Social Hedonism/ Ulilitarianism
Social Hedonism/Utilitarianism
The Jeremy Bentham Version- Act-Utilitarianism
Intuitive Aspects of
Act Utilitarianism
Problems with Act-Utilitarianism (Practical and
Theoretical)
Problems with Act-Utilitarianism: Responses
John Stuart Mill’s
Version - Rule Utilitarianism
Rights to Personal
Autonomy: Mill Against Paternalism
<!doctype html public "-//w3c//dtd html 4.0
transitional//en">Social Hedonism/Utilitarianism
Note:
“Egoistic Hedonism” is considered unsatisfactory as a moral theory because it
explicitly rejects what many call the "Moral Point of View" – Moral action requires that one treats
others and oneself equally.
The Moral Point of View – Moral action requires that one
treat others (and their interests) and oneself (and one’s own interests)
equally.
Being moral is NOT merely being prudent (as Egoism implies), but to
(sometimes) sacrifice one’s own best interest for the welfare of another.
As a correction to Egoistic
Hedonism of Epicurus, other Philosophers (e.g. Bentham, Mill et al.) propose Social
Hedonism or “Utilitarianism,” the central tenant of which is the Principle of Utility.
Principle of Utility: An action is right if and only if
it results in the greatest good for the greatest number (of … people?).[1]
Note: there is a minor difference between Social Hedonism and
Utilitarianism. Specifically:
Utilitarianism:
An action is right if and only if it results in the greatest GOOD for the greatest
number (of people?). (Here “good” is not
specified and may include other things besides pleasure. English philosopher G. E. Moore (1873 – 1958)
was this sort of Utilitarian.)
Social Hedonism:
An action is right if and only if it results in the greatest pleasure for the greatest
number (of people?). (Here “good” is specified as pleasure. J. Bentham and J.S. Mill were this sort of
Utilitarian.)
Were you to go on to take another course, perhaps an upper
division course in ethics, this distinction might be important. But for our purposes, the only Utilitarians
we are going to be looking at are social hedonists. So, I will treat these
terms, utilitarianism and social hedonism, as synonymous for the purposes of
our class.
Morality requires that one value everyone’s welfare, not just
one’s own. Utilitarianism implies it may be morally necessary to
sacrifice one’s own self interest for the good of others in some circumstances.
Social Hedonism/Utilitarianism suggests a cost/benefits analysis where
pleasure/pain is the "coin of the realm.” The right course of action among
available alternatives is whichever one nets the greatest amount of pleasure.
Most famous advocates:
Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832)
John Stuart Mill (1806-1873)
The Jeremy Bentham Version-
Act-Utilitarianism
Imagine I have been invited over my neighbor’s for dinner this
weekend and I am trying to decide if I
ought to go or not. I consider that if I
go, she’s not a very good cook and her kids get on my nerves. On the other hand, there is a season of Star
Trek Voyager I’ve been wanting to binge watch. I could binge watch it if I stay home. I reason:
|
Person Affected by my action |
I go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
I do not go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
|
Me |
-2 |
+2 |
Now, an egoistic hedonist (Epicurus) would be done.
I only have to consider how much pleasure an action would bring me and
weigh it against alternative actions.
But the Utilitarian would say, wait, wait, wait, You can’t just consider yourself. You need to consider others affected as
well. I must therefore consider my
neighbor.
|
Person Affected by my action |
I go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
I do not go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
|
Me |
-2 |
+2 |
|
Neighbor |
+1 |
-1 |
Net
Value |
|
-1 |
+1 |
Ok. But look, I still
create more “net” pleasure by staying home and binge watching. (yeah!).
Therefore this is the moral thing to do (i.e. the right thing to do)
since this action results in the greatest (net) pleasure.
Ah… but there is also my wife to consider. She enjoys my neighbor’s company, if not her
cooking, and the thought of me lying around watching a silly science fiction T.V.
series for hours will annoy her so…
|
Person Affected by my action |
I go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
I do not go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
|
Me |
-2 |
+2 |
|
Neighbor |
+1 |
-1 |
|
My wife |
+1 |
-1 |
Net
Value |
|
0 |
0 |
Ok. But look now. I create no more “net” pleasure by staying
home than by going. Both actions are of
equivalent value and thus morally equal.
