Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
Distinction between Theoretical (Pure) and
Practical Reason
Third Formulation and
Perfect and Imperfect Duties
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
Immanuel
Kant – Key concepts: The Categorical
Imperative
This
is Kant's term for the "Moral Law."
By this phrase he implies that moral duty is an obligation binding of
all moral agents without exception.
Formulations
of the CI:
The
formulations of the categorical imperative were not meant to be understood as
separate duties, but rather as different articulations of a single moral duty.
The categorical imperative.
1.
Always act in such a way that you could will that the maxim of your act become
a Universal Law.
This
is the requirement of Universalizablity
(everyone could act the same way).
2.
Always act in such a way that you treat Humanity, whether in your own person or
in the person of another as an end in itself and never merely as a means.
Requirement
of Human Dignity (Don't just use
people.)
3.
Always act in such a way that you are both legislator and legislated in the
kingdom of "Ends."
Requirement
of Reciprocity (Your action would be
considered fair from all perspectives.)
Note
: Kant is a systematic thinker, by which I mean
that his moral philosophy is an integral part of a coherent system of thought
and is interlaced with his metaphysics, his epistemology, aesthetics, philosophy
of religion, political philosophy, etc..
As such it is difficult to do justice to the rational
support Kant’s offers for the moral claims he makes without making reference to
the entire system of Kantian thought.
(If you are interested you might look as my notes on Kant’s Epistemology
and Metaphysics.) But, as this
is more detail then necessary for the present purposes, I will not include them
here. I begin from a certain “starting
points,” although Kant supplies reasoned defenses of each.
1. From
a moral perspective, (considered as a moral agent) we are all equal. No one is
privileged.
It almost immediately follows from this and the
principle of rationality that like must be regarded as like, that the same
moral duties and rights that apply to one apply to all moral agents.
2. The
consequences of our actions are morally
irrelevant.
The
only things for which a person can be held morally accountable are those things
which are under one’s own, direct control.
The consequences of our actions are NOT under our own control. Thus, we cannot be held morally responsible
for the consequences of our actions.
3.
However, our WILL is completely under our
own, direct control (usually, at least in healthy adults), thus our
will is the only basis for moral evaluation of our actions.
Thus,
Kant famously claims that “Nothing can possibly be conceived in the world, or
even out of it, which can be called good, without qualification, except a good
will.”[1]
This is not to say that there are not other good
things. It is only to say that they are
“qualified” goods (only instrumentally good).
People can have courage, resoluteness, etc.,
but not be good. In order for a person
to be morally good, one must have a good will.
A person can have various natural and social advantages (wealth, health,
intellect) or virtues (courage, discipline, friendliness) without being a good
person. Think, for instance, of the
healthy, wealthy, intelligent, courageous, disciplined and friendly murderer.
Distinction between Theoretical (Pure) and
Practical Reason
Like
Aristotle, Kant distinguishes between:
1.
Intellectual uses of reason (Pure or Theoretical Reason)
2.
Moral uses of reason (Practical Reason)
Unlike
Aristotle however, Kant claimed that moral behavior does not guarantee one will
attain happiness. Rather, Kant
claimed only that good will is indispensable for deserving happiness. For Kant, the connection between moral
conduct and happiness was not an empirical “is” correlation, (i.e. Moral people
are happy people.), but rather an a prior “ought”
correlation (i.e. Moral people ought
to be happy.). People deserve happiness
in proportion to their moral worth.)
This, incidentally, was one of his criticisms of Utilitarianism. While Utilitarianism argues that we should
maximize pleasure/ happiness for everyone, Kant argues we ought not seek to
maximize that happiness of those who will moral transgressions (e.g. murderers,
rapists, child abusers, etc.) Quite the
contrary. These deserve punishment, not
happiness.
But
for Kant, “Ought” implies “Can.” By this
Kant means the logical relation of “implication.” If the sentence, “He ought to
tell the truth.” is true, then the sentence, “He can tell the
truth. must also be true as well. It follows than if I am (morally) certain
that “He ought to tell the truth.” is true, I can be equally (morally) certain
that :He can tell the truth.” is true.
This
line of reasoning leads him to believe that morality requires:
1. Freewill
2. A Divine
Arbiter of Justice (God) and
3. An Afterlife
(An Immortal Soul- of some sort).
These
are metaphysical concepts, necessitated or presumed by practical reason, but
inaccessible to Pure Reason.
