LECTURE 2:
MEDIEVAL
PHILOSOPHY FLORIDA INTERNATIONAL UNIVERSITY
LECTURE NOTES
FROM
CLASSICAL TO MEDIEVAL
The transition from Greek
to medieval philosophy was a rather
rough one, and it exhibits a
love-hate relationship that Christian culture had with Greek civilization. On
the one hand, the new breed of philosophers was greatly influenced by Greek thought, particularly the views of Aristotle
and Plotinus. While Plato remained
a towering
figure, it was largely in name only since for many centuries copies of his writings virtually
vanished. In the absence of actual
books by Plato, medieval philosophers looked
to Plotinus for a summary of Plato's views, unaware of how original Plotinus's views were.
Thus, many of the most important
views that they attributed to Plato were those of Plotinus. On the other
hand, however, Christianity brought
with it a cultural and intellectual tradition from the land of Israel that was very much at odds with Greek ways of thinking.
At the heart of the difference was the Bible and its central themes
of a monotheistic God, life after death, and, perhaps
most importantly, the idea of furthering the kingdom of God. As Christian emperors took the throne, they took decisive
measures
to curb the influence of cultural institutions that conflicted
with the Christian
message. Orders were given to destroy all pagan
temples and shut down schools of philosophy that had been in operation
since the days of Plato and Aristotle. What we find within medieval philosophy, then, is an interesting blend of Greek and Christian
views to the degree
that thinkers of this period
were able to make
them compatible.
Historians mark off medieval civilization as starting with the downfall of the Roman Empire and ending with the founding of
the Renaissance-roughly from the years 400-1500. This range of time itself
falls into three distinct periods, each of which impacted developments within
medieval philosophy. The first period is the early middle ages, from around 400-1000. Often
called
the "Dark Ages", it is
characterized by tough times in the
aftermath of the Roman Empire's fall, including
localized
rule, decreased trade, mass migration, and feudalism. While
this timeframe witnessed the Christianization of Europe, Islam was also rapidly
enveloping the surrounding regions, and, as with Christianity, Muslims
developed their own philosophical tradition that mixed Greek philosophy with their own faith
tradition.
The next period is the high
middle ages, from 1,000 to 1300, which experienced much better times. Population
increased, countries and regions regained political cohesion, and intellectual thought was revitalized. Most important for philosophy, though, was the emergence
of medieval universities which
became centers of learning and gave birth to a distinct philosophical method
called scholasticism, which
systematically blended philosophy and theology. The final period is the late middle ages, lasting from 1300-1500. Times were again tough
with economic stagnation, wars, and the Black
Plague that killed around half of Europe's population. The unity of the Catholic
Church also came under fire, which helped bring the middle ages as a whole to
a close.
Four Issues
for Medieval Philosophers
1: The
relation between faith and reason
Throughout the middle ages, four specific
issues attracted the attention of its greatest philosophers from the Christian, Muslim and Jewish faith traditions. First is the relation between faith and reason, which
involves whether important philosophical and religious beliefs are grounded in the
authority of faith, or in
reason, or in some combination of the two. One of the most extreme proponents of the faith-only position is the early Church theologian Tertullian (155-230 CE), whose views are encapsulated in two vivid statements
that he makes.
First, he asks the
rhetorical question "What does Athens have to
do with Jerusalem?" Athens here symbolizes
reason and the tradition of Greek thinking; Jerusalem represents faith, and the
doctrines of Christianity that are held by faith. So, what, then does reason have to do with faith? His implied answer is "nothing at all!" His second famous
statement is "I believe
because it is absurd," which he wrote when discussing
a Christian doctrine about the
nature of Christ that went contrary
to logic. His point is that reason obstructs our discovery of truth so much that
we should expect truths of faith to run
contrary to it. Thus, reason
is not just a dead end in
the pursuit of truth, but it is
dangerously misleading. While
Tertullian may have been content with the faith-only
position, other philosophers held that reason could be an important
asset in demonstrating some religious truths that we also know through faith.
2:
Proving the Existence of God
A second issue of
interest for medieval philosophers was proving the existence
of God. Many medieval philosophers argued that, while we can certainly
believe in God on the grounds of faith alone,
there are rational proofs that we can also give to show God's existence. Chief among these is
a causal argument: motion and change
on earth trace back to a first cause, which is God. Several versions of this argument
were put forward, some with a particularly
high level of sophistication. Other
proofs for God's existence where also forthcoming, which used entirely
different strategies.
3.
Religious Language What Can We Say meaningfully Can We Say About God?
Third was the problem
of religious language. Even if we know
that God exists, can we say anything meaningful about him with human
language? We commonly describe God using words like "powerful" and "good", but all of these seem tainted by
our limited human experience. Should we give up describing God altogether? Should we reinterpret our descriptions of God in special ways? The solutions that
philosophers offered to this problem were both varied and original.
4.
The Problem of Universals
The fourth
issue is the problem of universals, namely whether concepts such
as "greenness" and "largeness" exist independently of human
thought. The particular tree in front of me is green and large. But there are lots of
other particular things that are also green or large, and thus in some sense share the more universal
attribute of greenness or largeness. The question,
then, is whether universals such as greenness
and largeness exist independently of
human thought in some external
reality, or whether they are just products of
the human mind.
Medieval
philosophers held every possible view on the subject, and in many ways the problem of universals represents medieval
philosophy at its best.
AUGUSTINE
Beauty and the Baptists: the significance for recovering a
theology of beauty
But this was
a long time coming. It was not commonly
believed that beauty was a matter of taste.
(Any more that truth and goodness were merely matters of
taste.)
St. Augustine
On Christian Doctrine
Begun in
about 396 and completed in 426.
Reflect not
only the early direction of the Christian Church, but the phenomenal influence
of Plato and Neo-Platonists
Considered to
have straddled the Ancient and Medieval Epocs
Book One
Two things
necessary to the treatment of the Scriptures
1. A way of
discovering those things which are to be understood.
2. A way of
teaching what we have learned.
Discovery:
·
great and
arduous work
·
difficult to
sustain
·
such a work
lies in Him (God)
Note all
things of value issue from the source of values not the Form of the Good in
this case, but rather God.
II
Makes the
distinction between signs and things.
III
Distinguishes
among:
things to be
enjoyed (make us blessed)
things to be
used (sustain us as we move toward blessedness)
things to be
enjoyed and used.
III
If we enjoy
(and cling to) those things which should be used, our course (to blessedness)
will be impeded and sometimes deflected.
shackled by
an inferior love
IV
To enjoy
something is to cling to it with love for its own sake.
To use
something, however, is to employ it in obtaining that which you love, provided
that it is worthy of love.
An illicit
use should be called rather a waste or an abuse.
IV
But if the amenities
of the journey and the motion of the vehicles itself delighted us, and we were
led to enjoy those things which we should use, we should not wish to end our
journey quickly, and, entangled in a perverse sweetness, we should be alienated
from our country, whose sweetness would make us, blessed
IV
Mortal life
must not become wandering from God
V
The (only)
things which are to be (genuinely) enjoyed are the Father, the Son, and the
Holy Spirit, a single Trinity, (a certain supreme thing common to all who enjoy
it)
VI
I feel that
I have done nothing but wish to speak
This is the
ineffable nature of the Divine.
But even
calling God ineffable is problematic, as Augustine points out, because your
effing.
This
contradiction is to be passed over in silence rather than re solved verbally.
XXXV
The end of
the Law and of all the sacred Scriptures is the love of a Being which is to be
enjoyed.
One might
add, this is true of all things to be used- Art. (Beauty?)
These next
three I put in just because I thought they show a more ecumenical side to
Augustine.
XXVI
Whoever,
therefore, thinks that he understands the divine Scriptures or any part of them
so that it does not build the double love of God and of our neighbor does not
understand it at all.
Whoever
finds a lesson there useful to the building of charity, even though he has not
said what the author may be shown to have intended in that place, has not been
deceived, nor is he lying in any way.
XXXVI
However, as
I began to explain, if he is deceived in an interpretation which builds up
charity, which is the end of the commandments, he is deceived in the same way
as a man who leaves a road by mistake but passes through a field to the same
place toward which the road itself leads. But he is to be corrected and shown
that it is more useful not to leave the road, lest the habit of deviating force
him to take a crossroad or a perverse way.
XXX
Indeed, if
faith staggers, charity itself languishes. And if anyone should fall from
faith, it follows that he falls also from charity, for a man cannot love that
which he does not believe to exist. On the other hand, a man who both believes
and loves, by doing well and by obeying the rules of good customs, may bring it
about that he may hope to arrive at that which he loves. Thus there are these
three things for which all knowledge and prophecy struggle: faith, hope, and
charity.
XXXVIII
Between
temporal and eternal things there is this difference: a temporal thing is loved
more before we have it, and it begins to grow worthless when we gain it, for it
does not satisfy the soul, whose true and certain rest is eternity; but the
eternal is more ardently loved when it is acquired than when it is merely
desired.
The first major medieval philosopher was
Augustine (354-430), who emphasized attaining knowledge through divine illumination and achieving moral goodness by loving
God. The details of his life are openly laid out
in his autobiography, titled Confessions,
which even today is considered a classic
of world literature. He was born in the
North African region of Tagaste to a devout Christian mother and pagan
father. For much of his youth, his middle-class parents' greatest concern was affording
a university education for him. Once having attained this difficult goal, learning rhetoric at Carthage,
Augustine's zeal for studying theology became
his driving force. But first came a period of trying out
life's alternatives. To his mother's great displeasure, he became entrenched in a new Persian
religion called Manichaeism and then joined a group of Neoplatonists. In both cases he
sought to understand how evil could exist in a world that was created by a good God. The Manichaean
explanation was that the material
world is inherently evil, but
through special knowledge from God we can rise above it. Neoplatonists argued
that evil results from the physical world
being so far removed from God, and thus absent from his goodness.
