FROM On Feminist
Knowledge
BY Elizabeth Grosz[1]
There is considerable
disagreement among feminists about which approach to take in questioning
philosophy's sexist, patriarchal and phallocentric assumptions. They are
divided over whether to accept philosophy on its own terms, to undertake a
revision of it in the light of feminist knowledges,
to abandon it or actively to undermine it. Radical feminists challenge
philosophy's orientation around oneness,
unity, or identity-one truth, one method, one reality, one logic, and so on.
Many have insisted that there are a plurality of perspectives and a
multiplicity of models on which philosophy could base itself. In their
endorsement of plurality and multiplicity, feminists such as Le Doeuff, Irgaray, and Lloyd are not,
however, committed to relativism. Relativism is the belief that there are no
absolute positions of judgment or
knowledge. There are many
positions, each of which is equally valid.
Relativism or pluralism implies the existence of frameworks and positions which
each have their own validity and standards; and the belief that none of these
positions is comprehensive or all-inclusive.
Pluralism and relativism
imply abandoning the right to criticize actively other positions, even those we
find offensive and disturbing-phallocentric or racist statements, for
example-and to accept them as having equal validity to our own positions. Radical
feminists instead aim to expand and multiply the criteria for what is considered
true, rational, or valid and to reject or condemn those they perceive to be discriminatory.
They insist on retaining the right to judge other positions, to criticize them,
and also to supersede them. Radical feminists are not absolutists nor
objectivists nor relativists nor subjectivists. They advocate a perspeclivism
which acknowledges other points of view but denies them equal value.
It is at this time impossible
to specify what a philosophy compatible with feminism would be like; given that
it does not exist as a definite body of texts, any definition or description
would be overly prescriptive. Nevertheless, some general tendencies can be
briefly outlined.
Among the features a feminist philosophy may
develop are the following.
(a) Instead of a commitment
to truth and objectivity, it can openly accept its own status (and that of all
discourses) as context-specific. It accepts its perspeclivism, that fact that all
discourses represent a point of view, have specific aims and objectives, often
not coinciding with those of their authors. Rather than seeing itself as
disinterested knowledge, it can openly avow its own political position: all
texts speak from or represent particular positions within power relations.
(b) Instead of regarding
philosophy as the unfolding of reason, a sure path of progress towards truth, a
feminist philosophy can accept itself as the product of a specific socio-economic
and textual-discursive history. Neither relativist nor subjectivist, it aims to
render these and other binary oppositions problematic. A feminist philosophy
defies modes of conventional evaluation. This is not, however, to claim that it
cannot be evaluated in any terms; simply that the criteria used must be
different. A theory's validity is not judged simply according to its adoption
of a fixed or pre-given form, but it may be judged according to its
intersubjective effects, that is, its capacity to be shared, understood, and
communicated by those occupying similar positions; and also by its intertextual effects, that is, its capacity to affirm or
undermine various prevailing or subordinated discursive systems, and the
effects it has on other discourses.
(c) Instead of separating the
subject and object of knowledge, a feminist philosophy may instead assert a
continuity or contiguity between them. The gulf necessary for objectivity is an
attempt to guarantee a knowing subject free of personal, social, political, and
moral interests (a Cartesian subject), unimplicated
in a social context, and uninfluenced by prior ideas and knowledges.
A feminist philosophy would need to reconceptualize
their interrelations so that reason and knowledge include history, context, and
specificity. A feminist philosophy could accept, as patriarchal discourses
cannot, that subjects occupying different positions may develop different types
of theory and have different investments in their relation to the object. Above
all, it can accept that all knowledge is sexualized, that it occupies a
sexually coded and structured position. However, the sexual position of the
text cannot be readily identified with the sexual identity of its author; a
female author, for example, does not in any way guarantee a feminine text.
(d) Instead of the
dichotomous, oppositional structure, which separates subject and object,
teacher and pupil, truth and falsity, etc., a feminist philosophy may regard
these terms as continuities or differences. Distinctions or oppositions imply
that two binary terms are mutually exclusive and exhaustive of the field; that
one term defines the other as its negative; that this other can have a place in
the binary structure; however, when terms are conceived as two among many
others, they are neither contradictory nor all-inclusive. If anything, the
relation of difference is based on contrariety not contradiction.
