Experience, Art and Understanding

                                                                                                                    

 

A Brief Detour:  Locke’s Causal Theory of Perception

 

John Lock (1632 -1704) was one of the three “British Empiricists” of the Enlightenment period. 

 

In classical empiricism, the mind is seen as passive:

 

John Locke: the mind is a “tabula rasa”.  (Blank Slate)

David Hume (1711 – 1776) refers to mental items as “impressions.”

Bertrand Russell (1872 – 1970) talks of “bare particulars”

 

Note: the passive metaphors they use.  This is not the first nor the last time that an unhelpful metaphor for understanding impeded scientific progress.  The impression  (humor intended here) that this leaves is that the mind “simply” receives information during experience, that perception is a matter of just “seeing what’s really there.”  Knowledge, then, is a matter of clearly and objectively as possible perceiving the “given.”

 

You cannot get much more passive than being an inert rock.  So, Locke’s metaphor for mind, a tabula rasa, is as passive as you can get.

 

So then for Locke (and Classical Empiricism generally):

 

          The only way to come to know the world is through sensory experience.

          We start life with a blank slate, "tabula rasa."

          Points out that

1.    there is the world … and …

2.    there are our ideas about the world. 

(This put him, somewhat, in league with Descartes.  It raises some of the same skeptical worries as it did for Descartes, about how reliably our perceptions provide to us accurate information about the world “as it really is.”  …Think “Matrix” type worries here.[1])

 

·         The world causes our ideas about/ perception of it.

 

But on this model, the mind contributes nothing to this “received” information.  The experience comes pre-structured and prepackaged.  It is a “given” and clear accurate perception (knowledge) depends upon having an ”innocent eye,” seeing the objective truth; seeing all and only what is “really there.”[2]

 

But…

 

As widespread as this view of experience became and as influential as this view was and continues to be, is it accurate?  Immanuel Kant and post-Kantian philosophers suggest the answer is a definitive, “No.” 

 

All experience is mediated by Active Mind

 

This was not appreciated until relatively recently.  (The myth of the “given” and the “innocent eye” still persist today.)

 

Immanuel Kant and Active Mind

 

Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804) marks an important development in Philosophy and conceptions of “Mind.”  At this point in the history of Western philosophy, two great opposing traditions had come to an impasse of sorts: Rationalism and Empiricism had both seemed inadequate to account for human knowledge.  Rationalism seemed unable to account for knowledge of our world of experience.  Conversely, Empiricism seemed unable to account for the necessary truths of math and geometry or even the universality of the laws of nature.  Taken to their logical extremes, both epistemological orientations seemed to end in skepticism (either Descartes’s or Hume’s).   Kant’s solution to the impasse was to revision the very nature of knowledge and experience.  The key Kantian insight is that the mind does not merely receive information in the act of perception; rather the mind shapes that information and constructs experience out of the raw sense data it receives.  This is sometimes referred to as Kant’s “Copernican Revolution” in Epistemology.  Rather than asking “Is knowledge/ understanding possible?” Kant asksHow is it that knowledge/ understanding is possible?” Rather than asking “How does knowledge impress itself onto mind?” (passive metaphor) Kant asks “How does mind construct knowledge?”

 

To accurately account for what is going on in perception it is necessary to see human experiences as having different content, but a consistent “form.”  If we were to abstract all content from human experience we would arrive at the pure form of experience.  Think of it as blank template into which mind pours all sensory information and thus arrives at a coherent experience.  Alternatively think of my (very old, MS DOS based) Maillist program that can organize records according to one and only one pattern.  No matter what data it receives, it will always organize them in the same fashion according to a single basic template. In this case it was:  Field 1: First Name, Field 2: Last Name, Field 3: Telephone Number, Field 4: Street Address.  Whether the data are for my mom, my sister, the guy I knew from high school, etc.,  the record was always be: First Name, Last Name, Telephone Number, Street Address. Thus I have knowledge of how my 100th record and any other record will look (in broad outline) in advance of actually reviewing the 100th record. 

