy and the latter the business of the natural sciences.

 

 

The Circularity Arguments: Background for analyticity

 

Historical and Popular Understanding of Analyticity

·         A statement is analytic when it is true by virtue of meanings and independent of fact.

o   Kant: an analytic statement is one that attributes to its subject no more than is already conceptually contained in the subject.

·         Necessary and contingent propositions

o   (Leibniz: truth of reason vs. truths of fact)

·         A statement is necessary iff it is true at all possible worlds, i.e. it is not logically possible that it be false (Leibniz)

·         its denial is self-contradictory

·         A statement is contingent iff it is not necessary

 

Problems:

 

Kant’s definition

·         restricts the definition to sentences in subject-predicate form

·         and is metaphorical: what do we mean by “contained”?

 

Raises the questions:

What is “meaning”? What is synonomy (sameness of meaning)?

What are logical possibility and necessity?

What is self-contradiction?

And what on earth are “possible worlds”?

 

Analyticity as truth in virtue of meaning alone

         Proposal: a sentence is analytic iff true in virtue of meanings and independent of fact.

         Problem: What is MEANING?

         The meaning of an expression in the sense that interests us is not its reference or extension.

     The extension of a singular term is the object it names

     The extension of a general term, or predicate, is the set of objects of which the general term is true

The extensions of some predicates

 

Meanings (Intensions)

         Problem: Analyticity has to be understood in terms of meanings (intensions) rather than extensions of terms

         But what are these meanings/intensions anyway?

         Properties? Individual concepts or Fregean senses?

 

            Quine speaks: Once the theory of meaning is sharply separated from the theory of reference, it is a short step to recognizing as the business of a theory of meaning simply the synonomy of linguistic forms and the analyticity of statements; meanings themselves, as obscure intermediary entities, may well be abandoned.

         We dont need intentions (meaning)—providing we can give an account of synonomy and analyticity.  (Where these are seen as relations between sentences.)

 

Rephrasing away bad things

 

Alice and Betty are of the same height

     Surface grammar suggests that this attributes a 3-place relation to Alice, Betty and Height.

     But we can rephrase it as

 

Alice is exactly as tall as Betty

     What we really have is a 2-place relation between Alice and Betty

     Height has been exorcized!

      (i.e. we don’t need to account for some “thing” that each possesses.”)

 

The Exorcism: paraphrasing away intensions

 

            Bachelor and unmarried male have the same meaning.

     Surface grammar again suggest that this says theres a 3-place on bachelor, unmarried male and a Meaning.

     But we can rephrase as

            Bachelor and unmarried male are synonymous

     What we really have is a 2-place relation

     (i.e. we don’t need to account for some “thing” that each possesses.”

     Meanings (intensions) have been exorcized!

  Synonomy

         Synonomy rather than “sameness of meaning”

         Even if there are no such things as meanings we can make do with synonomy since we can rephrase away meanings in the way that we paraphrased away heights.

         BUT now we have another problem: what is synonomy?

         And we need synonomy to understand analyticity!

         The problem of analyticity confronts us anew.

 

Two types of analyticity

         Logical truths: If we suppose a prior inventory of logical particles, comprising no, un-, if, then, and, etc. then in general a logical truth is a statement which is true and remains true under all reinterpretations of its components other than the logical particles.

 

(1)    No unmarried man is married.

 

(no ~x is X) (Ax, Fx -> ~ (~F~x)

         The other kind of analyticity

 

(2) No bachelor is married.

         The second kind can only be turned into the first kind if we recognize bachelor and unmarried male are synonymous.

 

“The characteristic of such a statement is that it can be turned into a logical truth by putting synonyms for synonyms… But] we still lack a proper characterization of this second class of analytic statements…inasmuch as we have had in the above description to lean on a notion of synonomy which is no less in need of clarification than analyticity itself.

 

Knowing that swapping bachelor for unmarried man is a licensed swap requires knowing that the terms are synonymous. 

Therefore this cannot very well be a TEST is synonymy.

Definition

         There are those who find it soothing to say that the analytic statements of the second class reduce to those of the first class, the logical truths, by definition; bachelor, for example, is defined as unmarried man

         But what do we mean by definition?

         Every definition is either descriptive, i.e. lexicographical, or explicative or stipulative and none will do the job!

         Dilemma:

     Lexicographical and explicative definitions assume that we already understand synonomy: for them definition rests on synonymy rather than explaining it.

     Stipulative definitions only go for a narrow range of cases

 

Descriptive definitions

         Lexicographical (dictionary) definition

     Bachelor = unmarried male that never has been married

     But we can ask whether dictionary definitions are correct, i.e. whether they really capture synonymous terms.  Since this is an open question, lexicographical definitions cannot unpack the notion of synonymy.

