1. FROM The Problems of Philosophy [1]
In daily life, we assume as
certain many things which, on a closer scrutiny, are found to be so full of
apparent contradictions that only a great amount of thought enables us to know
what it is that we really may believe. In the search for certainty, it is
natural to begin with our present experiences, and in some sense, no doubt,
knowledge is to be derived from them. But any statement as to what it is that
our immediate experiences make us know is very likely to be wrong. It seems to
me that I am now sitting in a chair, at a table of a certain shape, on which I
see sheets of paper with writing or print. By turning my head I see out of the
window buildings and clouds and the sun. I believe that the sun is about ninety-three
million miles from the earth; that it is a hot globe many times bigger than the
earth; that, owing to the earth's rotation, it rises every morning, and will
continue to do so for an indefinite time in the future. I believe that, if any
other normal person comes into my room, he will see the same chairs and tables
and books and papers as I see, and that the table which I see is the same as
the table which I feel pressing against my arm. All this seems to be so evident
as to be hardly worth stating, except in answer to a man who doubts whether I
know anything. Yet all this may be reasonably doubted, and all of it requires
much careful discussion before we can be sure that we have stated it in a form
that is wholly true.
To make our difficulties
plain, let us concentrate attention on the table. To the eye it is oblong,
brown and shiny, to the touch it is smooth and cool and hard; when I tap it, it
gives out a wooden sound. Anyone else who sees and feels and hears the table
will agree with this description , so that it might seem as if no difficulty
would arise; but as soon as we try to be more precise our troubles begin.
Although I believe that the table is "really" of the same colour all over, the parts that reflect the light look much
brighter than the other parts, that, if I move, the parts that reflect the
light will be different, so that the apparent distribution of colours on the table will change. It follows that if
several people are looking at the table at the same moment, no two of them will
see exactly the same distribution of colours, because
no two can see it from exactly the same point of view, and any change in the
point of view makes some change in the way the light is reflected.
For most practical purposes
the differences are unimportant, but to the painter they are all-important: the
painter has to unlearn the habit of thinking that things seem to have the colour which common sense says they "really"
have, and to learn the habit of seeing things as they appear. Here we have
already the beginning of one of the distinctions that cause most trouble in
philosophy-the distinction between "appearance" and "reality:'
between what things seem to be and what they are. The painter wants to know what things seem to
be, the practical man and the philosopher want to know what they are; but the
philosopher's wish to know this is stronger than the practical man's, and is
more troubled by knowledge as to the difficulties of answering the question.
To return to the table. It is
evident from what we have found, that there is no colour
which preeminently appears to be the colour of the
table, or even of anyone particular part of the table--it appears to be of
different colours from different points of view, and
there is no reason for regarding some of these as more really its colour than others. And we know that even from a given
point of view the colour will seem different by
artificial light, or to a colour-blind man, or to a
man wearing blue spectacles, while in the dark there will be no colour at all, though to touch and hearing the table will
be unchanged. This colour is not something which is
inherent in the table, but something depending upon the table and the spectator
and the way the light falls on the table. When, in ordinary life, we speak of
the colour of the table, we only mean the sort of colour which it will seem to have to a normal spectator
from an ordinary point of view under usual conditions of light. But the other colours which appear under other conditions have just as
good a right to be considered real; and therefore, to avoid favouritism,
we are compelled to deny that, in itself, the table has anyone particular colour.
The same thing applies to the
texture. With the naked eye one can see the grain, but otherwise the table
looks smooth and even. If we looked at it through a microscope, we should see roughnesses and hills and valleys, and all sorts of
differences that are imperceptible to the naked eye. Which of these is the
"real" table? We are naturally tempted to say that what we see through
the microscope is more real, but that in turn would be changed by a still more
powerful microscope. If, then, we cannot trust what we see with the naked eye,
why should we trust what we see through a microscope? Thus, again, the
confidence in our sense with which we began deserts us.