Notice
then that, if it is true that we ought to behave morally, then it
must also be true that we can behave morally and we must therefore
presume that human beings have free will. They are not constrained by the past,
but can, under normal circumstances, choose as they do (i.e. to act either
morally or immorally), but act freely. Free will seems to be presumed by any
ascription of moral obligation.
Likewise,
if it is the case that people ought to be rewarded proportional to their moral
worth then it must be the case that they can be rewarded proportional to their
moral worth. This, Kant thinks, requires a divine arbiter of justice or God. Again, his claim is the presumption of moral responsibility
is premised on the presumption of God or a divine arbiter of justice. And finally, if it is the case that we ought
to perfect our moral will, then it must be the case that we can perfect our
moral will. But this cannot take place
in a finite period of time. Therefore,
there must be an afterlife where we can continue to perfect our moral will. Again, his claim is that moral responsibility
presumes an afterlife or an immortal soul.
Note
that each of these is a metaphysical claim and Kant had famously argued that we
have no ability to know or even speculate about metaphysical reality using
theoretical reason. Indeed, theoretical
reason is limited to the jurisdiction of the realm of human experience alone
(i.e. the phenomenal realm).
Nevertheless, Kant claims that these metaphysical concepts are necessitated
and presumed by Practical Reason, despite being inaccessible to (Pure)
Theoretical Reason.
So,
if nothing can be said to be good without qualification except a “Good Will,”
then a lot seems to turn on the concept of “the good will” for Kant. But what is “the good will” for Kant? The good will is the will which acts from
freedom and respect for the moral law.
To
understand this, we must address three sub-questions:
What
is it to act freely?
1.
To do anything one wants?
No. Your
“wants” are assigned to you by nature.
Thus they are compelled by forces outside yourself (e.g. Nature, an
Addiction, a Tyrant, Hypnosis, etc.). Thus,
they are not freely chosen. While we may
often be free to choose to do what we want to do, we are not free to choose
what we want to do. If I could “choose”
my wants, then I would choose to want to exercise and eat healthy
food. As it happens, I want to lay
around the house and eat pasta in a cream sauce. When I act (merely) on these wants, I am
acting as a subjugated individual. I am
acting as I am commanded to act by nature and thus not acting freely.
2.
To live according to a law legislated by someone/ something else?
No. Clearly not, for the same reasons as
above.
3.
To live according to no law whatsoever?
No. This is not freedom, but only living a life
of random accident.
4.
To live by a law one gives oneself as a free being?
Ah, yes. This is to act freely and autonomously.
But
we must be careful here. For Kant, “oneself”
is not defined by those features given/ imposed on one by nature(What he terms
our “inclinations.”) The empirical
details of an individual (height, eye color, temperament, etc.) are assigned to
a person by nature, so none of these features can figure into the law one gives
oneself if it is to be a “free” law. The
law you FREELY give yourself cannot have its source in desire or emotion or any
other inclination. It must come strictly
from reason.
But
what would such a law look like? What is
this free law, the law freely chosen?
Well,
we know something about this law. The
Law I give myself as a free being would be EXACLTY THE SAME as the law you give
yourself as a free being (and is thus “categorical”). Remember, when acting freely and not from
personal inclinations, from the point of view of personal freedom, there are no
relevant differences among rational agents which would make one choose a law that
another agent would not.
But
the same can be said for the moral law.
From the moral point of view, where we are all equal, there are no
relevant differences among agents which would make one choose something the
other would not, nor are there moral duties, rights or privileges for one more
agent that did not extend to all moral agents.
When I’m wearing my “moral goggles” I can’t pick me out of a crowd. So what a freely will
for myself, is what I will for all.
Therefore,
I know myself to be following a “freely chosen” law when I follow a law that I
could will, not only for myself, but for all other moral agents. And I know that they too would will the same
law when willing freely.[2] Further, when I choose to conform my behavior
to the law because it is the universal free law, I am not only
acting in accord with the moral law, but I am acting out of respect for
the moral law.
This
is what would such a free law looks like, claims Kant. What is the free law? It turns out that the freely chosen law is
the Moral Law. (More on this in a bit.)
A
person whose behavior is governed by his or her inclinations, those desires and
appetites imposed by nature is a subjugated person and thus does not act
freely. For such an individual, behavior
is determined by the strength of the thing pushing or pulling and not by the
free agency of the individual at all.
But,
when one acts out of respect for the moral law, a law one freely chooses to obey
(it’s not like the law of gravity after all), a law one recognizes as a purely
rational agent, unsullied by inclinations, then one acts autonomously
(freely).