 

Explication definition

 

         Explication (contextual definition):

     Appeals to pre-existing synonomies

         the purpose…is to improve upon the definiendum by refining or supplementing its meaning. But even explication…does rest nevertheless on other pre-existing synonomies…[T]he purpose of explication is to preserve the usage of these favored contexts while sharpening the usage of other contexts.

         So were back to synonomy--and no wiser!

 

Stipulative definition

         Example: definition of logical operators in terms of primitives

     Example: if p then q is defined as not-p or q

         These definitions aren’t arbitrary, but what fixes them depends on purposes in formulating artificial languages

         But all they can deliver is analyticity-in-L (e.g. In L, let A and B be related analytically.)

         So we cant appeal to truth by definition to understand analyticity.

 

Interchangeability

 

            A natural suggestion…is that the synonymy of two linguistic forms consists simply in their interchangeability in all contexts without change of truth value; interchangeability, in Leibnizs phrase, salva veritate.

         Can we understand synonomy as intersubstitutivity salve veritate (preserving truth value) so that, e.g.?

     On this view, bachelor and unmarried male are synonymous comes to

     For any sentence where bachelor occurs, unmarried male can be substituted and the truth value of the sentence will stay the same.

 

            The question remains whether interchangeability salve veritate…is a strong enough condition for synonymy, or whether…some non-synonymous expressions might be thus interchangeable.

 

(i.e. this might not be sufficient.)

         Even if necessary, it is not sufficient.

 

Cognitive Synonomy

         [W]e are not concerned here with synonymy in the sense of complete identity in psychological associations or poetic quality…We are concerned only with what may be called cognitive synonymy

     Compare to Freges remarks about senses vs. ideas

         What we need is an account of cognitive synonymy not presupposing analyticity

         Interchangeability salva veritate is meaningless until relativized to a language

 

Quine Presents a Dilemma for this Approach:

     Either the languages is extensional or rich and non-extentional

     In a purely extensional language non-synonymous terms are intersubstitutable salva veritate (hearted and kidneyed)

 

But to say that these sentences don’t mean the same thing requires know already know that the terms are not synonymous.

A language rich enough to block the intersubstitutability of non-synonymous terms presupposes an understanding of analyticity.

       (The morning star is the evening star is not an analytic statement.)

      (You have to know they are no synonymous I order to block the “right” ones.)

 

Extensional equivalence isnt synonomy

         “F and G are extensionally equivalent means that all and only Fs are Gs

         Fact:  All and only creatures with hearts are creatures with kidneys

         BUT creature with a heart and creature with kidneys arent cognitively synonymous

     Sam believes that fish are creatures with hearts – true

     Sam believes that fish are creatures with kidneys – false

         Sam understands the phrases creatures with hearts and creatures with kidneys, but knowing what these terms mean doesn’t help him here.

         Therefore, extensional equivalence doesn’tt capture the notion of cognitive synonomy - sameness of meaning—that we want.

Necessity

         OK.  But it is only a contingent fact that creatures with hearts and creatures with kidneys. Perhaps if we strengthened the requirement from contingent coextensive sets to necessarily coextensive sets it would work.

         (i.e. Necessarily all and only Fs are Gs does capture synonomy)

         This fixes the heart/kidney problem; it is not the case that necessarily all and only creatures with hearts are creatures with kidneys.

         It is the case that necessarily all and only bachelors are unmarried men.

         If Tom understands what bachelors and unmarried men means then he knows that Dick and Harry are bachelors if and only if he knows that Dick and Harry are unmarried men.

         So bachelors and unmarried men are cognitively synonymous

 

So far so good.

But… Quine claims we cant use necessarily

         But we could only know that Necessarily all and only Fs are Gs if we already know that “All and only Fs are Gs is an analytic truth.

         Remember: analyticity is what we were trying to explain but

     We tried to explain analyticity in terms of synonomy and then

     explained synonomy of Fs and Gs in terms of a sentence using necessarily

     But then it turned out that tacking necessarily in front of a sentence just said that that sentence was analytic!

         So an account of analyticity in terms of necessity is circular!

 

Intersubstitutivity is language relative!

         The richer the language the less intersubstitutivity we get

         Example: sentences of the form If p then q and ~p or q are interchangeable in the truth-functional language of propositional logic

     If today is Wednesday then its sunny

         But not in ordinary English where if p then q says more.

 

Extensional language

         Quines example of an extensional language is the language of predicate logic, but so is English minus terms like necessarily

         Any two predicates which agree extensionally (i.e., are true of the same objects) are interchangeable salve veritate in such a language.

         But consider creature with a heart and creature with a kidney which are extensionally equivalent.