The shape of the table is not
better. We are all in the habit of judging as to the "real" shapes of
things, and we do this so unreflectingly that we come to think we actually see
the real shapes. But, in fact, as we all have to learn if we try to draw, a
given thing looks different in shape from every different point of view. If our
table is "really" rectangular, it will look, from almost all points
of view, as if it had two acute angles and two obtuse angles. If opposite sides
are parallel, they will look as if they converged to a point away from the
spectator; if they are of equal
a table, because experience
has taught us to construct the "real" shape from the apparent shape,
and the "real" shape is what interests us as practical men. But the
"real" shape is not what we see; it is something inferred from what
we see. And what we see is constantly changing in shape as we move about the
room; so that here again the senses seem not to give us the truth about the table
itself, but only about the appearance of the table.
Similar difficulties arise
when we consider the sense of touch. It is true that the table always gives us
a sensation of hardness, and we feel that it resists pressure. But the
sensation we obtain depends upon how hard we press the table and also upon what
part of the body we press with; thus the various sensations due to various
pressures or various parts of the body cannot be supposed to reveal directly
any definite property of the table, but at most to be signs of some property,
which causes all the sensations, but is not actually apparent in any of them.
And the same applies still more obviously to the sounds which can be elicited
by rapping the table.
Thus it becomes evident that
the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately
experience by sight or touch or hearing. The real table, if there is one, is
not immediately known to us at all, but must be an inference from what is
immediately known. Hence, two very difficult questions at once arise; namely,
(1) Is there a real table at all? (2) If so, what sort of object can it be?
1. FROM Theatetus[2]
BY Plato
SOCRATES: But the question
you were asked, Theatetus, was not, what are the
objects of knowledge, nor yet how many sorts of knowledge there are. We did not
want to count them, but to find out what the thing itself-knowledge-is... .
Perception, you say, is knowledge?
THEATETUS: Yes.
SOCRATES: The account you
give of the nature of knowledge is not, by any means, to be despised. It is the
same that was given by Protagoras, though he stated it in a somewhat different
way. He says, you will remember, that "man is the measure of all
things-alike of the being of things that are and of the not-being of things
that are not." No doubt you have read that.
THEATETUS: Yes, often.
SOCRATES: He puts it in this
sort of way, doesn't he, that any given thing "is to me
such as it appears to me and
is to you such as it appears to you," you and I being men?
THEATETUS: Yes, that is how
he puts it.
SOCRATES: Well, what a wise
man says is not likely to be nonsense. So let us follow
his meaning. Sometimes, when
the same wind is blowing, one of us feels chilly,
the other does not, or one
may feel slightly chilly, the other quite cold.
THEATETUS: Certainly.
SOCRATES : Well, in that case
are we to say that the wind in itself is cold or not
cold? Or shall we agree with
Protagoras that it is cold to the one who feels chilly
and not to the other? ... [I]ndeed the doctrine is a remarkable one. It declares that
nothing is one thing just by
itself, nor can you rightly call it by one definite name, nor
even say it is of any
definite sort.
In this way, Socrates claims that the empiricist cannot have any
knowledge at all. He defends the rationalist's claim earlier in the dialogue:
SOCRATES: You do not suppose
a man can understand the name of a thing when
he does not know what the
thing is?
THEATETUS : Certainly not.
SOCRATES: Then, if he has no
idea of knowledge, "knowledge about shoes" conveys
nothing to him?
THEATETUS: No.
SOCRATES: "Cobblery" in fact, or the name of any other art has no
meaning for
anyone who has no conception
of knowledge.
2. FROM
"Meditation I"[3]
BY Rene Descartess
OF THE THINGS WHICH MAY BE BROUGHT WITHIN THE SPHERE OF THE
DOUBTFUL
… It is now some years since
I detected how many were the false beliefs that I had from my earliest youth
admitted as true, and how doubtful was everything I had since constructed on
this basis; and from that time I was convinced that I must once and for all
seriously undertake to rid myself of all the opinions which I had formerly
accepted, and commence to build anew from the foundation, if I wanted to
establish any firm and permanent structure in the sciences.