It does not matter which I choose.
Therefore, it is moral for me to do either since I am not creating any
more “pleasure” by going than I would by staying home. (So can you guess which one I’m going to do?)
Ah… but there are also those annoying children. For whatever reason, they enjoy having me
over. So the final tally looks like
this.
|
Person Affected by my action |
I go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
I do not go to Dinner at the Neighbor’s |
|
Me |
-2 |
+2 |
|
Neighbor |
+1 |
-1 |
|
My wife |
+1 |
-1 |
|
Neighbor’s Children |
+2 |
0 |
Net
Value |
|
+2 |
0 |
Thus “going” creates more pleasure than “not going.” I am morally compelled, by the principle of utility,
to go and eat my neighbor’s lousy food and put up with her annoying
children. While morality does not always
require I sacrifice my own happiness for the sake of others, there are
circumstances where it does, according to Utilitarianism.
Utilitarianism is, in one way, the most idealistic of all ethical
theories: it takes for granted that people will be motivated to work for the
general good.
This was the ethical theory which inspired the reform movements in
the newly industrialized countries of Europe during the nineteenth century.
Utilitarian thinking helped bring about and justify the welfare state. (Karl
Marx's political theory was a reaction to the same social inequities.) This is also the principle behind
decriminalizing “victimless crimes.” If
I am not hurting anyone by what I’m doing, what sense does it make to hurt/
punish me for it?
In law and legal reasoning this is known as the “Principle of Harm.”
Aspects of a Pleasure to Consider
Since SO much depends upon correctly estimating the magnitude of
the resulting pleasure, Bentham gives some pointers on what to consider.
1. Intensity:
The aspect of pleasure one is considering according to Bentham,
when one estimates how acute, extreme or potent the pleasure is. The more
intense, the greater its value all other things being equal.
2. Duration:
The aspect of pleasure one is considering according to Bentham,
when one estimates how long the pleasure lasts.
The longer it lasts, the greater its value all other things being equal.
3. Purity:
The aspect of pleasure one is considering according to Bentham,
when one estimates whether or not the pleasure is mixed with any aggravation.
The purer the pleasure, the greater its value all other things being equal.
4. Surety:
The aspect of pleasure one is considering according to Bentham,
when one estimates the risk involved in the pleasure. The more certain one is of the pleasure, the
greater its value all other things being equal.
5. Propinquity (Nearness):
The aspect of pleasure one is considering according to Bentham,
when one estimates whether the pleasure is close at hand or not. The more near
at hand the pleasure, the greater its value all other things being equal.
6. Fecundity:
The aspect of pleasure one is considering according to Bentham,
when one estimates whether or not the pleasure is likely to give rise to other,
further pleasures in the future. The more fecund the pleasure, the greater its
value all other things being equal.[i]
7. Scope:
The aspect of pleasure one is considering according to Bentham,
when one estimates how many others are affected by the action. The greater the
scope of the pleasure, the greater its value all other things being equal.
Note that each of these aspects of a pleasure that Bentham points
out has to do with quantity. In every
case the more pleasure the better, the less pleasure the lower the value. Indeed, Bentham was what's called a
quantitative hedonist. Between any two
pleasures if they differ in value it was only because they differed in
quantity. As we shall see, John Stuart
Mill was a qualitative hedonist suggesting that two pleasures can differ in
quality as well as in quantity. But we'll get to that later.
Certain Intuitive Aspects of Act
Utilitarianism
The idea of Utilitarianism does capture how we try to reason
morally at least sometimes:
Imagine that a physician gives a heart transplant to Annie instead
of Bill and tells us he did so because Annie is a 30 year-old single mother of
3 and their sole means of support while Bill is a 55 year-old bachelor.