 

That is, I have a priori knowledge of the 100th record.  I know what the first field of my 100th record is for instance:  First Name.  My knowledge is not grounded in the particular experience of my 100th record, though it is grounded in experience in general.  After I get used to my program, and I have seen record after record after record, I can see the records as having a consisting form with differing content.  Now, I cannot make this distinction until I have looked at the program’s records.   In fact, I cannot make this distinction until after I have look at quite a few.  So, my knowledge of the 100th record arises from my experience with the program, though it is not grounded in the experience of my 100th record per se.  Further, I do not, nor could I know what the CONTENT of the record is; but I do know its form.  I know the form because when I am referring to this program’s “records,” I am referring to products of its organizing function which does not/ cannot change.

 

In like manner, Kant claims that claims at after long experience we can make a similar separation between the varying content of our experiences and their common form. All our experiences of the world will be of an “external” “extended: reality that obeys the laws of Euclidian 3-dimensional space.  (E.g., the shortest distance between two points is a straight line.)  All our experiences of the world will be temporally sequential as well.  These necessary and universal features of our experiences are so, according to Kant, not because “That’s how the world really is,” but rather because that’s the only way human mind organizes experience.[3]

 

Another illustration of what Kant has in mind here can be seen in those “Magic Eye” posters.[4]  At one moment they look like flat two-dimensional images.  The next they look like a three-dimensional image.  What is different from one moment to the next?  Is the poster giving you something different when it looks two dimensional from what it is giving you when it looks 3 dimensional?  No.  What is different is what YOU are doing, the activity of you mind in perception.  But this is just a more noticeable example of what the mind does constantly.  The reason you see reality as three-dimensional is NOT because “that’s how the world really is,” but rather because that’s how your mind (and every other normal, healthy human mind) is shaping its sense data.  Theoretical physicists might talk of reality in multiple dimensions, but even they don’t perceive it that way.  They come to that understanding purely theoretically.  Perhaps aliens from outer space perceive reality in more dimensions.  Perhaps God perceives it that way.  But not humans.  Not now, not ever, says Kant.  We will always only “image” the world as three dimensional.  And the same thing goes for unidirectional time.

 

Kant is very specific about what these forms and categories of experience are, but I’ll only refer to a few for illustration purposes.

 

Space and Time are the two pure forms of experience according to Kant.

 

All human experience will/ must conform to 3-dimensional Euclidian Space.

All human experience will/ must conform to unidirectional time.  (Past to present to future).

 

Opens the door to Radical Relativism:

 

Kant believed that our (human) empirical knowledge was universal (NOT RELATIVE) because the pure forms of experience and the categories of thought were universal for all humans. Therefore, he was certain that what is true for one human is true for all humans.[5] 

 

BUT....one might object to Kant’s view.

 

For instance, what if we do NOT all put the world together in basically the same way (e.g., woman according to a female template, men according to a male template)?  If “Men are from Mars and women are from Venus” then we are not experiencing the same worlds because we are building our worlds, shaping our experience according to different templates.  We are, in a very real sense, living in different worlds, and truth must be relativized to groups of cognizers who possess the same template.  Rather than univalent, truth becomes bivalent or, perhaps, multivalent.  Truth is potentially as multifaceted as there are minds, and no basis would exist for claiming that any particular worldview was privileged among the plurality.[6]

 

20th Century Philosopher and Art Historian Applies to Art

 

Both Ernest Gombrich (1909 - 2001) and Nelson Goodman (1906-1998) represent 20th century thinkers who echo the key Kantian Insight: Mind is NOT passive in experience, but rather active.  This insight is crucial to understand what is going on in art, among a great many other things, they claim.  Nelson Goodman, like Kant, denies the simple/passive view of perception. (There are no “bare particulars;” there are no “innocent eyes.”)   The mind is active from the onset.  The shape and content of experience/perception depend on the work the mind does (focusing, past experience, expectations).  Perception is a matter of focusing, ignoring, overlooking, interpreting. Thus, there is no difference between perceiving and interpreting according to Goodman.