We
will get to the substance of the moral law as Kant sees it in a
bit. For now let think of the moral law
as something like this: Do the right
thing. With this proxy for the moral law
in place, let’s first consider the form of the moral law.
Now
was sort of “Law” is this moral law?
Kant
distinguishes two types of imperatives:
1.
Categorical: Applies to all in the
category without exception.
2.
Hypothetical: Applies only to some
under certain circumstances.
(“If X then do Y.” or more usually, “If you want x then do y. )
Note: Recall that an imperative is a command.
Hypothetical imperatives are commands that apply to some people, some times under certain circumstances. The imperative “Don’t smoke!” may look
categorical initially. But it is really
a prudential, hypothetical imperative of the form, “If you want to avoid lung
cancer, throat cancer, mouth cancer, emphysema, heart disease, and prematurely
wrinkled skin, then don’t smoke.” For
the individual who does not have these desired ends, this imperative simply
does not apply.
Hypothetical
Imperatives are either:
a.
pragmatic: imperatives of prudence
b.
technical: imperatives of skill
But
hypothetical imperatives are optional; they apply only to some people, some times under some circumstances (and not others). The imperative “Take General Bio 1 and
general Bio.” applies to those wanting to go to medical school. But not to those who don’t, let’s say. It is a pragmatic hypothetical imperative.
Morality,
by contrast, is NOT optional. All moral
agents are obligated to act morally all the time. Consider:
Who should do the right thing? Everyone.
When should they do the right thing? Always.
Where should they do the right thing? Everywhere.
Thus,
morality (the Moral Law) is a Categorical Imperative. That is, it applies to all moral agents, at
all time, in all places, without exception.
Moral law is not a hypothetical imperative.
You (morally) ought to follow this
Categorical Imperative no matter what wants you might happen to have.
Hypothetical Imperatives are empirical, i.e.,
discovered through experience.
Categorical Imperatives are known a priori
according to Kant. They are discovered by means of practical reason, not by
experience.
Practical
reason gives its commands: purely, unconditionally, and categorically. (How?
Stay tuned.)
Note: This almost HAS to
follow from his claim that we are all equal from the moral point of view. Whatever moral duties apply to me apply to
everyone else and whatever apply to everyone else would apply to me. I’m not “special” such that special duties or
privileges apply to me alone.
So
for Kant, I must always do what duty requires of me and I must always refrain
from doing what duty forbids. Now, if
doing some act “y” is neither required nor forbidden by moral law, one does not
have to do it, but may if one wishes (morally permissible, but not obligatory.
Sometimes,
doing the right thing is also want we want to do for selfish or prudential
reasons. Suppose the moral law requires
us to do y. Suppose further that the
doing of y also gives us what we want, viz., x, (If you want x then do y.). Then the consequent of our peculiar
Hypothetical Imperative (Do Y.) is identical with that of the Categorical
Imperative (Do Y.).
Such
cases, Kant would say, demonstrate that the moral worth of an action
depends on the motive behind the action and not the action in and of
itself. So one might ask “Did she do the
right thing?” Did her action conform to
the CI? That is one question. If the answer is yes, then yes, she did the
right thing.
But
more deeply, one might ask, did she do the right thing for the right
reasons? Did she act that way
because she was motivated to do her moral duty, irrespective to her wants? Only in that case can she be said to be acting
from respect for the moral law. Only
in that case did she not only do the right thing, her action also is said to
have moral
worth, according to Kant.
For
Kant, it is very hard, if not impossible to know what our motive is in doing
something, especially if our moral duty is also something we want to do. Nevertheless, there is an important moral
difference between doing the right thing for selfish gain, and doing the right
thing because one believed is to be one’s duty.
A person can act rightly, (in accord with the moral law), but, if the
act is motivated by selfish or emotional factors, the act has no moral worth. In such cases we cannot say the person acted
wrongly, neither can we say that the person acted in a morally admirable
way.
Consider
if one is forced to give money to charity, or if one donates money to a charity
merely to get one’s picture in the paper.
These would be actions in accord with the moral law, but
not done out of respect for the moral law. As such they lack moral worth. Neither would they be instances of “good
will.” We could not say that the person
acted wrongly, since the person did not violate the CI, nevertheless, there
were not examples of acts of free will nor of good will.
Note: Kant places a great
deal of stress on the intention behind the action,
something completely overlooked by consequentialist ethics with their focus on
“the bottom line.”
Kant Posits a Moral
Duty:
Necessity to act from respect for the moral law.