He reasons that more good/happiness/pleasure is likely to come from giving the
heart to the younger patient with dependent children. Even if we ultimately
disagree with him, we can see his point. He is citing relevant moral
reasons.
By contrast if he had said, “Well of course I gave it to Annie
because I always go alphabetically.” that would strike us as weird and
irrelevant. The fact that Annie’s name comes first alphabetically is
morally irrelevant in a way that the amount of happiness that would result from
giving her the heart does not.
So pleasure/consequences do seem to play SOME role in moral
thinking. But... does it play EVERY role? Perhaps not.
Problems
with Act-Utilitarianism (Practical and Theoretical)
Practical
Problems:
Note: A Practical Problem is an objection to a theory which claims that
whether or not the theory is true, the theory is problematic because it can't
be used.
1. Estimating Values: (Seems impossible to put numbers on things
like family, health, reputation)
Here the objection is that we could never be so course as to
assign numbers to intangible human values of the sort as family, friends,
marriage, reputation, health or career.
But is we can’t assign numbers, we, literally, can’t do the math. We therefore cannot use the theory to guide
our actions (tell us what we ought to do).
2. Predicting Consequences:
This objection maintains that we cannot know the future consequences of
our actions, nor can we predict them with the needed accuracy or rapidity to
make all the moral decisions that confront us relentlessly. Therefore this theory cannot be used because
we cannot estimate resulting pleasures or pains.
Again, if we cannot know the consequences, we cannot use the
theory.
Theoretical
Problems:
Note: A Theoretical Problem is an objection to a theory which claims
that whether the theory can be used or not, the theory is problematic because
it isn't true (complete, accurate, etc.).
1. "Is X (e.g. murder, lying, cheating, stealing)
wrong?" Act-Utilitarianism can’t
say anything more than, “Depends.”
If slavery benefits more people than it harms it is moral.
This is not merely the position that “the ends justify the means.” In
that case, "means" matter, they are morally relevant, so much so that
they stand in need of justification. But according to Utilitarianism,
“means” don't matter at all. So, the morality of cheating, stealing, murdering,
all "depend" on the consequences in any particular situation,
according to this moral theory. Further, if two courses of action result
in the same amount of pleasure, but one requires theft, lying and murder while
the other did not, neither course of action would be morally preferable
according to Utilitarianism since it is only interested in “the bottom line.”
So if the two courses of action have the same pleasure outcome,
they are equivalent on Act-Utilitarian grounds even is one requires lying,
cheating and murder and the other does not.
Action A |
Action B |
Lies |
No Lies |
Cheating |
No Cheating |
Murder |
No Murder |
+10 |
+10 |
Courses of actions are
equivalent. |
2. Diametrically opposed to "rights."
Rights seem best to be understood as a check on Utilitarian
Advances. Notice that my “right to property” is another way of claiming that,
no matter what noble ends you have in mind (helping the poor, feeding the
hungry, educating children) you are morally prohibited from taking my
stuff without my permission. Likewise
with rights to life or liberty. Rights are thought to hold whether good
(immediate) consequences result or not, and in fact do the most work in
precisely those situations in which rights violations are an expedient means to
good consequences.
The theoretical objections above are meant to show that
Utilitarianism is counter-intuitive. Still, pointing out that a theory has
weird results is not the same thing as proving it false. Furthermore, it
can be said on Utilitarianism’s behalf that it is the job a moral theories to
correct mistaken intuitions.
Problems
with Act-Utilitarianism: Responses
To the Practical Problems:
Now the claim that we could never
assign numbers to such human intangibles such as career, reputation, health,
etc., is a weak objection when it's pointed out that we do precisely this in
civil court proceedings. Now this is not easy and it can be somewhat awkward.
But it's not as if the jury or judge are throwing darts at a board. Presumably
they take into account a number of factors to arrive at what would be
reasonable compensatory damages.
While it is true that I cannot
know with the far distant consequences of my actions are, I can be relatively
certain about the immediate consequences of my actions, at least in most cases.