… Now for this object it is
not necessary that I should show that all of these are false-I shall perhaps
never arrive at this end. But inasmuch as reason already persuades me that I
ought no less carefully to withhold my assent from matters which are not
entirely certain and indubitable than from those which appear to me manifestly
to be false, if I am able to find in each one some reason to doubt, this will
suffice to justify my rejecting the whole. And for that end it will not be
requisite that I should examine each in particular, which would be an endless
undertaking; for owing to the fact that the destruction of the foundations of
necessity brings with it the downfall of the rest of the edifice, I shall only
in the first place attack those principles upon which all my former opinions
rested.
… All that up to the present
time I have accepted as most true and certain I have learned either from the
senses or through the senses; but it is sometimes proved to me that these
senses are deceptive, and it is wiser not to trust entirely to any thing by which we have once been deceived.
But it may be that although
the senses sometimes deceive us concerning things which are hardly perceptible,
or very far away, there are yet many others to be met with as to which we
cannot reasonably have any doubt, although we recognize them by their means.
For example, there is the fact that I am here, seated by the fire, attired in a
dressing gown, having this paper in my hands and other similar matters. And how
could I deny that these hands and this body are mine, were it not perhaps that
I compare myself to certain persons, devoid of sense, whose cerebella are so
troubled and clouded by the violent vapours of black
bile, that they constantly assure us that they think they are kings when they
are really quite poor, or that they are clothed in purple when they are really
without covering, or who imagine that they have an earthenware head or are
nothing but pumpkins or are made of glass. But they are mad, and I should not
be any the less insane were I to follow examples so extravagant.
… At the same time I must
remember that I am a man, and that consequently I am in the habit of sleeping,
and in my dreams representing to myself the same things or sometimes even less
probable things, than do those who are insane in their waking moments. How
often has it happened to me that in the night I dreamt that I found myself in
this particular place, that I was dressed and seated near the fire, whilst in
reality I was lying undressed in bed! At this moment it does indeed seem to me
that it is with eyes awake that I am looking at this paper; that this head
which I move is not asleep, that it is deliberately and of set purpose that I
extend my hand and perceive it; what happens in sleep does not appear so clear
nor so distinct as does all this. But in thinking over this I remind myself
that on many occasions I have in sleep been deceived by similar illusions, and
in dwelling carefully on this reflection I see so manifestly that there are no
certain indications by which we may clearly distinguish wakefulness from sleep
that I am lost in astonishment. And my astonishment is such that it is almost
capable of persuading me that I now dream.
…Arithmetic, Geometry and
other sciences of that kind which only treat of things that are very simple and
very general, without taking great trouble to ascertain whether they are
actually existent or not, contain some measure of certainty and an element of
the indubitable. For whether I am awake or asleep, two and three together
always form five, and the square can never have more than four sides, and it
does not seem possible that truths so clear and apparent can be suspected of
any falsity [or uncertainty]
…Nevertheless I have long had
fixed in my mind the belief that an all-powerful God existed by whom I have
been created such as I am. But how do I know that He has not brought it to pass
that there is no earth, no heaven, no extended body, no magnitude, no place,
and that nevertheless [I possess the perceptions of all these things and that]
they seem to me to exist just exactly as 1 now see them? And, besides, as I
sometimes imagine that others deceive themselves in the things which they think
they know best, how do I know that I am not deceived every time that I add two
and three, or count the sides of a square, or judge of things yet simpler, if
anything simpler can be imagined? But possibly God has not desired that I
should be thus deceived, for He is said to be supremely good. If, however, it
is contrary to His goodness to have made me such that I constantly deceive
myself, it would also appear to be contrary to His goodness to permit me to be
sometimes deceived, and nevertheless I cannot doubt that He does permit
this.