For fifteen years he lived with an woman and
fathered a son; but when his mother eventually convinced him to marry properly, he left his mistress. While awaiting his bride-to-be's coming of age, he took up with
yet another woman and prayed his famous prayer, "Grant me chastity and continence,
but not yet." But his marriage to either woman never transpired. While teaching rhetoric in the city of Milan, he
attended sermons of the Bishop of that region, which gradually led to his Christian conversion. Returning to North
Africa, he was drafted into the priesthood by
the locals for his popular preaching, and later became their bishop, devoting the rest of his life to writing and
preaching in that region. Augustine died at 75, even
as invading barbarian armies were tearing down the city walls of Hippo.
Augustine's literary output
was enormous, and he may be the most prolific
writer of the ancient world.
His most famous writings are
his Confessions and The City of God. While only a couple
of his shorter works are devoted exclusively to philosophy, most notably On Free Choice, many of his compositions are interspersed with philosophical content, and from these a
complex system emerges.
Faith, Certainty, and Divine Illumination
The starting point for Augustine's philosophy is his stance on the relation between faith and reason. We've
seen that there are two ways of
approaching the relation between faith and reason: first, Tertullian's
faith-only position, and, second,
the view that reason by itself can go a long way in establishing
religious truths independently of faith. Augustine struck a middle ground between the two, advocating a position that he
called "faith seeking understanding." His inspiration for this was a passage from the Isaiah "Unless you believe, you will
not understand."[1] On this view, reason by itself is not good enough to give
us proper religious knowledge; instead, we have to begin with faith to set us in
the right direction and, once we believe
in God through faith, we can seek to understand
the foundations of our belief through reason.
A running theme throughout Augustine's writings is that knowledge is
indeed attainable, and
we should reject the efforts of philosophical
skeptics. By the time Augustine came on the scene,
different Greek schools of skepticism were well established, and for centuries had been producing arguments to show that we can know nothing at all for certain.
Every belief I have can be brought into
question; even my belief
that the tree in front of me exists is uncertain
since I might just be having
a hallucination. In opposition to the
skeptics, Augustine argues that
there are four main areas in which we
have genuine knowledge that even the skeptics cannot question. Right off, each of us has indisputable knowledge of our own
existence. He writes,
On none of these points do I fear
the arguments of the skeptics of the Academy
who say: what if you are deceived?
For if I am deceived, I am. For he who does not exist
cannot be deceived. And if
I am
deceived, by this same token I am. [City of God,
11:26]
His point here is simple:
no matter how deceived I am-such as through hallucinations or flawed sensory perception-I still have to exist in order to be deceived. This knowledge is so obvious and self-evident that it enables
me to go one step further and say that/ know that I know. Knowledge is thus an indisputable fact.
In addition to knowledge of one's own existence, we also have
certainty in three key areas: math, logic and immediate sense experience. Mathematical truths, such
as "three times
three is nine," are so compelling that it is impossible to doubt
them. So too with
logical truths:
I have learned through dialectic
[logic] that many other things are true. Count, if you can, how many there are: If
there are four elements in the world,
there are not five; if there is one sun, there are not two;
one and the same soul cannot die and still be
immortal; man cannot at the same time be happy
and unhappy; if the sun is shining
here, it cannot be night; we are now either awake or asleep; either there is a body which I seem to see or there is not a body.
[Against the Academics, 3:13]
While Augustine recognizes that sense perceptions themselves are not always trustworthy, he nonetheless maintains that
reports of immediate experiences are indisputable, such as "the snow
appears white to me." Even if
in reality the snow happens to be a different color, what remains true is that I perceive
it as white. He writes:
I do not know how the [skeptical] Academician can refute
him who says "I know that this
appears white to me, I know that my
hearing is delighted with this, I know that this has an agreeable odor, I know that this tastes sweet to me, I know
that this feels cold to me."
[Ibid 3:11]
These areas of knowledge, then, seem to be completely indisputable because of the self evident
nature of their specific truths. There are other
areas of knowledge, though, that lack this self-evidence and may indeed be fallible, such as the truths themselves of what our senses
report, and also the knowledge that we
gain through the testimony of other people.
Nevertheless, he argues, in view of how much
important information they provide us, we can have reasonable confidence in them as reliable sources
of knowledge. Regarding
our senses, he argues,
"Far be
it from us to doubt the truth of
what we have learned by the
bodily senses, since by them we have
learned to know the heaven and the earth, and those things in them which are known to us." So too with
the knowledge that we gain
through the testimony of other people. While the reports of
some people cannot be trusted, testimony is nonetheless an indispensable source of
knowledge.
He writes,
Far be it from us too to
deny that we know what we have learned by the testimony of others:
otherwise, we would
not know that there is an ocean, or that the lands and cities exist which
numerous report mention to us"
(On the
Trinity, 15).
Granted, then, according to Augustine
we can know many things indisputably and other things with at least a
high degree of certainty. While certainty in these areas seems to be
a natural part of human thinking, knowledge
of other types of truth require special help from God before we can grasp them. God illuminates our minds to enable us to see these truths,
and Augustine succinctly describes this theory of divine illumination here:
"The mind needs to be enlightened by light from outside itself, so that it can participate in truth,
because it is not itself the nature
of truth. You will light my lamp, Lord" (Confessions, 4:15:25).
Human nature is limited, Augustine believes, and thus
we're not in a position by ourselves to comprehend
the most important ones. Truths regarding virtuous living and religious
faithfulness are cases in point:
"Among the objects of the intellect, there are
some that are seen in the soul
itself, for example, virtues which will endure, such as
piety, or virtues that are useful for this
life and not destined to remain in the next, as faith" (Commentary
on Genesis, 31:59).
For us to grasp these
truths, God illuminates our soul, which triggers a special intellectual vision
by which we can see them. While Augustine is quite clear that humans stand in
need of divine illumination, he is less
clear about how this process takes place. Does divine intuition unleash a flood of specific innate ideas in our minds? Is it more like a capacity that allows us to detect and zoom in on
the truth? One recent interpretation is that
we first develop beliefs on our own, and then God illuminates our minds so that we can see if they
are true or false; God provides the justification for our beliefs.
Evil, Free Will, Foreknowledge
Medieval philosophers developed very precise notions of God and
the attributes that he has, many of which
are even now well-known among believers. For example,
God is all-powerful (i.e., omnipotent), all-knowing (i.e.,
omniscient),
and all-good (i.e., omni-benevolent). Other commonly discussed attributes of God are that he is eternal, that he is present everywhere (i.e., omnipresent) and that he has foreknowledge of future events. While these traditional attributes of God offer a clear picture of the kind of being that he is, many of them present special conceptual problems, particularly when
we try to make them compatible them
with potentially conflicting facts about the world.
One of these is the famous problem of evil: how are we to understand God's goodness in the face of all the suffering that we experience? It's clear that suffering is abundant
throughout the world, and such
suffering is a type of evil.
It's also clear for religious philosophers that God is in
control of things, which seems to imply that God is the source of that suffering and evil. But
if God is good, then it seems that he can't be
the source of evil. Thus, there
is a conflict between God's power and
goodness on the one hand, and
the presence of suffering on the
other. How can we resolve
this conflict? The first step, for Augustine, is to recognize
that God has only an indirect role in the
cause of some suffering, as he explains here:
[You ask whether God is the cause of evil. In response,]
if you know or believe that God is
good (and it is not right to believe otherwise) then he does
no evil. Further, if we recognize
that God is just (and it is impious
to deny it) then he rewards the good
and punishes the wicked. Such
punishments are indeed evils for those
who suffer them. Therefore, if no one is punished
unjustly (this we must believe since we believe that this universe is governed
by divine providence) it follows that God is a cause of the suffering
of some evil, but in no way
causes the doing of evil. [On Free Choice: 1:1]
For Augustine, God's goodness means that he does no evil.
Yet, God's justness
means that he rewards good and punishes
evil. Thus, God indeed causes
some suffering through
punishment, but he is not the cause of evil actions themselves.
The cause of evil
itself, according to Augustine,
is the human will, and thus all blame for it rests
on our shoulders, not on Gods. We willfully turn our souls away from God when
we perform evil deeds:
"look for the source of this movement
and be sure that it does not come
from God" (On Free Choice, 2:20). Even the punishment that God imposes on us for our evil
is something that we brought on ourselves, since "punishment is used in
such a way that it places
natures in their right order''
(On Free Choice, 3:9). Thus, a first
solution that Augustine offers to the
problem of evil is that human will is the cause of
evil and reason for divine
punishment. A second and related solution is
that the evil we willfully create within our souls is only a deprivation of goodness. Think of God's goodness like a bright
white light; the evil that we humans create is like an act of dimming that light, or shielding ourselves from it to create an
area of darkness. It is not like we've created a competing light
source of our own, such
as a bright red light that we shine
around to combat God's bright white
light. Accordingly, the evil that we create through our wills is the absence
of good, and not a substantive evil in
itself.
Augustine
writes, ''
That movement of the soul's turning away, which we admitted was sinful, is a defective movement,
and every defect arises from non-being"
(On Free Choice, 2:20)
Drawing from Plotinus, "non-being"
is Augustine's term for the complete absence of God.
Yet a third solution to the problem of evil is Augustine's suggestion that the apparent imperfection of any part of
creation disappears in light of the
perfection of the whole. To explain, Augustine considers a common objection
that God seems to be the
source of suffering when our young children die with no clear purpose. His response is this:
In view of
the encompassing network of the universe
and the whole creation (a network that is perfectly ordered in time and place,
where
not even one leaf of a tree is superfluous) it is not possible to create a superfluous person. Moreover, who knows what faith is practiced or what pity is tested when these children's sufferings break down the hardness of parents? We do not
know what reward God reserves in the
secret places of his judgment for these
children [On Free Choice, 3.27]
Augustine is saying here that
troubling events such as the suffering of children are part of a larger system of things in the
world, and
even these events have a
place in contributing to the good of the whole. If we were capable
of grasping the entirety of the creation, we would then see the role that each thing
plays in the greater
scheme of things, contributing to its
total perfection.