Therefore, one might respond that I should be held responsible for the
consequences I could reasonably foresee whereas I need not be held responsible
for consequences I could not reasonably foresee.[2]
To Theoretical Problems:
1. Calling a theory weird is not a critical response.
2. Reform the Theory
John
Stuart Mill’s Version - Rule Utilitarianism:
John Stuart Mill attempts to refine Utilitarianism in a way that
deals with the aforementioned problems.
Mill accepts the idea that calculating every decision according to such
criteria is a practical impossibility on a day to day basis. What ethics needs to provide then, are
general action guiding rules. He uses
the logic of Utilitarianism to provide us with good, action guiding (moral)
rules.
Rule Utilitarianism: A moral theory which states that
a moral
rule is correct if and only if, following the moral rule, generally,
results in the greatest good for the greatest number. And an act is moral
if and only if it accords with a correct moral rule.
According to this view, the right act for a person to do is the
one which conforms to the (right) moral code of the community; the right code
for the community to adopt is the one which, when adhered to by all, will best
promote the general good.
Because of the practical limitations on pleasure assessment,
personal bias, efficiency and time constrains of moral decision making and
consequence predictions, etc., morality must be about general action-guiding
directives (rules of thumb- policies)
rather than individual act assessments.
Therefore the moral question cannot (for practical reasons) be
“What action in this particular case will produce the greatest pleasure?” but
rather “Generally, what actions produce the greatest pleasure?”
Rule-utilitarianism was devised to cope with cases in which it
appeared that applying the utilitarian standard directly to practical
situations would lead us to contradict the traditional code of morality which
enjoys strong intuitive support.
This version (Rule Utilitarianism) does address some of the
objections raised against Act Utilitarianism:
PO1: As we move to the
question of “General Good/ Happiness” the calculations can be more rough and
estimated.
PO2: Again, since we are no longer concerned with predicting individual
causal chains linked to individual actions, the business of
evaluating the utility of a policy is more manageable and less speculative.
(See marketing, economics, sociology, city engineering, etc.)
TO1: Mill has a means of
justifying such intuitive moral claims as “Lying is wrong.” “Cheating is
wrong.” “Murder is wrong.” etc. independently of knowing the individual
consequences of individual actions. In
this way, he could reasonably claim that his theory confirms our most basic
moral intuitions, rather than contradicts them.
Mill believe that Rule Utilitarianism yielded results that were in
conformity with Christian Ethics and traditional ethics generally.
TO2: Further, Rule Utilitarianism provided Mill with a way of
trying to justify rights, moral duties and a “Liberal Society.”
Note: It's obvious enough that a theory which attempts to base morality
on the general good must also answer the question about what the “good” is.
Rights to Personal Autonomy: Mill
Against Paternalism
Mill argues against Paternalism
in 'On
Liberty"
Paternalism: Refers to those laws or other
prohibitions imposed on persons which constitute a limit on an individual's
personal freedom for his or her own good.
Mill argues that the government (and society in general) should
stay out of an individual’s private (self-regarding) affairs. He acknowledges that we ought to encourage
character development, but not through punitive regulation. Mill is thus seen as an early proponent of a
“Liberal Society,” that is, a society where government stays out of our private
affairs as much as possible, (That government is best which governs least[3].) Government ought only limit our individual
freedom when our exercise of that freedom impinges on the freedom of another.
But note: The ONLY thing which justifies
the rights of the individual according to Mill, is Utility. That is, generally speaking, it is an
empirical fact that society or government micro-managing the private affairs of
individuals is a less efficient means to general happiness than letting people
pursue happiness privately unmolested by government.
However, if this is the ONLY
justification of rights, then in principle, should government develop more
efficient methods or regulating the private lives of citizens[4],
it would be justified in taking more intrusive action. Mill would have probably disapproved, even
under these circumstances. However, it is unclear what philosophical objections
his system would present.
According to Mill, our knowledge of moral values and moral
obligations is based upon experience, the experience of ordinary
people. This appeal to human desires and preferences, rather than to
Reason (Rational/ Moral Structure of the Universe) or Nature (teleology) or the
Will of God earned utilitarianism the reputation of being a "godless"
doctrine.