(e) Instead of aspiring to
the status of truth, a feminist philosophy prefers to see itself as a form of
strategy. Strategies are not abstractions, blueprints, or battle-plans for
future action. Rather, they involve a provisional commitment to goals and
ideals; a recognition of the prevailing situation, in opposition to which these
ideals are erected; and an expedient relation to terms, arguments, and
techniques which help transform the prevailing order into the ideal. To deny
that a feminist philosophy aspires to truth is not to claim it is content with
being regarded as false; rather, the opposition between truth and falsity is
largely irrelevant for a strategic model.
(f) Instead of dividing
theory from practice-so that practice is located chronologically before and after
theory (construed as either a plan or a post facto reflection, respectively)-a
feminist philosophy may regard theory as a form of practice, a textual,
conceptual, and educational practice, one involved in struggles for theoretical
ascendancy, where dominant and subordinated discourses battle with each other.
Theory is not privileged by its isolation from practice and its relegation to a
pure conceptual level. When it is seen as a material process, theory can be
seen as a practice like any other, neither more nor less privileged in its
ability to survey and assess other practices. As a material labour
or practice, theory relies on concepts, words, and discursive "raw
materials," processes of theoretical production (e.g. the form of
argument, narrative, or linguistic structure needed to make coherent
discourses) and a determined product (a text or theory). It is not
hierarchically privileged over other practices, reserving the right of judgement; rather it is itself capable of being assessed by
other practices.
(g) Instead of opposing
reason to its others, a feminist philosophy expands the concept of reason. It
has analyzed how reason as we know it is allied with masculinity and relegates
feminine attributes to a repressed or subordinated status. A feminist philosophy
would not reverse the relation between reason and its others, but would expand
reason so that its expelled others are now included. In beginning with women's
lived experiences in the production of knowledge it seeks a reason that is not
separated from experience but based upon it, that is not opposed to the body
but accepts it, not distinct from everyday life but cognisant
of it.
(h) Instead of accepting
dominant models of knowledge (with their logic, binary structure, desire for
precision and clarity) a feminist philosophy can accept its status as material,
textual, and institutional. As such, it can accept the provisional, not
eternal, status of its postulates. It aims for the production of new methods of
knowing, new forms of analysis, new modes of writing, new kinds of textual
objects, new texts. No one method, point of view, position for subjects and
objects is the norm or model for all philosophy.
FROM
On Feminist Epistemology
BY
Uma Narayan[2]
A fundamental thesis of
feminist epistemology is that our location in the world as women makes it
possible for us to perceive and understand different aspects of both the world
and human activities in ways that challenge the male bias of existing
perspectives. Feminist epistemology is a particular manifestation of the
general insight that the nature of women's experiences as individuals and as
social beings, our contributions to work, culture, knowledge, and our history
and political interests have been systematically ignored or misrepresented by mainstream
discourses in different areas.
Women have been often
excluded from prestigious areas of human activity (for example, politics or
science) and this has often made these activities seem clearly
"male." In areas
where women were not excluded
(for example, subsistence work), their contribution has been misrepresented as
secondary and inferior to that of men. Feminist epistemology sees mainstream
theories about various human enterprises, including mainstream theories about
human knowledge, as one-dimensional and deeply flawed because of the exclusion
and misrepresentation of women's contributions.
Feminist epistemology
suggests that integrating women's contribution into the domain of science and
knowledge will not constitute a mere adding of details; it will not merely
widen the canvas but result in a shift of perspective enabling us to see a very
different picture. The inclusion of women’s perspective will not merely amount
to women participating in greater numbers in the existing practice of science and
knowledge, but it will change the very nature of these activities and their
self-understanding.