The tension between God and evil is just one of the problems
surrounding God's attributes. Another that Augustine considers is the possible
conflict between God's foreknowledge and
human free will. If God knows ahead
of time what I will do at midnight tonight, then when the time comes I must
do that, and thus have no free choice. The
problem can be laid out more precisely as follows:
If God foreknows all events, then all events happen
according to a fixed, causal
order.
If all events
happen according to a fixed,
causal order, then nothing depends on us and there is no such thing as free will.
God foreknows all events,
hence there is no such thing as free will.
Augustine's solution
is to distinguish between
two distinct things about my future
decisions that God might focus
on. On the one hand, God might focus on and foresee my actions, in which case it looks
as though my actions are already causally fixed on the timeline. On the
other hand, however,
God might focus on and foresee what my choice
will be, what mental decision I make. By
foreseeing my choice, God is
focusing on a free will
decision that will be left to me in the future. Thus, God's foreknowledge of my actions is dependent upon what my
choice will be, and not on my action itself. He explains this here:
Since God foreknows our will, the very will that he
foreknows will be what comes about.
Therefore, it will be a will, since it is a will that
he foreknows. And
it could not be a will unless it were
in our power. Therefore,
he also foreknows this power. It follows,
then, that his foreknowledge does not take away my power; in
fact, it is all the more
certain that I will have that power, since he whose foreknowledge never errs
foreknows that I will have it. [On Free
Choice, 3:3)
For Augustine, the issue comes down to this. Suppose that I somehow foreknew what choice you would make tomorrow at noontime. Would that necessitate
you doing it? Clearly not. Thus,
God's foreknowledge of your choice
does not interfere with your freedom any more than my foreknowledge of your
choice would.
Morality, Proper Desire, Two Cities
Augustine's moral philosophy rests on a single
theme: desiring all things in their appropriate manner, and reserving our most supreme
desire for God. Humans have the capacity to desire things with a wide range of intensity, from very low
to very high. According to Augustine,
our human psyches are designed in
such a way that the highest
intensity of desire should be our ultimate love for God. The intensity of our desires for other things-wealth, fame, material
goods-should be far less. Our principal moral
task is to make sure that all of our desires are properly
ordered, that we desire things in the right way. When we fail to do this, our desires become disordered; that is, we
desire a lowly thing such as a coat
with the intensity that we should
otherwise devote to something much higher,
even God himself. It is this disordered desire that
motivates us to do evil: He writes,
When the miser prefers his gold
to justice, it is through no fault of the gold,
but of the man; and so with
every created thing. For though it is good, it may be loved
with an evil as well as with a good
love: it is loved rightly when it is
loved with proper order; evilly,
when disordered. [City of God, 15:22]
Not only is properly ordered desire central
to morality and virtuous conduct, but it is also the cornerstone to a good and just society.
Augustine's political views are mapped
out in his book The City of
God, which he initially
wrote against Roman pagans who blamed the 410 fall of Rome on the
domination of Christianity within society and their abolition of polytheistic worship. According to Augustine, we need to
see society as consisting of two "cities"
or cultures: an earthly one and a heavenly one. The defining difference between the two is that citizens of the
earthly city are motivated by disordered desire, while those of the heavenly city have properly
ordered desires. He writes,
Two cities have been formed by
two loves:
the earthly by the love of self, even to the contempt
of God; the heavenly by the love of
God, even to the contempt of self. The former, in a word, glories in itself, the latter in the
Lord. For the one seeks glory from men; but
the greatest glory of the other is God, the witness of conscience. The one lifts
up its head in its own glory; the other says to its God, "You are my glory, and you lift up my head." In the one,
the princes and the nations it subdues
are ruled by the love of ruling; in
the other, the princes and
the subjects serve one another in love, the latter obeying, while the former
take thought for all. The one
delights in its own strength, represented in the persons of its rulers; the other says to its God,
"I will love you, Lord, my strength." [City of God, 14:28]
The Roman Empire
itself, he argues,
is a perfect example of an earthly city that overindulged in disordered desires. This led to immorality, vice, crime, and its ultimate
downfall. Citizens of the heavenly city, who have
properly ordered desires, realize that the only eternal good is
found in God. They live by faith
and "look for those eternal
blessings which are promised" (City of God, 19:17)
People of
the heavenly city are obviously forced to live
here on earth among rival
members of the earthly city. However,
they consider themselves as resident aliens and follow the laws and
customs of the society they in which they dwell, but do not settle
down to enjoy them. He writes,
"So long as the heavenly city lives like a captive
and a stranger in the earthly city ... it does not hesitate to obey the laws of the earthly city, whereby the things necessary for the maintenance of this mortal life are
governed" (ibid).
The earthly city at its best seeks peace in this
life, a necessary condition for happiness. Accordingly,
"the earthly city, which does not live by faith, seeks
an earthly peace, and the end
it proposes... is the combination of men's wills to attain the things which are helpful to this life" (ibid).
The heavenly
city makes use of this peace only because it must.
BOETHIUS
While Augustine was the dominant
philosopher of the early middle ages, one other was influential on some specific
philosophical issues, namely,
Boethius.
Boethius. St. Benedit and the Preservation of Ancient Learning
During the Early Middle Ages
Following Augustine, original intellectual activity pretty
much ceases in Western Europe. Thus,
the early Middle Ages we can label a culturally bleak period. The political situation that came about after
the fall of the imperial government in the four hundreds, virtually destroyed
the social institutions that allowed for the transmission and preservation of
Greek and Roman culture in the Mediterranean.
The cities in Western Europe decline both in number and in
population. They were the primary
targets of barbarian attacks because most of the wealth was concentrated in
them. Once Germanic kingdoms were
established, civil war and banditry disrupted trade and cut off cities and
communication from each other within Western Europe. The threat of attack and
the decline in trade forced city dwellers to leave the city and relocate to the
countryside to become farmers, herdsmen
or monks. Roman schools of rhetoric and
law were also lake located in the cities and supported by city government. With the fall of the cities, formal higher
education disappeared as well. Educated
men needed to go to rural estates or relocate to monasteries. They were able there to pass on some
knowledge to the next generation, but it was difficult because of their
isolation. Limited intellectual activity
continued throughout the five hundreds and six hundreds and became even more
restricted over time. One sign of the
decline of intellectual learning was the disappearance of the knowledge of
Greek. In the late empire, virtually all
educated Romans were bilingual speaking both Latin and Greek. You had to know both Greek and Latin. But by
the three hundred, knowledge of Greek became much more rare. Augustine, for instance, who was a very
educated man of his day, knew very little Greek. The fall of the western empire, cuts off ties
with the West to the Greek empire and what remained a Greek speaking world. This further contributed to the decline of
Greek literacy in what had formerly been the western empire. Between 400 and 1400 we know of very few
western intellectuals who are fluent in Greek. This means that the Greek
learning in philosophy, science, culture, etcetera were inaccessible to
intellectuals in the western world and to the extent they were accessible, they
were accessible only through Latin translations. These translations were not numerous. By the end of the late Middle Ages, only one
of the major works of Plato was accessible in Latin to western
intellectuals. The educated men of this,
perceived that the great leaning of Greece and Rome was slipping away. Thus, the main effort of intellectuals of
this period, after the four hundreds, was to preserve as much as possible. A representative figure who did this, was a
man named Boethius. He was a Roman, but
he served as a minister for one of the Ostrogothic kings of Italy. He was finally executed for political reasons.
But he knew Greek, and he set out to translate Aristotle and Plato into
Latin. His death, however, prevented him
from completing this project. He was only
able to translate 2 basic works from Aristotle on logic. It wasn't very much, but it was the only
thing that Western Europe knew about Aristotle until about the year 1200. Another man who had great influence on the
preservation of learning was Saint Benedict of Nursia. He came from a wealthy Roman family. But he eventually turned to religion. After a time, he came to live as a hermit
monk. He therefore decided to build a
monastery in central Italy. For his
monastery he writes, rules to govern the organizations and the everyday
activities of the monks. These rules
were so popular and influential that they were adopted by other Western
monasteries. One of the key rules was
that the monks needed to keep busy all of the time to keep them from falling
into sin. One such activity was to copy
manuscripts. It was through the efforts
of Benedictine monks that any of the great books from ancient times were
preserved at all. In this work of
preservation generally, so much had to be done that only the slimmest
intellectual ties were maintained. To
save time, men passed on books that covered the widest possible range of
intellectual learning. Much of what was
kept were only sort of textbooks. As
such, they were very general and very elementary. They did not delve deeply into most
subjects. Since these medieval scholars
occupied most of their time in preservation, they had little chance for
original research and original thought.
They placed an unduly high value on the limited learning of texts. Despite their efforts to preserve ancient
culture, the early Middle Ages became an increasingly dark age
intellectually. So, what we can call the
decline and fall of Rome, represented far more than just a change in government
in Western Europe. It marked a
significant break in the line of development of civilization in two different
ways. To take the most obvious way first, adverse conditions determined that a
great portion of the Greco Roman intellectual world was gone. Men in the Middle Ages generally knew less
about ancient life and ancient thought than we know today. And even our knowledge is much more limited
than what we would like. Just as
important however, is the fact that that many of the basic assumptions of the
Greeks and the Romans had been discarded or radically altered well before the
Roman Empire ceased to exist.