Mill departed from Bentham's doctrine that all pleasures were of equal
quality (Push Pin was as Good as Poetry) by saying that some
kinds of pleasure are intrinsically better than others.
Unlike Bentham who was a “Quantitative Hedonist” Mill was a
“Qualitative Hedonist.”
Quantitative Hedonist: one who holds that the only value
difference between two pleasures is amount. (Bentham)
Qualitative Hedonist: one who hold that two pleasures
of equal quantity may differ with respect to value based on their respective
qualities. (Mill)
Mill’s Utilitarianism was accused of being a “swinish doctrine”
since it only appeals to pleasure. Mill
counters that this would only be the case if we imagined humans capable only of
swinish pleasures. But humans can
experience more that those, and these latter are superior.
How can we know which pleasures are superior to which? Experience,
says Mill, specifically, by consulting the feelings and preferences of people
who have a wide experience of life.
“Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or almost all who
have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling
of moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure.”
Mill would urge us to acquiesce to the judgements of
“pleasure-assessors” to decide on the moral desirability of various
pleasures. Ask those who are familiar with both which they prefer.
Mill claims that experience demonstrates that Mental Pleasures are
judged more satisfying than mere Physical
Pleasures by those well acquainted with both. Thus, we have empirical
reason to believe that mental pleasures are of a superior quality (for humans
at least) than physical pleasures.
Thus, says Mill:
In both cases, the “dissatisfied” party is, nevertheless, enjoying
better qualities of pleasure and thus a better quality of life than the
intellectual inferior.
Note: This is termed “Mill’s Heresy because to claim that two pleasures
of equal quantity may nevertheless differ in value seems to presuppose a
standard of evaluation (a “good-making quality) other then
pleasure. Thus it seems to contradict Hedonism.
Note: He is stacking the deck since the only persons qualified to judge
on his terms are going to be those who have developed (distorted?) pleasure
tastes. This is why he is accused of being an elitist who sanctifies the
preferences of upper-middle class middle-aged European white men.
Further, this smacks of Aristotelian Virtue. The Happy Life
(meaning “State”) verses momentary satisfaction. I am unconvinced Mill
can defend this view on purely Hedonistic grounds.
One can devise examples which would have been embarrassing to
Mill, e.g., "Which is better, gay sex or straight sex?" The jurors would have to be persons who had
experienced both, and enjoyed both, if they were to be able to tell us which is
morally preferable.
[1] A former colleague of mine, Dr. Kenneth Henley, would always stress when teaching Utilitarianism that the Principle of Utility was largely a slogan that supporters of Jeremy Bentham popularized, but that Bentham never actually used. Further, as a principle it contains two unbounded variables which means it is imprecise. So, while the slogan does indeed convey the general idea, it does not survive close scrutiny. Greater precision is required and fortunately both Bentham and John Stuart Mill gave just such greater precision to their moral systems.
[2] This is by no means a problem free move on the part of the act utilitarian however because notice they have left the criterion of evaluating actions solely based on consequences and added a new criterion that is the intention of the moral agent.
[4] Think Brave New World here.
[i] One thinks of Wordsworth’s poem:
I wandered lonely as a cloud
That floats on high o'er vales and hills,
When all at once I saw a crowd,
A host, of golden daffodils;
Beside the lake, beneath the trees,
Fluttering and dancing in the breeze.
Continuous as the stars that shine
And twinkle on the milky way,
They stretched in never-ending line
Along the margin of a bay:
Ten thousand saw I at a glance,
Tossing their heads in sprightly dance.
The waves beside them danced; but they
Out-did the sparkling waves in glee:
A poet could not but be gay,
In such a jocund company:
I gazed—and gazed—but little thought
What
wealth the show to me had brought:
For
oft, when on my couch I lie
In
vacant or in pensive mood,
They
flash upon that inward eye
Which
is the bliss of solitude;
And
then my heart with pleasure fills,
And dances with the daffodils.