It would be misleading to
suggest that feminist epistemology is a homogenous and cohesive enterprise. Its
practitioners differ both philosophically and politically in a number of
significant ways (Harding 1986). But an important theme on its agenda has been
to undermine the abstract, rationalistic, and universal image of the scientific
enterprise by using several different strategies. It has studied, for instance,
how contingent historical factors have colored both scientific theories and
practices and provided the (often sexist) metaphors in which scientists have
conceptualized their activity (Bordo 1986; Keller
1985; Harding and O'Barr 1987). It has tried to reintegrate
values and emotions into our account of our cognitive activities, arguing for
both the inevitability of their presence and the importance of the
contributions they are capable of making to our knowledge.... It has also
attacked various sets of dualisms characteristic of western philosophical
thinking-reason versus emotion, culture versus nature, universal versus
particular-in which the first of each set is identified with science,
rationality, and the masculine and the second is relegated to the
nonscientific, the nonrational, and the feminine.
At the most general level,
feminist epistemology resembles the efforts of many oppressed groups to reclaim
for themselves the value of their own experience. The writing of novels that
focused on working-class life in England or the lives of black people in the
United States shares a motivation similar to that of feminist epistemology-to
depict an experience different from the norm and to assert the value of this
difference.
In a similar manner, feminist
epistemology also resembles attempts by third-world writers and historians to
document the wealth and complexity of local economic and social structures that
existed prior to colonialism. These attempts are useful for their ability to
restore to colonized peoples a sense of the richness of their own history and
culture. These projects also mitigate the tendency of intellectuals in former
colonies who are westernized through their education to think that anything
western is necessarily better and more "progressive." In some cases,
such studies help to preserve the knowledge of many local arts, crafts, lore,
and techniques that were part of the former way of life before they are lost
not only to practice but even to memory.
These enterprises are
analogous to feminist epistemology's project of restoring to women a sense of
the richness of their history, to mitigate our tendency to see the
stereotypically "masculine" as better or more progressive, and to
preserve for posterity the contents of "feminine" areas of knowledge
and expertise-medical lore, knowledge associated with the practices of
childbirth and child rearing, traditionally feminine crafts, and so on.
Feminist epistemology, like these other enterprises, must attempt to balance
the assertion of the value of a different culture or experience against the
dangers of romanticizing it to the extent that the limitations and oppressions
it confers on its subjects are ignored.
I think that one of the most
interesting insights of feminist epistemology is the view that oppressed
groups, whether women, the poor, or racial minorities, may derive an
"epistemic advantage" from having knowledge of the practices of both
their own contexts and those of their oppressors. The practices of the dominant
groups (for instance, men) govern a society; the dominated group (for instance,
women) must acquire some fluency with these practices in order to survive in
that society.
There is no similar pressure
on members of the dominant group to acquire knowledge of the practices of the dominated
groups. For instance, colonized people had to learn the language and culture of
their colonizers. The colonizers seldom found it necessary to have more than a
sketchy acquaintance with the language and culture of the "natives. “Thus,
the oppressed are seen as having an "epistemic advantage" because
they can operate with two sets of practices and in two different contexts. This
advantage is thought to lead to critical insights because each framework
provides a critical perspective on the other.
I would like to balance this
account with a few comments about the "dark side," the disadvantages,
of being able to or of having to inhabit two mutually incompatible frameworks
that provide differing perspectives on social reality. I suspect that
nonwestern feminists, given the often complex and troublesome
interrelationships between the contexts they must inhabit, are less likely to
express unqualified enthusiasm about the benefits of straddling a multiplicity
of contexts. Mere access to two different and incompatible contexts is not a
guarantee that a critical stance on the part of an individual will result.
There are many ways in which she may deal with the situation .
First, the person may be
tempted to dichotomize her life and reserve the framework of a different
context for each part. The middle class of nonwestern countries supplies
numerous examples of people who are very westernized in public life but who
return to a very traditional lifestyle in the realm of the family. Women may
choose to live their public lives in a "male" mode, displaying
characteristics of aggressiveness, competition, and so on, while continuing to
play dependent and compliant roles in their private lives. The pressures of
jumping between two different lifestyles may be mitigated by justifications of
how each pattern of behavior is appropriate to its particular context and of
how it enables them to "get the best of both worlds."