Boethius: Universals and Divine Foreknowledge
Boethius (480-524) is best remembered for his theory
of universals which set the conceptual framework for discussion on that topic throughout the middle ages. He
was born in Rome to a wealthy
Christian family, but soon after orphaned, he was raised by his adopting family with a great appreciation for
Greek and Roman culture, at a time when Rome was ruled by barbarian kings. He was well acquainted
with classical philosophy, particularly Plato, Aristotle and Neoplatonism, and his extensive
knowledge made him a valuable asset to the royal government. Quickly moving up the ranks in
administrative posts, his career
came to an abrupt end when he was accused of treason and executed. While in prison he wrote his most
influential work, The Consolation of Philosophy.
Boethius has the honor of being the first medieval philosopher to systematically explore
the problem of universals, that is, the
question of whether abstract
notions such as "greenness"
exist somewhere in reality or only in our minds. He got his inspiration from a brief comment about universals made by the Neoplatonist philosopher Porphyry:
I shall avoid investigating (a) whether genera and species
[i.e., universals] are real or are situated in bare thoughts alone, (b) whether as real they are bodies or incorporeals, and (c) whether they are separated
or in sensibles and
have their reality in connection
with them. Such business is profound, and requires another, greater investigation. [Introduction to Aristotle's Categories]
In the
above passage Porphyry lists possible ways of understanding how universals
might exist, and Boethius refined
these into three positions. The first position is that universals such as "greenness" exist outside of our minds and even separately
from bodies physical
bodies such as a green tree. This is the classic
position taken by Plato who held that
abstract notions such
as "greenness" exist in the non-physical realm of the Forms. The term
for this option is "universals ante rem", Latin for "before the thing." Position
two is that universals are intrinsic-or built into-physical things. For example,
the universal "greenness"
is found in all green individual objects, such as trees and grass. This is the view
taken by Aristotle, and the term for
this position is "universals in
re", Latin for "in
the thing." The third
position is that universals exist
only as concepts in the human mind, and not in
any real way in the external
world. We abstract them from particular things, such as when after viewing
several green trees I form the mental
abstraction of "greenness". The official term for this is "universals post rem",
Latin for "following the thing." These three positions on
universals, as laid out by Boethius,
became the definitive options of further discussion on the subject by later medieval philosophers as they defended one of these positions
against the others. So, which of these
three views did Boethius think is right? It's not clear. He criticizes them all on various grounds, but in one of his writings he seems to go along with Aristotle and in another
with Plato.
Boethius was particularly influential on one
other philosophical issue that of the conflict between divine
foreknowledge and free will. Again, the problem
here is that if God knows
what I will do before hand, then that event must
happen, and I have no free will to do otherwise.
Boethius has an ingenious solution
to this problem: God stands outside of time and thus knows what I will do by viewing the whole timeline at once; this does not constrain our free choices. This solution
rests on a unique conception of God's attribute of eternality. Consider these
two conceptions of what it means to be eternal: (1) endless existence on the timeline,
and (2) existence completely outside of time. To say that God is eternal in the
first sense means simply that at any point
that you pick in the time line, God existed or will
exist at that point. God moves through time along with me and everything
else in the world. The second notion
of eternality places God completely outside of the timeline and
suggests that the phenomenon of time does not even apply to God. Boethius goes with this second notion of God's eternality:
"eternity is the possession of endless life, whole and perfect
at a single moment" (Consolation of Philosophy, 5:6).
Once we adopt this second view of God's eternality, according to
Boethius, the conflict between foreknowledge
and free will disappears. God does not foresee
my future actions by peeking down the timeline with a special telescope. Rather, he inspects the entire timeline at once, which includes the free will choices that I make at the moments that I make
them.
Since God stands forever in
an eternal present, his knowledge, also transcending all movement
of time, dwells in the simplicity of its own changeless present. It embraces the whole infinite sweep of the past and of the future, contemplates all that falls within
its simple cognition as if it
were now taking place. And therefore, if you will carefully consider that immediate presentment whereby it discriminates all things, you will more rightly conclude that it is not
foreknowledge as of something future, but knowledge of a moment that never passes....
Thus, the divine anticipation does not change
the natures and properties of things, and it
beholds things present before it, just
as they will hereafter come to pass in
time. [Ibid]
For Boethius, then, it is misleading to
even call this divine "foreknowledge" since
this wrongly implies that God is looking into the
future. Instead, it is an "outlook" that
"embraces all things as from some lofty height"
(ibid).
Boethius
The Consolation of Philosophy
Consolatio Philosophiae
·
Written around the year 524
·
Written during his imprisonment before his trial and execution for
the crime of treason.
·
Victim of treachery while at the height of his career
·
Reflects on evil and God (the problem of theodicy) and how
happiness can be attained
References
to God, but philosophical and not religious
No
reference made to Jesus Christ or Christianity, etc.
God
is represented as an eternal, all-knowing being and the source of all Good.
Boethius
writes the book as a conversation between himself and Lady Philosophy.
She
consoles Boethius by discussing the transitory nature of fame and wealth
She
contends that happiness comes from within by attaining virtue. No one can take away a persons virtue.
When she saw that the Muses of poetry were present by my couch
giving words to my lamenting, she was stirred a while; her eyes flashed
fiercely as she said: Who has suffered these seducing mummers to approach this
sick man?
Never have they nursed his sorrowings
with any remedies, but rather fostered them with poisonous sweets. These are
they who stifle the fruit-bearing harvest of reason with the barren briars of
the passions; they do not free the minds of men from disease but accustom them
thereto.
I would think it less grievous if your allurements drew away from
me some common man like those of the vulgar herd, seeing that in such a one my
labors would be harmed not at all. But this man has been nurtured in the lore
of Eleatics and Academics.
Away with you, sirens, seductive even to perdition, and leave him
to my Muses to be cared for and healed!
We
see what will become an institutional censoring, very similar to what Plato
prescribed in the Republic, of Art and all things beautiful should the fall
short of the test of true beauty.
Boethius
seems also to have inherited Plato suspicion of Theatre as deliberate deception.
ANSELM
Anselm (1033-1109) made his mark in the
history of philosophy for developing what is
now called the ontological
argument for God's existence. He was born to a noble family, owners of
considerable property in the city of Aosta in the Italian Alps. His virtuous mother
faithfully provided young Anselm with religious training and inspired in him a love of
learning. In contrast, his father
was a harsh man with a violent
temper. At 14 years of age Anselm sought admission to a monastery, but the abbot, fearing trouble
from his father, refused him without
paternal permission. The boy was so desperate,
he prayed for an illness, hoping the
monks would pity him and change their minds. He got half his wish. He became ill, but was
still not accepted. This, and the death
of his mother, resulted in Anselm leaving his studies
for a more carefree life. By age 23, he could take his father's
abuse no longer and left, wandering for three years through the region. He then
entered the Benedictine abbey at Bee, Normandy,
as a novice, and in a few short
years became its Prior. He was later enthroned as archbishop of Canterbury. However, when the King
refused to free the church from royal control, Anselm went into exile
in protest. When the King died, the subsequent ruler called
Anselm back, but the terms were no
different, and so Anselm remained in exile.
Throughout this time he wrote many short works. At the time these did
not receive their deserved
appreciation, but are now considered
great achievements. Anselm's writings are in
the form of dialogues and meditations, the most important of which
are his Monologium and
Proslogium.
Anselm followed Augustine's view of the
relation between faith and reason: faith seeking understanding. Thus, Anselm writes "I hold it to be
a failure in duty if after we have become steadfast in our faith we do
not strive to understand what we believe."
In his effort to understand his faith, he was
consumed with the idea of proving God's existence, and, in his first
effort to do so, he offers a proof from absolute goodness. He presents the basic intuition behind this argument here:
Since there are goods so
innumerable, whose great diversity we experience by the bodily senses,
and discern by our mental faculties, must we not believe
that there is some one thing,
through which all goods whatever are
good? [Monologium
1]
More formally, his argument is this:
Goodness exists in a variety
of ways and degrees.
This would be impossible
without an absolute standard of
good, in which all goods participate.
Therefore, an absolute standard
of good exists, which is God.
The argument takes its inspiration from Plato's view of the Form of the Good. According to Plato,
all good things that we see around
us-a good person,
a good photograph, a good meal-obtain their goodness by participating in perfect form of Goodness
that exists in a nonphysical realm. Anselm
agrees, and he draws attention to the fact that the same kind of things often differ in their degree of goodness. Some people
are very good, others not so much. Some
meals are good, others not so much. The standard
of goodness, then, must come from
some outside source which is always perfectly good, and that perfectly good source is
God.
Ontological Argument
Although Anselm believed that this argument
successfully proved God's existence, he also felt that it was a little too cluttered. It first requires us to experience various good things in the world, then assess their differing levels of goodness, then finally draw the conclusion.
Perhaps, Anslem thought, he could do
better and construct a more self-contained argument: "I began to ask myself whether there might be found a single argument which would require no other for its proof than itself alone" (Proslogium, Preface). This indeed is what he
accomplished in his Ontological Argument for God's existence, which even today stands as one of
the greatest arguments in the history of philosophy. It doesn't require us to experience
anything through our senses. Rather, it simply
begins with a definition of God, and draws its conclusion directly from that definition. Although the argument is quite self-contained, it is a bit challenging to grasp its central point as he presents it here:
Even the fool [who says in his heart
there is no God]
is convinced that something
exists in the understanding, at least, than which nothing greater can be conceived. For, when
he hears of this, he understands
it. And whatever is understood,
exists in the understanding. And assuredly that, than which nothing greater can
be conceived, cannot exist in the
understanding alone. For, suppose it exists in the understanding alone: then it can be conceived to exist in reality; which is greater.