         [I]nterchangeability salva veritate, if construed in relation to an extensional language is not a sufficient condition of cognitive synonymy in the sense needed for deriving analyticity.

 

A Richer Language

         Ordinary English, a richer language, includes words that can only be understood if we already understand what analyticity is

         Example: NECESSARILY

         Necessarily all and only bachelors are unmarried men just comes to “’All and only bachelors are unmarried men is analytic.

         If a language contains an intensional adverb necessarily…or other particles to the same effect, then interchangebility salva veitate in such a language does afford a sufficient condition of cognitive synonymy; but such a language is intelligible only if the notion of analyticity is already clearly understood in advance.

 

If this is true, they the whole discussion of “interchangeability” is a red herring/ waist of time.

 

Interchangeability wont do

         A language in which interchangeability is sufficient for synonomy must be richer than a purely extensional language.

         And the additional stuff will include words like necessarily which we cant understand unless we already understand analyticity

         Which is what we were trying to understand in the first place!

         The project is circular (but, sly question, are all circles vicious?)

 

Semantical Rules

 

         Quine is alluding to Carnaps project which we will largely ignore.

         The jist of his worry here is that appeal to semantical rules of a language, L, to explain analyticity only explains analyticity-in-L.

         But that doesnt explain analyticity for any other language or, what were after, the notion of analyticity as such.

END PART I (and the First Dogma)

 

            [A] boundary between analytic and synthetic statements simply has not been drawn. That there is such a distinction to be drawn at all is an unempirical dogma of empiricists, a metaphysical article of faith.

         We dont know what analyticity is because

         We still dont know what synonomy is

         Can we get at the idea of synonomy by appeal to the Verification Theory of meaning?

 

Verification Theory of Meaning & Reductionism

         The verification theory of meaning…is that the meaning of a statement is the method of empirically confirming or infirming it.  An analytic statement is that limiting case which is confirmed no matter what.

         Statement synonymy is said to be likeness of method of empirical confirmation or infirmation…[What] is the nature of the relationship between a statement and the experiences which contribute to or detract from its confirmation?...The most naïve view…is radical reductionism. Every meaningful statement is held to be translatable into a statement (true or false) about immediate experience.

         If this works we can understand both formal analyticity in terms of logical truth, and informal analyticity/cognitive synonymy in terms of likeness in verification/falsification conditions.

 

So, if the verification theory (of meaning) can be accepted as an adequate account of statement synonymy, the notion of analyticity is saved after all.”

         But for this to work the reduction process of synthetic statements to direct experiences has to be doable.

         Is it?  Fat chance.

Phenomenalism: an example of Reductionism

 

“Statement synonymy is said to be likeness of method of empirical confirmation or infirmation

       This raises the questions of what are these methods of empirical confirmation are.

       What, in other words, is the nature of the relationship between a statement and the experiences which contribute to or detract from its confirmation?

        

       “Locke and Hume held that every idea must either originate directly in sense experience or else be compounded of ideas thus originating…we might rephrase this doctrine in semantical jargon by saying that a term, to be significant at all, must be either a name of a sense datum or a compound of such names or an abbreviation of such a compound.

 

Two problems:

 

1.       Physical Substance does not name a datum or compound of data.

2.       This renders mysterious what “object” are.

 

The first thing that appears when we begin to analyze our common knowledge is that some of it is derivative and some of it is primitive…the immediate facts perceived by sight or touch or hearing do not need to be proved by argument…[but] what is actually given in sense is much less than most people would naturally suppose and…what at first sight seems to be given is really inferred[1].

 

·         Hume raise the specter of Phenomenalism as the only metaphysical position consistent with Empiricism and science. (Seems no objects as all.)

·         Mill (and on some interpretations Berkeley) understood physical objects as permanent possibilities of sensation.

·         Russell suggests theyre logical constructions out of objects of acquaintance—comparable to the average plumber

 

Objects of a kind, F, are said to be “logical constructions” out of objects of another kind, G, if the  facts about Fs reduce to facts about Gs, or everything said using the F vocabulary may be said in a more basic or fundamental way referring only to Gs

The Average Plumber is a logical construction.

       There is no such being as the Average Plumber over and above regular plumbers!

       The form of the sentence “the Average Plumber has 2.3 children” is misleading:  “the Average Plumber” does not refer to any individual.

       What we mean is that if we divide the number of plumbers’ children by the number of plumbers we get 2.3

·         Ayer reconstructs phenomenalism as the claim that talk about physical objects can be reduced to talk about experiences.

Verification Theory of Meaning and Synonymy

 

·         Russell's concept of definition Quine claims was an advance over the impossible term-by-term empiricism of Locke and Hume. The statement, rather than the term, came with Frege and Russell and to be recognized as the unit accountable to an empiricist critique.