Second, the individual may
try to reject the practices of her own context and try to be as much as possible
like members of the dominant group. Westernized intellectuals in the nonwestern
world often may almost lose knowledge of their own cultures and practices and
be ashamed of the little that they do still know. Women may try both to acquire
stereotypically male characteristics, like aggressiveness, and to expunge
stereotypically female characteristics, like emotionality. Or the individual
could try to reject entirely the framework of the dominant group and assert the
virtues of her own despite the risks of being marginalized from the power
structures of the society; consider, for example, women who seek a certain sort
of security in traditionally defined roles.
The choice to inhabit two
contexts critically is an alternative to these choices and, I would argue, a
more useful one. But the presence of alternative contexts does not by itself
guarantee that one of the other choices will not be made. Moreover, the
decision to inhabit two contexts critically, although it may lead to an
"epistemic advantage," is likely to exact a certain price. It may
lead to a sense of totally lacking roots or any space where one is at home in a
relaxed manner.
This sense of alienation may
be minimized if the critical straddling of two contexts is part of an ongoing
critical politics, due to the support of others and a deeper understanding of
what is going on.When it is not so rooted, it may
generate ambivalence, uncertainty, despair, and even madness, rather than more
positive critical emotions and attitudes. However such a person determines her
locus, there may be a sense of being an outsider in both contexts and a sense
of clumsiness or lack of fluency in both sets of practices. Consider this
simple linguistic example: most people who learn two different languages that
are associated with two very different cultures seldom acquire both with equal
fluency; they may find themselves devoid of vocabulary in one language for
certain contexts of life or be unable to match real objects with terms they
have acquired in their vocabulary. For instance, people from my sort of
background would know words in Indian languages for some spices, fruits, and
vegetables that they do not know in English. Similarly, they might be unable to
discuss "technical" subjects like economics or biology in their own
languages because they learned about these subjects and acquired their
technical vocabularies only in English.
The relation between the two
contexts the individual inhabits may not be simple or straightforward. The
individual subject is seldom in a position to carry out a perfect
"dialectical synthesis" that preserves all the advantages of both
contexts and transcends all their problems. There may be a number of different
"syntheses," each of which avoids a different subset of the problems
and preserves a different subset of the benefits.
No solution may be perfect or
even palatable to the agent confronted with a choice. For example, some Indian
feminists may find some western modes of dress (say trousers) either more
comfortable or more their "style" than some local modes of dress.
However, they may find that wearing the local mode of dress is less socially
troublesome, alienates them less from more traditional people they want to work
with, and so on. Either choice is bound to leave them partly frustrated in
their desires.
Feminist theory must be
temperate in the use it makes of this doctrine of"double
vision"-the claim that oppressed groups have an epistemic advantage and
access to greater critical conceptual space. Certain types and contexts of oppression
certainly may bear out the truth of this claim. Others certainly do not seem to
do so; and even if they do provide space for critical insights, they may also
rule out the possibility of actions subversive of the oppressive state of
affairs.
Certain kinds of oppressive
contexts, such as the contexts in which women of my grandmother's background
lived, rendered their subjects entirely devoid of skills required to function
as independent entities in the culture. Girls were married off barely past puberty,
trained for nothing beyond household tasks and the rearing of children, and
passed from economic dependency on their fathers to economic dependency on
their husbands to economic dependency on their sons in old age. Their
criticisms of their lot were articulated, ifat all,
in terms that precluded a desire for any radical change. They saw themselves
sometimes as personally unfortunate, but they did not locate the causes of
their misery in larger social arrangements.
I conclude by stressing that
the important insight incorporated in the doctrine of "double vision"
should not be reified into a metaphysics that serves as a substitute for
concrete social analysis. Furthermore, the alternative to "buying"
into an oppressive social system need not be a celebration of exclusion and the
mechanisms of marginalization. The thesis that oppression may bestow an
epistemic advantage should not tempt us in the direction of idealizing or
romanticizing oppression and blind us to its real material and psychic
deprivations.
[1] Elizabeth Grosz. "Philosophy" in Feminist Know/edge: Critique and Construct, ed. Sneja Gunew, London: Routledge, 1990.
[2] Uma Narayan, "The Project of Feminist Epistemology: Perspectives from a Non-Western Feminist," in Gender/Body/ Know/edge, ed. Alison M. Jaggar and Susan R. Bordo. Copyright © 1989 by Rutgers, The State University. Reprinted by permission of Rutgers University Press.