Therefore, if that, than which nothing greater can be conceived, exists in the understanding alone, the very
being, than which nothing greater can be conceived, is one,
than which a greater can be conceived. But
obviously this is impossible. Hence, there is no doubt that
there exists a being, than which nothing greater
can be conceived, and it exists both
in the understanding and in reality. [Proslogium, 2)
Worded more simply,
his argument is this:
God is defined as "The Greatest Possible Being."
The Greatest Possible Being must have every quality that would make it
greater (or more superior) than it would be otherwise.
Having the quality of real existence is greater than having
the quality of imaginary existence
Therefore, the Greatest Possible
Being must have the quality
of real existence.
Premise one gives a definition of God.
Anselm's actual wording is that God
is "that than which nothing greater
can be conceived," which more concisely
means simply that God is the greatest possible being. Premise two rests on the notion
of a quality that makes something great: to possess it makes you greater
than to lack it. Having the quality of strength makes a
bridge greater than it would be if
it lacked it. Having the quality of
healthiness makes be greater than I
would be if I lacked it. By definition, the "Greatest
Possible Being" must have every quality that would make it great.
Premise three states that "existence" is a quality that makes
something great. Having a real gold
coin in my pocket is greater than
just imagining to have one. By
existing in reality, I am greater than I would otherwise be if I only existed
in someone's imagination. The conclusion
that follows is that the Greatest
Possible Being must have the quality of real existence: if it lacked
it, it could have been greater. That is, it would be the
"Greatest Possible Being that
could have been greater," which is a contradiction.
Anselm recognizes that "existence"
is just one quality that makes something greater than it would be otherwise.
Another such quality is ultimate power, and, thus, we can reword
premise 3 with this quality:
Having the quality of ultimate power
is greater than having limited
power.
Thus, the Greatest Possible Being must also have the quality of
ultimate power. So too with ultimate wisdom, and ultimate goodness.
Anselm writes that the Greatest
Possible Being is "just, truthful, blessed, and whatever it is better to be than not to be. For it is better to be just than not
just; better to be blessed than not blessed" (ibid, 3). Anselm
uses this strategy to show
that, not only does the Greatest
Possible Being exist,
but it exists necessarily; that is, it would be impossible for him to not exist-or, as he words it, "it cannot be conceived not to exist" (ibid).
Thus, again, we can reword premise 3 with this quality:
Having the quality of necessary existence
is greater than having contingent existence.
The term "contingent existence," as used
above, refers to things that just happen
to exist, but don't need to exist,
such as me, the chair I'm sitting on, and
every other physical thing in the world. That is, we can conceive
of a universe where none of these
things existed. By contrast,
necessary existence has to do with
things whose non-existence is impossible.
Mathematical concepts such as 2+2=4 might be examples
of these, since it is impossible for hese
notions to be false. Anselm's point above is that necessary existence is superior to mere contingent existence, and thus the Greatest
Possible Being must have the quality of necessary
existence.
Guanilo's
Criticism
As Anselm's writings circulated, a monk
named Guanilo had trouble accepting Anselm's
argument. While Guanilo certainly believed that God
existed, he felt that Anselm's argument was
flawed, and thus tried
to expose the problem. Guanilo suggests that we
should imagine a mythological
"lost island" that we might
define as "The Greatest Possible Island". By plugging this definition into Anselm's
ontological argument, we could then prove the existence of that island. Guanilo writes,
You can no longer doubt that this island which is more excellent than all lands
exists somewhere, since you have
no doubt that it is in your understanding. And since
it is more excellent not to be in the understanding alone, but to
exist both in the understanding and in
reality, for this reason it
must exist. For if it does not exist, any land which really exists will be more
excellent than it; and so the island already understood by you
to be more excellent will not be more excellent. [Ibid, Guanilo]
Following
the argument structure
above, the parallel
argument that Guanilo offers is this:
The Lost Island is defined as "The
Greatest Possible Island."
The Greatest Possible Island must have every quality that would make it greater (or more superior)
than it would be
otherwise.
Having the quality of real existence
is greater than having the quality of imaginary existence.
Therefore, the Greatest Possible Island must have the quality of real existence.
The larger point of Guanilo's
criticism is that Anselm's type of argument is
so flawed that it would show the existence of the greatest possible
anything-the Greatest Possible Shoe, the Greatest Possible Unicorn,
the Greatest Possible Eyebrow.
Anselm gave an extensive reply to Guanilo, attempting to show that the argument
format only works with "The Greatest Possible Being" and not with
things like islands.
That being alone, on the other hand, cannot
be conceived not to exist,
in which any conception discovers neither beginning nor end nor composition of parts, and which
any conception finds always and everywhere as a whole....So, then, of God alone it can be said
that it is impossible to conceive of his nonexistence; and yet
many objects, so long as
they exist, in one sense
cannot be conceived not to exist. But in
what sense God is to be conceived
not to exist, I think has been shown clearly enough in my book.
[Ibid, Reply]
Anselm's reply seems to be this. The argument structure only works with "the Greatest Possible Being," since only "being" is capable of having
ultimately great qualities, such as necessary existence. An island, by contrast, is a finite and limited
thing that is composed of parts, and is thus incapable of having ultimately great qualities. The very notion of "The Greatest Possible Island" is self-contradictory since it attempts
to impose the greatest possible
qualities on a finite
thing. Again, only the notion
of "being" is capable of having ultimately great qualities piled onto it. Thus, only one version of the argument
works-the one that focuses
on the greatest possible
being-and this is an argument that proves
specifically proves the existence
of God.
AQUINAS
Perhaps the leading philosopher of the middle ages was Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), who maintained that reason, unaided
by faith, can give us
knowledge of God's existence
and an understanding of morality as it is grounded in natural law. At his family's
castle in Naples, Italy, Thomas Aquinas was born to
nobility on both sides, being a son of
Count and a relative of a dynasty of Holy
Roman emperors. His education
began at age five at a monastery where his uncle was abbot,
and expectations were high that Aquinas
would one day fill that position. He
was later transferred to the
University of Naples, where he became acquainted with the Dominicans and, to his family's
horror, resolved to join them. At 18, he set off for Rome, but was seized by his brothers, returned to the family
castle, and held captive while the family prayed, threatened, and even tempted
him with a prostitute, hoping to change his mind. They could not. A year later the family yielded under pressure from the Pope, and Aquinas was sent to Cologne to study under some of the great philosophers of the time.
While Aquinas was described
as refined, affable and lovable,
he was physically big, solemn
and slow to speak, earning him the
nickname of the Dumb Ox. A story
relates that Aquinas's colleagues teased him saying that there was a flying cow outside, and when he looked out the
window they laughed. Aquinas responded
that he would rather believe that a cow could fly than that his brothers would deceive
him. During his subsequent education, apprenticeship, and public
business in the church, he became famous for religious
devotion and excellent memory, having memorized much of the Bible. The church
offered to make him an archbishop and an
abbot, but he refused both, preferring his studies. He composed book after book until
he had a mystical experience that compelled him to
cease writing altogether. Traveling to attend a Church
Council, he became ill and died. Fifty years later he was canonized as a saint
despite the lack of traditional saintly manifestations-stigmata, miracles, mortifications-which were waived in lieu of his outstanding
contribution to the Church. His philosophical
writings commentaries on
Aristotle and his most important work,
the multi-volume Summa Theologica (Latin
for "theological synopsis").
Aquinas wrote in a formal and technical
style that was common during
this period of medieval
philosophy. From the time of Augustine, medieval
philosophy had a mystical and intuitional
component to it. We've seen this specifically with Augustine's motto "faith seeking understanding" and Pseudo-Dionysius' view that through
denying our notions
of God we ascend higher
in our experience towards him. The larger
message of this earlier
period was one of warning: reason
is all well and good in its proper context,
but it should not replace the more
religiously intimate element of faith. Around 1100, though, this gave way to a more rationalistic approach that emerged within medieval universities called scholasticism, meaning the method of the "schools". The goal of scholasticism was to systematically bring philosophy
into dialogue with theology through a very specific
methodology. Philosophical texts would no longer be written as prayers to God
or meditations, but rather in a much more scientific-like manner.
Precise questions would be posed, followed by a critical
analysis of previous philosophers' views of the subject. Subtle distinctions would be made to help clarify problems. Through this critical analysis,
rationally-informed answers to the
questions would emerge. Some medieval philosophers, such as Anselm, were transitional figures with their feet in both genres.
Aquinas's writings, though, fully embody the scholastic approach.
Twofold
Truth
and
Proofs
for
God
Like other medieval philosophers, Aquinas' philosophy starts
with a view of the relation between faith and reason. For a religious believer,
faith in God and scripture is of
course fundamental. However, he argues, many basic religious truths such as God's existence
can be proven without faith
and through reason alone. Accordingly, he
proposes a view of faith and reason which he calls
the twofold truth: while reason
can give us some truth, other truths can only be attained through faith. He
writes,
The truths that we confess
concerning God fall into two
categories. Some things that are true of God are beyond all the competence of human reason, such as that God is three and one. There
are other things to which
even human reason can attain, such as
the existence and unity of God,
which philosophers have proved to a demonstration under the guidance of the
light of natural reason. [Summa Contra Gentiles, 1.3]
The first
class of truths that are accessible through reason alone he calls
presuppositions of faith, which include the truths that God exists and God is one. The second class of truths,
called mysteries of faith,
are accessible only through faith and involve doctrines like the Trinity, which we learn about in
scripture and are central to the Christian faith in particular. Human reason
alone cannot access these truths, he argues,
since, in our present life
"knowledge and understanding begins with the senses" (ibid). While
this prevents us from knowing God's inner nature, our senses can still give
us information about creation which allows us to infer that there is a
powerful and designing creator to all that
we see.
Again, one of the things that we can know through reason alone is that God exists,
and to that end Aquinas offers five
ways of proving God. Briefly, they are these:
There must be a first mover of things that are in
the process of change and motion.