Respect for the Moral
Law:
A person who has respect from the moral law is to be moved to act.
Respect for the moral law may motivate a
person to do what he otherwise would not choose to do and not to do what he
does want to do.
Thus
an act has moral worth (i.e., is
morally good) if and only if it:
1.
is in accordance with the moral law (right- morally permissible or obligatory);
2.
it is not performed merely from inclination, regardless of whether or not the
inclination be selfish or benevolent and;
3.
is performed from respect for the moral law.
The
shopkeeper who acts from a selfish reason when not cheating his customers acts prudentially,
not morally.
The
shopkeeper who acts from feeling of compassion in not cheating his customers
acts likewise cannot be said to act morally, because it is
motivated by personal emotion.
This
might strike us as strange initially, since many think that emotions (more
precisely sympathy and compassion) are precisely what ground and motivate moral
actions. (See David Hume.) But Kant denies this. Consider: What if the shopkeeper wasn’t
feeling particularly compassionate that day?
If the only reason she is acting morally is because a feeling, there
is no guarantee that she is moral or is interested in morality. Nor is it any sign that she acts rightly or
has considered the rightness of her act.
Many immoral things have been done and are done in the name of love and
compassion. (Think of the mother who
killed her five children to send them to heaven.)
So
An act is right if and only if it is in accord with the moral law
And
It has moral
worth if and only if done out of respect for the moral law. (This is so, regardless of the
consequences.)
The
Categorical Imperative: Kant's term for the "Moral
Law." By this phrase he implies
that it is an obligation binding of all moral agents without exception.
As
previously noted, this amounts to something like: “Do the right thing!”
But,
even if we are all in agreement that we should always do the right thing. the
question then becomes, how does one come to know WHAT the right
thing is in a given situation.
Kant
offers “formulations” of the Categorical Imperative to help us figure out what
our moral duty is. These are not meant
to be separate rule or duties, but rather different articulations of the single
universal moral command.
1.
Always act in such a way that you could will that the maxim of your act become
a Universal Law.
This
is the requirement of Universalizablity
(everyone could act the same way).
There
are two ways of understanding this requirement.
A.
The Kant-lite Way
This
is fairly intuitive. It’s like when your
mother would say to you, “What if everyone did that? You wouldn’t like that would you? Well then, you shouldn’t do it either.”
Again,
the idea here is that you not singularly special so that different rules apply to
you than do to everyone else. So, when
acting out of respect for the moral law or from “the moral point of view” you
see yourself as an equal among equals and will for yourself only those actions
you will others to do.
There
is some similarity here between this reading of Kant and “The Golden Rule,”
however, the Golden Rule is a call to active ministry. (i.e. DO unto others.) One could, arguably, satisfy the first
formulation by staying home and avoiding interacting with other people
altogether.
B.
The Logical Contradiction of Will Way
This
understanding of the First Formulation is a bit more technical. The idea here is not merely that you wouldn’t
want
the maxim of your action to be a universal law, but rather, whether you’d want
it or not, you could not will the maxim of you action a universal
law. That is, you could not even imagine
a society where this rule were the law that everyone obeyed. Universalizing certain maxims inevitably
leads to a contradiction of will.
Consider,
for example, lying.
You
might be tempted to lie on an occasion (say when you have an assignment due for
me, but neglected to complete it). You
might even imagine universalizing the action.
“Let everyone lie all the time.” you might think to yourself. Then you approach me and tell me with your
false story. (My dog ate my homework.)
But,
as were are now living in the society you willed, a society where
the rule is “Lie all the time.” I am undeceived because WE BOTH KNOW the rule
is “LIE.” We both know that you are
doing you best to deceive me. (It would
be like a case of stage magic; since I know it’s a trick, I’m not really deceived. I know he isn’t really cutting a lady in
half.)
Oddly
enough, in a society which universalizing lying, one can’t lie (i.e.
deceive). In order to lie, and to lie
effectively, that is, in order for the intentional telling of falsehoods to
deceive to have any practical value, the rule, understood and endorsed by
everyone, has to be “Don’t lie.” Both
parties to the lie, the liar and the victim, have to know that one ought to
tell the truth and one ought not lie. You
know this has to be the rule, in fact you need this to be the
rule, AS YOU ARE LYING. You are counting
on the rule being “Don’t Lie.” or else your gambit will be useless. You are counting on me thinking that you are
telling the truth.
So
note what the state of your mind must be.
“I will that no one lies.”