 

·         More reasonably, and without yet exceeding the limits of what I have called radical reductionism, we may take full statements as our significant units -- thus demanding that our statements as wholes be translatable into sense-datum language, but not that they be translatable term by term.

 

·         Verificationists assume that each statement, taken in isolation from its fellows, can admit of confirmation or information at all.

 

·         Sentences are synonymous exactly the same experiences count for and against them.

 

·         A sentence is analytic if all experiences count for it--in effect, if no experiences count for or against.

 

Quine’s Holism

 

But Quine rejects the idea that one can understand the meaning of a sentence purely in terms of its verification conditions. Instead he offers a Holism

 

If we recognize with Pierce that the meaning of a sentence turns purely on what would count as evidence for its truth, and if we recognized with Duhem that theoretical sentences have their evidence not as a single sentences but only as larger blocks of theory, then the indeterminacy of translation of theoretical sentences (or, mutatiis nutandis, meaning holism) is the natural conclusion.

 

… Philosophers have rightly despaired of translating everything into observational and logico-mathematical terms. They have despaired of this even when they have not recognized, as the reason for this irreducibility, that the statements largely do not have their private bundles of empirical consequences.[2]

 

            Our statements about the external world face the tribunal of sense experience not individually but only as a corporate body. There is no firm distinction between a linguistic and factual component of the truth of any individual statement.

 

Quines Holism

Empiricism Without the Dogmas

 

·         Some statements are more entrenched in our corporate body of beliefs than others but all face the tribunal of experience together.

·         So no statements are purely linguistic (Analytic)

·         The unit of empirical significance is the whole of science

 

The Web of Belief

 

            The totality of our so-called knowledge or beliefs, from the most casual matters of geography and history to the profoundest laws of atomic physics or even of pure mathematics and logic, is a man-made fabric which impinges on experience only along the edges.

 

·         The field whose boundary conditions are experience

·         Every belief/ statement is, in principle, revisable--the difference between logical principles and empirical claims concerns the costs of revision

·         Physical objects then, are merely posits (like Homeric gods)

 

Ontology (again)

 

·         What we admit to our ontology is a matter of what we need for the best scientific theory

·          

·         Physical objects?

·         Sets? Sets of sets?

·         Brick houses on Elm street?

 

“Best” us understood as “problem solving.”

·         Protons?

·         Ids, egos and super egos?

·         Past lives?

 

 

Quines radical pragmatism

 

       “Now Carnap ["Empiricism, semantics, and ontology," Revue internationale de philosophie 4 (1950), 20-40.] has maintained10a that this is a question not of matters of fact but of choosing a convenient language form, a convenient conceptual scheme or framework for science. With this I agree, but only on the proviso that the same be conceded regarding scientific hypotheses generally. Carnap has recognized that he is able to preserve a double standard for ontological questions and scientific hypotheses only by assuming an absolute distinction between the analytic and the synthetic; and I need not say again that this is a distinction which I reject.”

 

·         Likewise, when it comes to ontology everything is negotiable: Ontological decisions are a matter of cost-benefit analysis reflecting on the needs of science--an extension of common sense.

·         This serves to blur the distinction between philosophy/metaphysics and science.  For both, it shifts questions of ontology in the direction of pragmatism

     The correct ontology is the one that best serves the purposes of the best science

     If science progresses so that the best science requires a different ontology then we adopt a different ontology.

 

My comment:

      If science progresses/evolves so that the best science requires a different ontology then we adopt a different ontology.

      These are importantly different concepts.  Strictly speaking there can be no progress since there doesn’t seem to be anything towards which we are “progressing” (or from which re are “regressing.”)

      Peirce talks about an “end of inquiry,” but it is hard to see how this isn’t just a poetic myth.

      If we get hit by an asteroid tomorrow, then the “end of inquiry is today.

 

 

 

The Naturalization of Philosophy

 

            Ontological questions…are on a par with questions of natural science…the issue over there being classes seems more a question of convenient conceptual scheme; the issue over there being centaurs, or brick houses on Elm Street, seems more a question of fact. But I have been urging that this difference is only one of degree, and that it turns upon our vaguely pragmatic inclination to adjust one strand of the fabric of science rather than another in accommodating some particular recalcitrant experience. Conservatism figures in such choices, and so does the quest for simplicity…Each man is given a scientific heritage plus a continuing barrage of sensory stimulation; and the considerations which guide him in warping his scientific heritage to fit his continuing sensory promptings are, where rational, pragmatic.



[1] Russell, Bertrand: The Problems of Philosophy, 1912

[2] Quine, Willard van Orman; Ontological Relativity and Other Essays 1969, pp.80-3