There must be a first efficient
cause of the events that we see around us.
There must be a necessary being to explain
the contingent beings
in the world around us.
There must be an ultimately
good thing to explain the good that we see in lesser things.
There must be an intelligent being who guides
natural objects to their ends or purposes.
The first
three of his proofs share a similar strategy, which was inspired by
Aristotle's notion of the unmoved
mover: there is a first cause of all the motion that takes place throughout the
cosmos. In more recent times this argument strategy has been dubbed
the cosmological argument. We'll look specifically at Aquinas's second
argument from efficient cause as he
presents it here:
The second way is
from the nature of the efficient cause.
In the world of sense we find there is an order of efficient causes. There is no case known (neither is it, indeed, possible) in which a thing is found to be the efficient cause
of itself; for so it would be prior to itself, which is impossible. Now in efficient causes it is not possible to go on to infinity, because
in all efficient causes following
in order, the first is the cause of the intermediate cause, and the intermediate is the cause of the ultimate cause, whether
the intermediate cause be several,
or only one. Now to take away the cause is to take away the effect. Therefore, if there be no first cause among efficient causes, there will be no ultimate, nor any intermediate cause.
But if in efficient causes
it is possible to go on to infinity, there will be no first efficient cause, neither will there be an ultimate effect, nor any intermediate efficient causes; all of which is plainly false. Therefore it is necessary to admit a first efficient
cause, to which everyone
gives the name of God. [ST 1, Q. 2, Art. 3]
According to Aquinas, we experience various kinds of effects in the world around us, and in every case we
assign an efficient cause to each effect.
The efficient cause of the
statue is the work of the sculptor. If we took away the activity of the
sculptor, we would not have the effect,
namely, the statue. But there is
an order of efficient causes: the hammer strikes the chisel which in turn strikes the marble. But it is impossible
to have an infinitely long sequence of efficient causes, and so we arrive at a first efficient cause.
Aquinas's argument from efficient cause is deceptively brief, and he appears to be offering the same argument that early Muslim
philosophers did in the so-called
Kalam argument for God's existence.
That is, it seems as though he is saying that it
is impossible to trace such
causal connections back through time and, ultimately, we must arrive at a first
cause, namely, God.
However, other writings by Aquinas make it clear that he is doing something different. Why, at least in theory,
couldn't this causal sequence trace back through time, to infinity past, and never have a starting
point? Although this may be a strange contention, there is nothing logically
contradictory about it. He writes that
"It is by faith alone that we
hold, and by no demonstration can it be proved,
that the world did not always exist" (ST
1, Q. 46, Art. 2).
Aquinas suggests that we view the
causal sequence somewhat differently.
Some causal sequences do indeed take place over time, such as when Abraham produces his son Isaac,
who later produces his own son Jacob. But in
addition to these time-based sequences, there are also simultaneous
causal sequences, which do not trace back through
time. Imagine, for example, if I hold a stick in my hand and use it to move a stone. According to Aquinas,
my hand, the stick, and the stone
all move at the same time. He makes
this point here using the terminology of "essential" causes that are simultaneous and
"accidental" causes that are time-based:
In efficient
causes it is impossible to
proceed to infinity essentially
[i.e., simultaneously]. Thus, there cannot be an
infinite number of [simultaneous] causes that are essentially required for a certain effect-for instance, that a stone be moved by a stick, the stick by the hand, and so on to infinity. But it is not impossible
to proceed to infinity accidentally [i.e., over time] as regards efficient
causes. [Ibid]
Aquinas's causal proof, then, proceeds
like this:
Some things exist and their existence is caused.
Whatever is caused to exist is caused to exist by something else.
An infinite series of simultaneous causes resulting in the
existence of a particular thing is impossible.
Therefore, there is a first cause of whatever
exists.
Aquinas did
not give us an example
of the sort of simultaneous causes in
the natural world that traces
immediately back to God, but here is a likely instance of what he is talking about.
Consider the motion of the winds. At the very moment that the winds are moving, there are larger physical forces at work that create
this motion. In medieval science, the motion of the moon is responsible for the motion of the
winds. But the moon itself
moves because it too is
being simultaneously moved
by other celestial motions, such as the planets,
the sun, and the stars. According to Aquinas, simultaneous causal sequences of motion cannot
go on forever, and
we must eventually find a first
cause of this motion, which
"everyone understands to be God."
So much for Aquinas's second way to prove God's existence. As noted, the
first and third ways follow similar
strategies, insofar as they claim that causal sequences
of change and contingency cannot go on forever. The fourth way is like Anselm's argument from absolute
goodness: there must be an absolute standard
of goodness which is the cause of the good that
we see in lesser things. His fifth way, though,
is unique and is a
version of what in later
times is called
the design argument. He writes,
The fifth way is taken from the governance of the world. We see that things which lack intelligence, such as natural
bodies, act for an end, and this is evident
from their acting always, or nearly always, in the same way, so as to obtain
the best result. Hence it is plain that not fortuitously, but
designedly, do they achieve their end.
Now whatever lacks intelligence cannot move towards an end, unless it be directed by some being endowed with knowledge and
intelligence; as the arrow is
shot to its mark by the archer. Therefore some intelligent being
exists by whom all natural
things are directed to their end;
and this being we call God. [ST 1, Q. 2, Art.
3]
More formally,
his argument is this:
Objects without intelligence act
towards some end (for example, a tree grows and
reproduces its own kind).
Moving towards an end exhibits
a natural design that requires
intelligence.
If a thing is unintelligent, yet acts for some end, then it must be guided to this end by something which is intelligent.
Therefore, an intelligent being exists that moves natural things
toward their ends, which is God.
The central
notion behind this argument is that natural objects such as plants and animals have built-in purposes. Here Aquinas draws directly on Aristotle's concept of a "natural object" which has an innate
impulse towards change in specific ways. According to Aquinas, when natural objects
move towards their end, this reveals
a natural design that could not have come about through chance, but requires
intelligence. Since plants and animals lack intelligence to do this, some
other intelligence is responsible
for this, namely God.
Divine
Simplicity and Religious Language
Not only can we prove the existence of God through reason unaided by faith, but there are
some features of God's existence that reason by itself can also reveal to us. Religious
philosophers often describe God as having a cluster
of attributes, such as being all-powerful, all knowing, all-good;
Aquinas certainly agrees that God is these things. However, he maintains that God in fact has a single attribute: divine simplicity. Several philosophers prior
to Aquinas, including Parmenides and Plotinus, held that God is best described as "the One", namely, a simple, indivisible entity. Aquinas agrees as we see
here:
There is neither composition of
quantitative parts in God, since He is not a
body; nor composition of matter and form; nor does His nature differ from His
person; nor His essence from His existence; neither is there
in Him composition of genus and difference,
nor of subject and accident. Therefore, it is
clear that God is nowise composite, but is altogether simple. [ST 1, Q 3, Art. 7]
According
to Aquinas, God has no parts
whatsoever, no physical parts, and, more importantly,
no conceptual parts, such as
specific properties or predicates. His basic
proof for God's simplicity is this:
If something is composed of parts then it must be potentially divisible (e.g., an actual book is
potentially a pile of torn
out sheets of paper).
God is not potentially divisible.
Therefore God is not composed of parts (i.e., God is simple).
While God
in is true nature is simple, Aquinas
concedes that to finite human minds
he appears to have distinct parts. The
reason for this seems to be that our minds are designed to understand things in the world around us, virtually all of which have parts--parts of trees, parts of chairs, parts of languages. When we then attempt to understand God in his simplicity,
we then very naturally view him as a
thing that is composed of parts,
and attempt to understand
him one element at a time. He writes,
We can speak of simple things only as though they
were like the composite things from which we derive our knowledge. Therefore in speaking of God,
we use concrete nouns to signify His subsistence, because with us only those things subsist which are composite; and we use abstract nouns to signify His simplicity. In saying therefore
that Godhead, or life, or the like are in God, we indicate the
composite way in which our intellect understands, but not that there is any composition in God. [ST 1, Q 3, Art. 3]
To satisfy our tendency to view God as a composite thing, we can
deduce some sub-attributes of God from his main attribute of simplicity. For example, we
can say that God is eternal since if a thing is simple, then it has no "before" or "after''
and thus is eternal. Similarly, we
can say that God is perfect since if a thing is simple then it is completely actualized, with no remaining
potentiality, and complete actualization is perfection. The whole issue of God's
attributes raises an even more fundamental
question of the adequacy
of religious language: can any of our
descriptions of God satisfactorily represent him? For example, if we
say that "God loves us,"
what sort of "love" are we talking
about, and is the notion of
divine love something that can even be put into words? We've already seen a variety
of answers to this question of religious language: Many said we can only describe God negatively; Maimonides said that we
can only describe God allegorically. Aquinas approaches the issue by noting
three ways that our words might, at least in theory, apply to God. The first
is univocal: the religious and non-religious uses of a word like
"love" are completely the same, whether we're talking about human love or divine love. Aquinas rejects this approach:
Univocal predication is impossible between God and creatures... [The] term "wise" is not
applied in the same way to God and to
man. The same rule applies to other
terms. Hence no name is predicated univocally of God and of creatures. [ST 1, Q. 13, Art. S]
The problem with the univocal approach is
that the gulf between God's nature and human nature is so vast that the term
"love" cannot possibly mean the exact
same thing when we're talking about divine love vs. human love. The next way is equivocal:
the religious and non religious uses of a word
like "love" are completely
different. Aquinas rejects this approach
as well:
Neither, on the other
hand, are names applied to God and creatures in a purely equivocal sense, as some have said. Because if that
were so, it follows that from
creatures nothing could be known or demonstrated about God at all. [Ibid]
The problem
here is that if religious language and human
language have nothing in common,
then we can say nothing at all
about God. Rejecting
both the univocal and equivocal approach, Aquinas
recommends a middle ground between
the two: an analogical approach
whereby the religious use of a word bears some analogy to the non-religious use. For example, we can say that divine
love is to God just as parental love is
to a parent. He writes,
In analogies the idea is
not, as it is in univocals, one and the same, yet it is not totally diverse as in equivocals. Rather
a term which is thus used in a
multiple sense signifies various proportions to some one thing. Thus "healthy" applied
to urine signifies the sign of
animal health, and applied
to medicine signifies
the cause of the same health.