 

Ernst Gombrichno innocent eye

 

“The eye comes always ancient to its work, obsessed by its own past and by old and new insinuations of the ear, nose, tongue, fingers, heart, and brain.”[7]

 

It does not much mirror the world as take and make.

 

Goodman argued against the persistent myth of the “Pure Empirical Fact.”  Classical empiricism would claim that perception is “automatic,” non-cognitive, or minimally so, merely “biological.”  But Goodman insists that perception is NOT non-cognitive and that what we “see” is a direct result of what and how we’ve been trained to “read” the world.  His model for perception can clearly be seen in other modes of perception.  Consider wine tasting, X-ray reading, hearing bird calls, and art. Despite the fact that perception may (seem to) be automatic, there is nothing basic or given in perception.

 

Nelson Goodman admits that perception may indeed be automatic, but that does not mean passive. It does not mean inevitable. Consider the act of hearing a sentence spoken in your native language.  You cannot help but hear it as a sequence of intelligible (meaningful) sounds. Though this can be automatic, this is a learned, cognitive skill.  You are interpreting those phonemes whether your realize it or not.  And for those with poor command of the language, it takes effort.  But for those with good command over the language it is “second nature.”  Automatic perhaps, but nevertheless learned and acquired actively.

 

For another example, think of visually ambiguous images, specifically the “Duck/Rabbit.” 

 

 

This phenomena shows why the old model of passive perception is inadequate for understanding how perception works.  For Locke, he thought it was enough to talk about the object, the perceiving organ and the perception.  On this view the object “impresses” itself on the mind and the mind is simply the inert passive recipient of the information.

 

 

We can complicate this simple model a bit by talking about the object, the organ, the retinal image, and the perception.  But again, on this model, the perception is understood as the inevitable product of the retinal image.  Mind plays no active role.

 

 

But in the case of ambiguous images, the poverty of this view is revealed.  In the case of the “Duck/Rabbit” image, I can see a duck or I can see a rabbit, that is I can have the duck-perception or the rabbit-perception and which perception I have cannot be explained in terms of the object, the organ or the retinal image.  When I have the duck-perception, the object, the perceiving organ and the retinal image are the same  as when I have the rabbit-perception.     There must be some other factor that explains the difference in perception, and that factor is the activity of mind.  The old Lockeian model of mind simply cannot account for the phenomena.

 

 

After Kant theorists argue against passive accounts of mind and knowledge and emphasizes the role of the faculty imagination in the formation of experience. This opened the door to the position that there is not merely one right way to experience or to know.  If our experience of the world is a product of what the world gives us and what we do with it (how we “image” it) then it follows that there may be as many different experiences of the world as there are “imagers” and no one is in a privileged position with respect to its rivals.

 

This realization gave rise to the Post-modernists’ notion that there is no one point of view from which Truth can be determined. Imagine two groups of people, one who could only see the duck and one that could only see the rabbit.  Which group is seeing what is “really there” and which group is wrong?  Well of course we see in this example that there is no reason to think that either group is privileged here.  Further, the only reason we could have to say that one of them has truth and the other has falsehood and is not seeing the world “correctly” would be to advance a political, economic or social agenda.

 

Perception: 8 Gestalt Principles and Bottom-Up verses Top-Down Processing

 

1. Distal and Proximal Stimuli vs. Percepts

 

The root of Distal is clearly related to the English word distance, and should, I hope communicate the idea that this it the "outside" stimulus.

 

Proximal essentially means "near" or "close to", and that root is also used in the English word approximate, which basically means "to make or come close to".

 

The term Percept comes from the same root that has a concrete meaning of "to catch" or "caught". Pretty clearly, it's what we end up with, an identity that we can use in further processing.

 

Distal and Proximal Stimuli vs. Percepts

 

When you see somebody walking down a hallway away from you, you don't think that the person is shrinking, despite the fact that the image on your retina is doing precisely that. Further, if the person were shrinking, the image on your retina would be pretty much the same, but you would likely misinterpret it as the person is moving away for you.