…Nevertheless I have long had
fixed in my mind the belief that an all-powerful God existed by whom I have
been created such as I am. But how do I know that He has not brought it to pass
that there is no earth, no heaven, no extended body, no magnitude, no place,
and that nevertheless [I possess the perceptions of all these things and that]
they seem to me to exist just exactly as 1 now see them? And, besides, as I
sometimes imagine that others deceive themselves in the things which they think
they know best, how do I know that I am not deceived every time that I add two
and three, or count the sides of a square, or judge of things yet simpler, if
anything simpler can be imagined? But possibly God has not desired that I
should be thus deceived, for He is said to be supremely good. If, however, it
is contrary to His goodness to have made me such that I constantly deceive
myself, it would also appear to be contrary to His goodness to permit me to be
sometimes deceived, and nevertheless I cannot doubt that He does permit
this.
…I shall then suppose, not
that God who is supremely good and the fountain of truth, but some evil genius
not less powerful than deceitful, has employed his whole energies in deceiving
me; I shall consider that the heavens, the earth, colours,
fIgures, sound, and all other external things are nought but the illusions and dreams of which this genius
has availed himself in order to lay traps for my credulity; I shall consider
myself as having no hands, no eyes, no flesh, no blood, nor any senses, yet
falsely believing myself to possess all these things; I shall remain
obstinately attached to this idea, and if by this means it is not in my power
to arrive at the knowledge of any truth, I may at least do what is in my power
[i .e., suspend my judgment], and with firm purpose avoid giving credence to
any false thing, or being imposed upon by this arch deceiver, however powerful
and deceptive he may be. But this task is a laborious one, and insensibly a
certain lassitude leads me into the course of my ordinary life. And just as a
captive who in sleep enjoys an imaginary liberty, when he begins to suspect
that this liberty is but a dream, fears to awaken, and conspires with these
agreeable illusions that the deception may be prolonged, so insensibly of my
own accord I fall back into my former opinions, and I dread awakening from this
slumber, lest the laborious wakefulness which would follow the tranquility of
this repose should have to be spent not in daylight, but in the excessive
darkness of the difficulties which have just been discussed.
3. FROM
"Meditation II" BY Rene Descartes[4]
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN
MIND;
AND THAT IT IS MORE EASILY
KNOWN THAN THE BODY The Meditation of yesterday filled my mind with so many
doubts that it is no longer in my power to forget them. And yet I do not see in
what manner I can resolve them; and, just as if I had all of a sudden fallen
into very deep water, I am so disconcerted that I can neither make certain of
setting my feet on the bottom, nor can I swim and so support myself on the
surface. I shall nevertheless make an effort and follow anew the same path as
that on which I yesterday entered, i.e. I shall proceed by setting aside all
that in which the least doubt could be supposed to exist, just as if I had discovered
that it was absolutely false; and I shall ever follow in this road until I have
met with something which is certain, or at least, if I can do nothing else,
until I have learned for certain that there is nothing in the world that is
certain. Archimedes, in order that he might draw the terrestrial globe out of
its place, and transport it elsewhere, demanded only that one point should be
fixed and immovable; in the same way I shall have the right to conceive high
hopes if I am happy enough to discover one thing only which is certain and
indubitable.
I suppose, then, that all the
things that I see are false; I persuade myself that nothing has ever existed of
all that my fallacious memory represents to me. I consider that I possess no
senses; I imagine that body, figure, extension, movement and place are but the
fictions of my mind. What, then, can be esteemed as true? Perhaps nothing at
all, unless that there is nothing in the world that is certain.
But how can I know there is
not something different from those things that I have just considered, of which
one cannot have the slightest doubt? Is there not some God, or some other being by whatever name we call it, who puts
these reflections into my mind? That is not necessary, for is it not possible
that I am capable of producing them myself? I myself, am I not at least
something? But I have already denied that I had senses and body. Yet I
hesitate, for what follows from that? Am I so dependent on body and senses that
I cannot exist without these? But I was persuaded that there was nothing in all
the world, that there was no heaven, no earth, that there were no minds, nor
any bodies; was I not then likewise persuaded that I did not exist? Not at all;
of a surety I myself did exist since I persuaded myself of something [or merely
because I thought of something]. But there is some deceiver or other, very
powerful and very cunning, who ever employs his
ingenuity in deceiving me. Then without doubt I exist also if he deceives me,
and let him deceive me as much as he will, he can never cause me to be nothing
so long as I think that I am something. So that after having reflected well and
carefully examined all things, we must come to the definite conclusion that
this proposition: I am, I exist, is necessarily true each time that I pronounce
it, or that I mentally conceive it.