[Ibid]
The point is that there is something
in common to both religious language and
human language, but it can only be understood as a comparison of two relations. For example, to grasp the notion of divine love, we must first examine the relation between human parents and parental
love: we have a special attachment
to our offspring that overrides every other human interest. In some parallel
way, this is what God's love towards humans involves.
Morality and Natural Law
In the arena of moral philosophy,
Aquinas developed a view called natural
law theory, which for centuries was perhaps the dominant view regarding the source of moral principles. In a nutshell,
natural law theory holds that God endorses specific moral standards and fixes them in
human nature, which we discover
through rational intuition. According to Aquinas, there are
four kinds of law: eternal
law, natural law, human law and divine law. Eternal
law, the broadest type of law, is the unchanging divine governance over
the universe. This includes both the general moral rules of conduct, such as "stealing is wrong," and particular rules
such as "people should not intentionally write bad checks." Natural law is a subset of eternal law, which God
implants in human nature and we
discover through reflection. However, it includes
only general rules of conduct, such as "stealing is
wrong," not specific cases. Next, human
law is a derivation of natural
law that extends
to particular cases, such as "people should not write bad checks." Finally, divine law, as contained
in the Bible, is a specially
revealed subset of the eternal law that
is meant to safeguard against possible errors
in our attempts to both obtain natural
law through reflection, and derive more particular
human laws. In this way we see that the Bible
condemns stealing in general, as well as various forms of theft through fraud.
All moral laws whether general ones discovered through reflection, or specific ones derived
by legislators, or ones found in the scriptures- are ultimately
grounded in an objective, universal, and unchanging eternal law.
What, specifically, are the
principles of natural law that God
has embedded into human nature? First, there
is one highest principle: "Good
is to be done and evil is
to be avoided." Aquinas writes,
This is the
first precept of law, that "good
is to be
done and pursued, and evil is to be
avoided." All other precepts
of the natural law are based
upon this: so that whatever
the practical reason naturally apprehends as man's good (or evil) belongs to the precepts of the natural law as something to be done or
avoided. [ST la-2ae, Q. 94, Art. 2]
From this, we determine what is "good" for us by looking at our human inclinations; he notes six in particular that are
connected with our human good: self-preservation, heterosexual activity,
educating our offspring, rationality, gaining knowledge of God, and living in society. He writes,
Because in man
there is first of all an inclination
to good in accordance with the nature which he has in
common with all substances: inasmuch as every substance seeks the preservation of
its own being, according to its
nature: and by reason of this inclination, whatever is a means
of preserving human life, and of warding off its obstacles,
belongs to the natural law. Secondly, there is in man an inclination to things that pertain to him more specially, according to that nature which he has in common with
other animals: and in virtue of this inclination, those things are said
to belong to the natural law, "which
nature
has taught to all animals," such as sexual intercourse, education of
offspring and so forth. Thirdly, there is in man an inclination to good,
according to the nature of his reason, which nature is proper to him:
thus man has a natural inclination to know
the truth about God, and to live in
society: and in this respect,
whatever pertains to this inclination belongs to the natural law; for instance, to shun ignorance, to avoid harming or offending
those among whom one has to live, and other such things regarding the above
inclination. [Ibid]
For Aquinas, these six inclinations comprise
what is most proper for humans, and provide the basis for the primary
precepts of morality. This gives us six primary principles of natural law: (1) preserve human life, (2) have heterosexual intercourse, (3)
educate your children, (4) shun ignorance, (5) worship God, and (6) avoid
harming others.
Each of these
primary principles encompasses more specific
or secondary principles. For
example, the primary principle "avoid harming others" implies the
secondary principles "don't steal" and "don't assault." These, in turn, imply even more specific or tertiary principles, such as "don't write bad checks." As the principles become
more specific, they leave the domain
of natural law and enter that of
human law. When considering whether
natural law is the same in all people,
he argues that the primary principles are common to everyone, such as "do not harm others." However, more particular tertiary derivations of human
law are not necessarily common to all societies. Still, he argues, human law will carry
the force of natural law if the tertiary principles are derived correctly. But,
"if in any point it deflects
from the law of nature, it is no longer a law but a perversion of law" (ibid, 95)
Notes on Aquinas:
Remember that philosopher since Thales were puzzled about the
notion of "Change." Positions
varied from one extreme (that there can be
no real change and all apparent
change is an illusion) to the
other (there is only
change and there is nothing permanent, lasting or true -except change).
Aristotle's answer
is to say that a thing can "be" in more than one way. It can
"be" actually and it
can "be" potentially. The hard rubber ball is actually hard, but is potentially gooey.
To realize its potential,
(to actualize its potential) some
actual thing must act on it. (Heat). Only actual heat (not "potential heat") can move the potentially
gooey rubber ball to actuality. So any change/
motion requires a actuality to more so potentiality to actuality. Potentiality itself cannot actualize
anything; it is impotent and has no power to
actualize.
Consider a hand moving a stone with a stick (a favorite example
for those speaking on this topic). The
stone moves only insofar as the stick moves and thus moves the stone, and the
stick itself moves only insofar as
the hand moves. Aristotle/ Aquinas
would say that the stone's potentiality for motion
is actualized by the stick, but only because, simultaneously, the stick's potentiality for motion is actualized
by the hand. The stick HAS NO
ABILITY to move the stone on its own, but derives all of its actualizing
ability from the hand.
But so too the hand. The hand is not really
the first member
of the series. It moves only because
the arm moves it.
"The
motion of the stone
depends on the motion of the hand, which depends on the motion of the
stick, which depends on the firing
of the neurons, which depends
on the firing of other neurons, all of which
depends on the state of the nervous
system, which depends
on its current molecular structure, which depends on the atomic basis of that molecular structure, which depends on electromagnetism, gravitation, the weak and strong forces, and so on an so forth, all simultaneously, all here and now. The actualization of one potential depends on the simultaneous actualization of another, which depends on the simultaneous actualization of another, which depends
on the simultaneous actualization of
another, which depends on ...
How far can it go? Not
that far, actually; certainly not to infinity. For what we
have here is an essentially ordered causal series, existing here and now... And an essentially ordered
series, of its nature, must have a first member. All the later members of such a series exist at all (and have
sufficient actuality to actualize the next member in the series) only
insofar as the earlier ones do, and those earlier ones
only insofar as yet earlier ones do; but were there finally no first
member of the series, there'd be no series at all in the first place, because
it is
only the first member which is in the
strictest sense really doing or actualizing anything. The later members are mere instruments,
with no independent, actualizing power of their own.
Think of my bicycle chain example. Since each link is move the next link, but NO link has the power to move unless it is given the power to move from something
else, no link can be the ultimate
source of motion. There must be an ultimate source of motion
(prime mover) for there to
be any intermediate movers. There can be no series of intermediary movers without a prime mover. Otherwise we would
have an impossible regress of movers/ causes/
beings.
The first mover in such a series
must be itself not only be unmoved (or uncaused or necessary) because if it were moving is would be moving from potential to actual.
But as we have noted, for something to move from potential to actual
requires an actuality outside the changed thing. In which case it wouldn't be the
first mover. And
we're back where we started. Thus the prime mover is pure actuality (pure "act). (God has no potential
:-) He/It is not only
unmoved, He/it is unmovable. The only way to stop this regress of actualizers who receive their power to actualize from outside themselves is to arrive
at a first member of the series
is with a being whose
existence does not need to be actualized by anything else.
The series can only
stop, that is to say, with
a being that is pure actuality (or "Pure Act," to use
the Scholastic phrase), with no admixture of potentiality whatsoever. And having no potentiality to realize or actualize,
such a being could not possibly move or change. That a stone is moved by a hand via a stick, then -and more generally, that things change at all suffices to show that there is and must be a first Unmovable Mover or Unchangeable Changer.
Now, how you get from this to "God" Aquinas actually takes great pains
to demonstrate, but not in the
Via Quique Those who criticize him for making
an unwarranted leap from "Unmoved mover" to "... and that all men call God." simply haven't read him. But that's what happens when you only read
the Spark Notes.
Related to the Summa Bonum: {A slight
departure)
I think there is an important similarity to this
line of argument
and Aristotle/ Aquinas's argument for a "summa bonum" or "final good."
Aristotle arrives at his conception of the "good life" for a human (as a rational
being) by asking,
"What is the natural good for man?" that is, what all humans desire "for
its own sake" and not "for the sake of anything
else."
Here it is helpful to distinguish two kinds of "value[2]
1) Intrinsic Value: Something has intrinsic value if it is
valuable for itself and not merely for some other reason.
2) Instrumental Value: Something has instrumental value if it is valuable to means of some other end
(ex. money).
Aristotle points out that some things
we value because they are means to other ends. But it cannot
be that
everything is valued
(or have value) for some other reason for that would lead to
an infinite regress. If I value
"1" because it is an efficient means to "2," and I value
"2" because it's a means to "3" and so on, this "regress" must stop somewhere; It cannot be infinite. As above,, the
"intermediary" values have no value of their own, but derive all their value from some other source
(something outside themselves). But that means
that if I value anything at all right now
instrumentally (derivatively), then there must be something
I value intrinsically, right now. The thing of intrinsic value must exist simultaneously
with the thing(s) of instrumental value to bestow them with their instrumental
value. There must be some card holding the house of
cards up.