(Necessary for the lie to be possible at all and effective.) AND… “I will that someone lies
(me).” This is what Kant calls a “contradiction of will.” I suppose you are really willing something
like “I will that no one lies except me.”
But why “except you?” What makes you so special that special rules apply
to you and no one else? From a moral
point of view, absolutely nothing. Thus
your “exception” is irrational, since it stands counter to reason.
You
might also consider “cheating.” But if
that were universalized, then a 4.0 GPA would mean nothing. (Everyone
would have one and it would indicate nothing about skill or competence). So the whole point of cheating would vanish
in any society that universalized it.
The person cheating simultaneously wills “That no one cheats.” (so the
grades mean something in that society and cheating is effective) AND wills “That someone cheats.” (him).
The person cheating WILLS grades to
accurately reflect skills and abilities (or else his GPA would be worthless) AND
he WILLS that grades to NOT accurately reflect (his) skills and abilities.
There
again is the “contradiction of will.”
Note:
Morality, Freedom and Rationality:
Therefore, for Kant, moral action, done out
of respect for the moral law, IS the
most free (a law one freely chooses for oneself as a free being) action and the
most rational (free of logical or rational contradictions).
2.
Always act in such a way that you treat Humanity, whether in your own person or
in the person of another as an end in itself and never merely as a means.
The
“Anti-coercion” Principle or
Requirement of Human Dignity (Don't
just use people.)
According
to Kant there are two types of beings: persons
and things. Persons have infinite worth, while things
have finite worth and a price and can be bought or sold. The second formulation
of the Categorical Imperative is based on this distinction between persons and
things.
Like
Aristotle, Kant believe that our rationality was the most salient feature of
our nature. It was the source of our
autonomy and dignity. One is morally obligated to respect this dignity and
value in oneself and in others. It is
not the human body that gives human beings their dignity, but their rationality
and their status as rational free beings and moral agents.
We
have a duty to this humanity in ourselves
and others.
Kant
is not saying never treat another as a means; rather, never treat another human
merely as a means.
We
use other people differently or for
various purposes and this can be perfectly moral.
1. You are using me as a means toward earning 3
credits in philosophy (and perhaps as a means toward greater understanding of
philosophical issues).
2.
I am using you as a means to a paycheck (and perhaps as a means to greater
understanding of philosophical issues).
3.
You go to the store to buy something use the grocer as a means to a loaf of
bread while he uses you as a means to a dollar bill.
However,
if these are to be MORAL exchanges,
all parties must treat each other, not merely as objects of instrumental value
alone (things with finite value), but as objects of intrinsic value as
well. That is, we must recognize one
another as autonomous, rational beings capable of willing freely. We must not frustrate that freedom and
autonomy, but rather enhance it by allowing the other to make a free autonomous
choice. To frustrate that freedom
through coercion (force, threats of force, deception) is always immoral.
This
is what is meant by a “Free Exchange”
One
cannot/ does not will that one be treated as a thing. Thus, it is immoral to will that any other
moral agent be treated as a thing.
3.
Always act in such a way that you are both legislator and legislated in the
kingdom of "Ends."
Requirement
of Reciprocity (would be considered
fair from all perspectives).
This
formulation is a close echo of the first, but acknowledges the social and
systematic nature of the Moral Law. The Moral Law is a “systematic union of
different rational beings under common laws.”[3]
Imagine a society where we were blind to
the empirical differences among ourselves and others. Further, imagine that no one acted from inclinations
(accidental preferences placed upon individuals by nature or society), but
rather acted purely out of respect for the moral law. Notice, since all (morally irrelevant)
differences among agents have been neutralized with respect to their behavioral
consequences, everyone would act in the same ways and endorse the same moral
rules. Curiously, as with the first
formulation, ethics is at once subjective, universal and necessary.
An
action or principle that appeared moral from one vantage point in society (say
a rich person’s point of view) would appear moral from all vantage points in
society (say a poor person’s point of view) and vice versa. This is the thinking behind his talk of “The Kingdom of Ends.”
Well,
this imagined “kingdom” exists (albeit imperfectly) as our moral reality. We are ends who should be blind
to the morally irrelevant empirical details among agents and we ought to be
willing laws that are moral from all vantage points (once we adopt the
moral-point-of-view eyeglasses). So,
this is no mere thought experiment. If
Kant is correct, we are already living in the “Kingdom of
Ends” (albeit not perfectly) since we are moral agents who should be blind to
our inclinations and those of others passing universal laws by which we and
others are to live.