4. FROM
"Meditation VI"[5]
BY Rene Descartes
Since He has given me a very
strong inclination to believe that these ideas (of trees, houses, etc.) arise
from corporeal objects, I do not see how he could be vindicated from the charge
of deceit, if in truth they proceeded from any other source, or were produced
by other causes than corporeal things? (For example, by the evil demon, or in
dreams.)
Therefore,
We cannot be deceived
[whether by the evil demon or whatever else] . ... I cannot doubt but that
there is in me a certain passive faculty of perception, that is, of receiving
and taking knowledge of the ideas of sensible things; but this would be useless
to me, if there did not also exist in me, or in some other thing, another
active faculty capable of forming and producing those ideas. But this active
faculty cannot be in me [in as far as I am but a thinking thing], seeing that
it does not presuppose thought, and also that those ideas are frequently
produced in my mind without my contributing to it in any way, and even
frequently contrary to my will. This faculty must therefore exist in some
substance different from me; in which all the objective reality of the ideas
that are produced by this faculty is contained formally or eminently, as I
before remarked: and this substance is either a body, that is to say, a
corporeal nature in which is contained formally [and in effect] all that is
objectively [and by representation] in those ideas; or it is God himself, or
some other creature, of a rank superior to body, in which the same is contained
eminently. But as God is no deceiver, it is manifest that he does not of
himself and immediately communicate those ideas to me, nor even by the
intervention of any creature in which their objective reality is not formally,
but only eminently, contained. For as he has given me no faculty whereby I can
discover this to be the case, but, on the contrary, a very strong inclination
to believe that those ideas arise from corporeal objects, I do not see how he
could be vindicated from the charge of deceit, ifin
truth they proceeded from any other source, or were produced by other causes
than corporeal things: and accordingly it must be concluded, that corporeal
objects exist. Nevertheless they are not perhaps exactly such as we perceive by
the senses, for their comprehension by the senses is, in many instances, very
obscure and confused; but it is at least necessary to admit that all which I
clearly and distinctly conceive as in them, that is, generally speaking, all
that is comprehended in the object of speculative geometry, really exists
external to me.
5. FROM An Essay Concerning Human Understanding[6]
~BY John Locke
1. The way shown how we come by any knowledge, sufficient to prove it not
innate. It is an established opinion among some men, that there are in the
understanding certain innate principles; some primary notions, characters, as
it were, stamped upon the mind of man which the soul receives in its very first
being, and brings into the world with it. It would be sufficient to convince
unprejudiced readers of the falseness of this supposition, if I should only
show (as I hope I shall in the following parts of this discourse) how men,
barely by the use of their natural faculties, may attain to all the knowledge
they have, without the help of any innate impressions, and may arrive at
certainty, without any such original notions or principles . .. .
2. General Assent the great Argument. There is nothing more commonly
taken for granted, than that there are certain principles, both speculative and
practical (for they speak of both), universally agreed upon by all mankind,
which therefore, they argue, must needs be constant impressions which the souls
of men receive in their first beings, and which they bring into the world with
them, as necessarily and really as they do any of their inherent faculties.
3. Universal Consent proves nothing innate. This argument, drawn from
universal consent, has this misfortune in it, that if it were true in matter of
fact that there were certain truths wherein all mankind agreed, it would not
prove them innate, if there can be any other way shown how men may come to that
universal agreement in the things they do consent in, which I presume may be
done.
4. "What is, is," and "it is impossible for the same Thing
to be and not to be," not universally assented to. But, which is
worse, this argument of universal consent, which is made use of to prove innate
principles, seems to me a demonstration that there are none such; because there
are none to which all mankind give an universal assent. I shall begin with the
speculative, and instance in those magnified principles of demonstration,
"Whatsoever is, is" and "It is impossible for the same thing to
be, and not to be"; which, of all others, I think, have the most allowed
title to innate. These have so settled a reputation of maxims universally
received that it will no doubt be thought strange if anyone should seem to
question it. But yet I take liberty to say that these propositions are so far
from having an universal assent that there are a great part of mankind to whom
they are not so much as known.