There must come a
point where I value "N" simply because it is
what it
is and
it has
the properties it has, and not merely
as a
means to some other
end.
In other words, in order to make sense of the whole "valuing" project, I
must posit a thing of intrinsic
value, and "final
good" or what Aquinas would
call.a "Summa Bonum." In the end, if I value
anything at all, I can be certain
that there is a Summa Bonum. The only question is: "What is
it?" Thus, if we value anything
at all there must be something we value intrinsically. And this thing (or things) of
intrinsic value is what motivates all our actions. This is a teleological view of human action. The idea is that thoughtful,
deliberate action is goal oriented.
But this system of goals cannot be an infinite series
(infinite regress). There must
be a Summa Bonum, a Final End of human action(s).
A Topography of Cosmological Arguments
The following are notes drawn from William Lane Craig's Historical and Critical Analysis of the Family of Cosmological Arguments. You will recall
I mentioned that this tradition begins with Plato, received full development for the first time with Aristotle, was subsumed by the
Islamic philosophical/ theological tradition, imported back into Western Europe by way of Jewish and Christian philosophers and theologians. Leibniz's version
marks an important continuation of and yet
a break from this tradition. Despite the formidable challenges raised by David Hume and Immanuel Kant,
not only to Cosmological Arguments, but to the very possibility of metaphysics in general, Cosmological Arguments have
contemporary defenders, not the least of which is William Lane Craig.
PART II : CRITICAL CHAPTER
IX
My Notes
A TYPOLOGY OF COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS
Attacks of Hume and Kant mark a watershed in the history of
the cosmological argument. ushered in "modern era" of the
cosmological argument
Arthur Schopenhauer: Kant had dealt a "death
blow" to the cosmological argument2 Proposes a common criterion
"by which all or most of the arguments
can be categorized."
2 Arthur Schopenhauer, "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, " in Two Essays by Arthur
Schopenhauer (London: George Bell & Sons, 1889),
pp. 42,146.
Three types:
1)
Those that maintain the impossibility of an infinite
temporal regress,
Kaalam proofs for the beginning of the
world and the existence of a Creator.
2)
Those that maintain
the impossibility of an infinite
essentially ordered regress,
Aquinas's three ways: proofs from motion,
causality, and possible and necessary being
those that have no reference to an infinite
regress at all.
3) Leibniz's
version
No reference to infinite
regress, but seeks a sufficient reason for all things.
Alternative sorting: the basic principle on which they operate
and by which the existence of God is inferred.
Such a criterion
produces three types:
·
arguments based on the principle
of determination,
·
arguments based on the
principle of causality,
·
arguments based
on the principle of sufficient reason.
The first type is again the Kalam arguments
The second the Thomist arguments
The third the
Leibnizian argument.
"Failure to appreciate their demarcation not
only leads to an incorrect understanding of the historical
versions, but also conceals the crucial fact that one type may be impervious to
a criticism that is fatal to another."
Beware of sloppy amalgamations of
the different types of the argument. Quotes William L. Rowe as an unfortunate
example:
"The proponents of the Cosmological Argument
insist that the fundamental principles appealed to in the argument are necessary truths, known either
directly or by deduction
from other a priori principles that are known directly.... Such a
principle... is the Principle of Sufficient Reason, the pivot
on which the cosmological argument turns. There are a number of versions or forms of the Cosmological Argument. Apart from the
versions in Plato or Aristotle, which represent the early beginnings of the argument, the most forceful and, historically,
the most significant versions of the argument
appeared in the writings of Aquinas and Duns Scotus in the thirteenth century and in the writings
of Leibniz and Samuel
Clarke in the eighteenth century "
Criticisms
that may be definitive against
one version of the argument
may turn out to be utterly
irrelevant to some other important version.
On the other hand, all versions
of the argument
rely on some form of the
Principle of Sufficient Reason.3
William L. Rowe, The Cosmological
Argument (Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press, 1975),
Craig cites lots of
others who make similar mistakes.
Rowe's conclusion might nevertheless be true: the principle of causality is a specific form
of the principle of sufficient
reason.4
Nevertheless, misleading
But:
Defenders of the Thomist
argument maintain an essentially
ordered infinite regress of causes simply cannot exist.
Leibnizian versions would suggest rather that such a series "would yield no ultimate explanation..."
For instance, Rowe and others suggest that Scotus and-Aquinas reject an infinite
regress because it does not ultimately explain anything.
But this is a misread: Aquinas {et al.) is claiming that "an essentially ordered, infinite
causal regress cannot exist, not just that it cannot explain anything."
"Joseph Owens is at pains to emphasize
that Aristotle begins with sensible things, asks for causes, and proceeds to an ultimate cause of the world; he is not seeking abstract reasons, but physical causes."6
This is because in such an impossible series no actual motion would ever occur.
The point of each of Aquinas' s three ways is not
"that the effect would exist unexplained, but that it would not exist at all."
Craig and others have suggested that, ironically, Thomists themselves are partly to blame for this misinterpretation
as they, over the years, "gradually assimilated the
Leibnizian-Wolffian emphasis on sufficient reason
so that the Thomist and Leibnizian*arguments became
blended together."7
Problematic because it wrongly
implies
that
by denying the principle of sufficient
reason one has
thereby undercut all versions of the cosmological argument.
4 For this view, see Bruce Reichenbach, The Cosmological Argument: A Reassessment (Springfield, II.: Charles C. Thomas, 1972), PP.
s Rowe, Argument, pp. 32-38,48-50.
6 Joseph Owens, The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian "Metaphysics," 2d ed. (Toronto, Canada: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval
Studies, 1963), pp. 172,174.
7 Edwin Gurr, The Principle
of Sufficient Scholastic Systems., 1750-1900 {Milwaukee:
Marquette University
Press, 1959), pp. 15,48-49.
Even if one were to accept the possibility of an "explanatory ultimate" for which no reason can be given
"... it does not touch the Thomist
proof for it concerns causes, not reasons,
and it does not depend on everything's having
a cause, but specifically
aims at reaching an uncaused
cause. Moreover, while one may toss off the principle
of sufficient reason as false, it is not so easy to
deny honestly the principle of causality."
Further, one must carefully distinguish between the two principles to see that
Thomas is not suggesting a "self-caused being," a notion...
"caricatured by Schopenhauer as being like Baron
Munchhausen pulling himself and his steed out of the water by his
pigtails."8
Leibniz 's argument
concludes to a being which is self-explained.
Thomas's argument concludes
to being which is uncaused.
Neither is arguing for a
being that is SELF-caused.
Must, therefore, keep the principle of causality distinct
from the principle of sufficient reason
and recognize that in the Thomist and Leibnizian proofs
we 'have two distinct' types of cosmological argument.
It is also important to keep the Kalam proof distinct from the
above two, although it suffers
more from being ignored than being misconstrued.
One might regard the Kalam proof as based, along with the
Thomist argument, on the principle of causality. But this is inadequate, for the
cause of the world to which the
Kalam argument concludes is
"not just a mechanically operating set of
necessary and sufficient conditions, but a
personal agent who chooses by an act
of the will which of two alternative
options --universe or no universe-- will
be realized.
As A. J. Wensinck emphasizes,
"If the world
was produced, that signifies therefore that it did not exist-*at some time and that it came to be afterwards. It is not permitted, therefore, to
conceive of the production of the world by God as the production of the effect by, the cause: God is not cause,
but Creator.9
Craig argues (that
the Kalam argument demonstrates) that the creator of the world cannot be a
"mechanistic force," but rather must be personal and create with freewill. This is because
for mechanistic forces, the (total)
cause is sufficient for the effect and thus,
and thus would be contemporaneous with the effect. It could
not exist without its effect.
In that case,
there could be no "beginning to the world"
if the world is the contemporaneous effect of an eternal God's sufficient causal force. But a personal
being who freely chooses
to create the world might
exist without the world (i.e. "before" he creates it). Thus, while the cause/creator/total sufficient cause of the world is eternal,
the world/ effect is not.
8 Schopenhauer, "Fourfold Root," p. 17.
9 A.. J. Wensinck, "Les preuves
de existence de Dieu dans la
theologie musulmane," Mededeelingen
der KoninkZijke van Weten-81 (1936): 47-48. sch
"The principle of determination
is not, therefore,
reducible to the principle of causality simpliciter. Such a reduction would rob the Kalam argument of its interesting distinctive features: the necessity of a personal agent who freely chooses
between the equally possible and competing
alternatives."
"The Kalam argument is thus,
along with the Leibnizian and Thomist
proofs, a distinct type of cosmological argument.
[1] Unless you believe, you will not understand. Isaiah 7:9
[2] "The practice of every art and every kind of inquiry, and likewise every intentional act and every purpose, seems to aim at some good; and so we may say that 'The Good" is that at which everything aims. But a difference is observable among these aims or ends. What is aimed at is sometimes the exercise of a faculty, sometimes a certain result beyond that exercise. And where there is an end beyond that act, there the result is better than the exercise of the faculty. Now since there are many kinds of actions and many arts and sciences, it follows that there are many ends also; (e.g. health is the end of medicine, ships of shipbuilding, victory of the art of war, and wealth of economy.) But when several of these are subordinated to some one art or science. -as the making of bridles and other trappings are to the art of horsemanship, and this in tum, along with all else that the soldier
does, to the art of war, and so on, -then the end of the master art is always more desired then the end of the subordinate arts, since these are pursued for its sake. And this is equally true whether the end in view be the mere exercise of a faculty or something beyond that, as in the above instances.
...If then in what we do there be some end which we wish for on its own account, choosing all the others as a means to this (not every end without exception as a means to something else, for we should go on ad infinitum, and desire would be left void and objectless), -this evidently will be the good or the best of all things.