Third Formulation and
Perfect and Imperfect Duties
With
the first formulation you are asked to formulate a maxim that summarizes your
action and the reason for acting as you propose. You then imagine your maxim as
a universal law of nature governing all moral agents. You then consider whether a society operating
by that maxim is even conceivable. On
this formulation, suicide is ruled out immediately since we cannot even
conceive of a society where everyone commits suicide.
However,
what the third formulation asks you to consider is whether you would
will to live community so governed. Morality
requires that, by our actions, we will moral rules to stand alongside the
physical laws of nature to govern society.
People who belong to the kingdom of ends individually “legislate”
universal laws and are subject to those same laws. They thus are both legislators and legislated
within the Kingdom. (This is similar to John
Rawls’s original bargainers choosing principles of justice from “behind the
veil of ignorance.”) For an action to be
just, it must be rationally desirable from all perspectives in society. Notice, even the thief does not want things
stolen from him. And the rich person would
want someone to help him out if he were poor.
Thus, morally requires that we will only actions which would be
acceptable were “the shoe on the other foot,” so to speak.
If
your maxim fails the first formulation, you have a ‘perfect’ duty to avoid such behavior, admitting “of no exception in
favor of inclination.” You must refrain
from acting on it. Thus since lying
fails the first formulation and you have a perfect duty not to lie, to anyone.
Now,
if your maxim passes the first (you could envision such a society), but fails
the third formulation (you would not rationally will such a society), you have
an ‘imperfect’ duty requiring that you avoid that behavior.
Thus
you have an imperfect duty to give to charity, because while a society where no
one gives to charity may be conceivable, is it not rationally willable
from the point of view of reciprocity. The
reason this is called an imperfect duty is NOT to suggest you do not have a
duty to be charitable, according to Kant.
You do indeed. However, one is
not duty-bound to be charitable to each and every moral agent,
according to Kant, Now, to never
help others one is NOT acting as both legislator and legislated in the Kingdom of
Ends. You have a duty to be charitable,
to be sure, but whom to be charitable to and when is at the discretion of the
agent.
Let
us conclude our look at Kant’s ethics with his distinctions among duties,
rights and governmental intervention. Can
there be rights without duties? Not
according to Kant. But can there be
duties which do not correspond to right?
Yes, according to Kant. Kant
claims that the duty to charity is an imperfect duty and thus does NOT
correspond to any right held by moral agents.
For
Kant, duty is a central concept on morality. Not rights. Wherever there is a
right, there is a duty.
If
we cannot imagine our maxim as a universal law, then we have a perfect
duty not to perform the act that is covered by the maxim (and that
occasioned its formulation). On Kant's
example, we have a perfect duty never to make false promises. And this perfect duty corresponds to my right
not to be so deceived. Here the
government might very well have a justified role in protecting my rights if you
are trying to break a contract or, take my life, say.
If
we can conceive of our maxim as a universal law, but cannot will
that our maxim be a universal law for all rational beings (i.e. it passes the
first formulation, but not the third), then we have an imperfect duty to do the
opposite of the maxim. On Kant's
example, we have an imperfect duty to cultivate some of our talents some of the
time. Since we could not/ would not will
the maxim that says all should neglect their talents, we then have the
imperfect duty to do the opposite of neglecting our talents--which is
developing them. But as this is an
imperfect duty and not a perfect duty, I have more latitude in how I keep it. Which talents I develop and what degree left
my discretion. I am not duty bound to
become an opera singer rather than a brain surgeon. But to develop none of my prodigious talents
would be immoral.
Likewise,
the obligation to help others in need is an imperfect duty according to
Kant. It is an obligation that is
general and therefore grants no rights to any one person. To fail to help a person in need might be
wrong, but it is not unjust. Further, if
I donate to the United Way rather than to the Red Cross, I have not wronged the
Red Cross in any way. They simply are
not entitled to my charity.
If
so, then no one is entitled to help and none of their rights are violated is
they receive none. In this case, the use
of force through government taxation (coercion), for example, for purposes of wealth
redistribution may be seen as illegitimate, a confusion of two rather different
kinds of obligations. Charity is an
individual virtue and a private matter, according to Kant, not something to be
conducted with the coercive power of government.
[1] Kant, Immanuel Groundwork for the
Metaphysics of Morals p 5
[2] As we shall see, this is captured in Kant’s first formulation of the categorical imperative: Always act in such a way that you could will the maxim of your action an universal law.
[3] Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals By Immanuel Kant, H. J. Paton Page 100 Harper Perennial Modern Thought Edition 1964