5. Not on the Mind naturally imprinted, because not known to Children,
Idiots, &.-For, first, it is evident that all children and idiots have
not the least apprehension or thought of them; and the want of that is enough
to destroy that universal assent which must needs be the necessary concomitant
of all innate truths: it seeming to me near a contradiction to say that there
are truths imprinted on the soul which it perceives or understands not;
imprinting, if it signify anything, being nothing else but the making certain
truths to be perceived. For to imprint anything on the mind without the mind's
perceiving it, seems to me hardly intelligible. If therefore children and
idiots have souls, have minds, with those impressions upon them, they must
unavoidably perceive them, and necessarily know and assent to these truths;
which since they do not, it is evident that there are no such impressions. For
if they are not notions naturally imprinted, how can they be innate, and if
they are notions imprinted, how can they be unknown? To say a notion is
imprinted on the mind, and yet at the same time to say that the mind is
ignorant of it, and never yet took notice of it, is to make this impression nothing.
No proposition can be said to be in the mind which it never yet knew, which it
was never yet conscious of.
…Let us suppose the mind to
be, as we say, a blank tablet (tabula rasa) of white paper, void of all
characters, without any ideas; how comes it to be furnished? Whence comes it by
that vast store, which the busy and boundless fancy of man has painted on it
with almost endless variety? Whence has it all the materials of reason and
knowledge? To this I answer in one word, from experience: in that all our
knowledge is founded, and from that it ultimately derives itself.
6. FROM New Essays on Human Understanding[7]
BY Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz
The question at issue is
whether the soul in itself is entirely empty, like the tablet upon which
nothing has yet been written (tabula rasa), as is the view of Aristotle and the
author of the Essay (Locke), and whether all that is traced on it comes solely
from the senses and from experience; or whether the soul contains originally
the principles of various notions and doctrines which external objects merely
awaken from time to time, as I believe, with Plato and even with the Schoolmen,
and with all those who take in this sense the passage of St. Paul (Romans,
2:15) where he remarks that the law of God is written in the heart .... From
this there arises another question, whether all truths depend on experience,
that is to say, on induction and examples, or whether there are some that have
some other basis. For if some events can be foreseen before any trial has been
made of them, it is clear that we must here contribute something of our own.
The senses, although necessary for all our actual knowledge, are not sufficient
to give us the whole of it, since the senses never give anything except
examples, that is to say, particular or individual truths. All examples which
confirm a general truth, however numerous they may be, are not enough to
establish the universal necessity of this same truth; for it does not follow
that what has happened will happen again in the same way.
It would seem 'that necessary
truths, such as are found in pure mathematics, and especially in arithmetic and
in geometry, must have principles the proof of which does not depend on
examples, nor, consequently, on the testimony of the senses, although without
the senses it would never have occurred to us to think of them. This ought to
be well recognised; Euclid has so well understood it
that he often demonstrates by reason what is obvious enough through experience
and by sensible images. Logic also, together with metaphysics and ethics, one
of which forms natural theology and the other natural jurisprudence, are full
of such truths; and consequently their proof can only come from internal
principles, which are called innate. It is true that we must not imagine that
these eternal laws of the reason can be read in the soul as in an open book, as
the edict of the praetor can be read in his album without difficulty or
research; but it is enough that they can be discovered in us by dint of
attention, for which opportunities are given by the senses. The success of
experiments serves also as confirmation of the reason, very much as proofs
serve in arithmetic for better avoiding error of reckoning when the reasoning
is long.
It seems that our able author
claims that there is nothing potential in us and nothing even of which we are
not at any time actually conscious; but he cannot mean this strictly, or his
opinion would be too paradoxical; for acquired habits and the contents of our
memory are not always consciously perceived and do not even always come to our
aid at need, although we often easily bring them back to mind on some slight
occasion which makes us remember them, just as we need only the beginning of a
song to remember the song. Also he modifies his assertion in other places by
saying that there is nothing in us of which we have not been at least formerly
conscious. But besides the fact that no one can be sure by reason alone how far
our past apperceptions, which we may have forgotten, may have gone, especially
in view of the Platonic doctrine of reminiscence, which, mythical as it is, is
not, in part at least, incompatible with bare reason; in addition to this, I
say, why is it necessary that everything should be acquired by us through the
perceptions of external things, and that nothing can be unearthed in ourselves?
Is our soul, then, such a blank that, besides the images borrowed from without,
it is nothing? . .. [T]here are a thousand indications that lead us to think
that there are at every moment numberless perceptions in us, but without
apperception and without reflections; that is to say, changes in the soul
itself of which we are not conscious, because the impressions are either too
slight and too numerous, or too even, so that they have nothing sufficient to
distinguish them one from the other; but, joined to others, they do not fail to
produce their effect and to make themselves felt at least confusedly in the
mass.
FROM
An Essay Concerning Human Understanding[8]
BY John Locke
1. Concerning the simple
ideas of Sensation, it is to be considered-that whatsoever is so constituted in
nature as to be able, by affecting our senses, to cause any perception in the
mind, doth thereby produce in the understanding a simple idea; which, whatever
be the external cause of it, when it comes to be taken notice of by our
discerning faculty, it is by the mind looked on and considered there to be a
real positive idea in the understanding, as much as any other whatsoever;
though, perhaps, the cause of it be but a privation of the subject.
2. Thus the ideas of heat and
cold, light and darkness, white and black, motion and rest, are equally clear
and positive ideas in the mind; though perhaps, some of the causes which
produce them are barely privations, in those subjects from whence our senses
derive those ideas. These the understanding, in its view of them, considers all
as distinct positive ideas, without taking notice ofthe
causes that produce them: which is an inquiry not belonging to the idea, as it
is in the understanding, but to the nature of the things existing without us.
These are two very different things, and carefully to be distinguished; it
being one thing to perceive and know the idea of white or black, and quite
another to examine what kind of particles they must be, and how ranged in the
superficies, to make any object appear white or black.
7. To discover the nature of
our ideas the better, and to discourse of them intelligibly, it will be
convenient to distinguish them as they are ideas or perceptions in our minds;
and as they are modifications oj matter in the bodies
that cause such perceptions in us: that so we may not think (as perhaps usually
is done) that they are exactly the images and resemblances of something
inherent in the subject; most of those of sensation being in the mind no more
the likeness of something existing without us, than the names that stand for
them are the likeness of our ideas, which yet upon hearing they are apt to
excite in us.
8. Whatsoever the mind
perceives in itself, or is the immediate object of perception, thought, or
understanding, that I call idea; and the power to produce any idea in our mind,
I call quality of the subject wherein that power is. Thus a snowball having the
power to produce in us the ideas of white, cold, and round-the power
[1] 2 Bertrand Russell. The Problems of Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1912.
[2] 4 Plato, from Theatetus, trans. F. M. Cornford, reprinted in The Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. Edith Hamilton and Hunlington Cairnes, Bollingen Series, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 19BO, p. 61.
[3] 5 Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy. in The Philosophical Works of Descartes. trans. Elizabeth S. Haldane and G. R. T. Ros s, 1911. Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge University Press.
[4] 6 Rene Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. Elizabeth S. Haldane and G. R. T. Ross, 1911. Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge University Press.
[5] Rene Descartes. Meditations on First Philosophy. in The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. Elizabeth S. Haldane and G. R. T. Ross. 1911. Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge University Press.
[6] John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. ed. A. C. Fraser, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894.
[7] "Leibniz's Rebuttal," from New Essays on Human Understanding. by Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz, trans. A. G. Langley. Reprinted by permission of Open Court Publishing Company, a division of Carus Publishing Company, Peru, IL. Copyright © 1949 by Open Court Publishing.
[8] John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. A. C. Fraser, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894.