 

Why?

 

Well, one explanation is that because we have adapted to live in the real world and in the real world that sort of visual simulation is far more often tied to objects retreating from you rather than staying in a fixed position and shrinking.  This, in effect, is a perceptual heuristic.

 

Heuristic: a strategy for organizing a great deal of information quickly via a “rule of thumb” where examining each datum individually is not practical.  These are used to control and facilitate problem solving (in human beings and machines).

 

Our visual systems must be able to construct depth information from the 2-d image that falls on our retina. This requires a perceptual heuristic which Gestalt theory refers to as “size constancy.”   We find depth “cues” and use them to interpret the retinal image and come up with a depth-independent size.   We automatically judge the object of our perception to be remaining the same size.  This “assumption” is what allows us to further judge its relative speed, location and trajectory. 

 

These heuristics a valuable under “normal" life circumstances, but they allow us to set up all sort of peculiar illusions under “abnormal” circumstances.

 

For instance, given two circles of the same size, one surrounded by large circles and the other by small circles, the circle surrounded by small circles will appear to be larger.  This is because our visual system uses the size of the surrounding "context" circles as a relative depth cue. Because the circle with smaller surrounding circles is judged farther away, the size of the circle itself must be larger.

 

A similar situation happens with the so-called Ponzo Illusion:

 

The presence of a “vanishing point” is suggested by an acute angle.  It can be enough to make us perceive a size difference, even between lines of equal length when they differ in distance from the angle.

 

In both cases, the sizes of the retinal images for the shapes involved are identical (the proximal stimuli are identical) but our visual system gives us the percept that the two shapes differ in size.  Since under normal circumstances the presumed distal stimulus in a three-dimensional scene is further presumed to be larger.

 

 

2. Gestalt Principles (Seven)

 

1. Similarity (Perceptual Grouping)

 

Similar objects tend to be perceived as “grouped together.”  Similar” is understood across one or more dimensions (such as color, shape, orientation, and other simple visual features).

 

dotsim

Note that this image is seen as columns of circles and squares (rather than rows of “circle, squares”).

 

To explain this we must refer to what we are doing with the image, not merely “what it there.”

 

2. Proximity (Perceptual Grouping)

 

Objects that are closer together are perceived as forming a “group.”

 

proxdot2

Here this is seen as rows, not columns.

 

proxdot2

Interesting (aesthetically?) things happen, however, when similarity and proximity work against each other.

proxdot1 dots

 

In the last of the three, the images strikes us as neither/both rows or columns. 

 

3. Good Continuation (Perceptual Grouping)

 

Objects or pieces of objects (especially edges and other line segments) are grouped together to the extent that we can "trace" a good continuation between the pieces. The Kaniza triangle illusion is a classic example of this.

 

 

Kaniza Illusion

Kaniza Illusion

 

 

Name the beginning and ending points of the lines here.

 

 

 

More than likely you named a/b and c/d NOT a/c or a/d.

 

 

4. Closure (Perceived Object Shape)

 

Essentially a form of Good Continuation; there is a tendency to "close up" the boundaries of objects even when there are small gaps or openings.

 

 

 

Here we tend to see three broken rectangles (and a lonely shape on the far left) rather than three 'girder' profiles (and a lonely shape on the right). In this case the principle of closure cuts across the principle of proximity, since if we remove the bracket shapes, we return to an image used earlier to illustrate proximity...

 

 

5. Symmetry (Perceived Object Shape)

 

Everything else being equal, we prefer to group objects so as to make symmetrical forms rather than asymmetrical forms.   The symmetrical areas tend to be seen as figures against asymmetrical backgrounds.

 

 

 

6. Smallness

 

Smaller areas tend to be seen as figures against a larger background. In the figure below we are more likely to see a black cross rather than a white cross within the circle because of this principle.

As an illustration of this Gestalt principle, Coren, Ward and Enns (1994, 377) argue that it is easier to see Rubin's vase when the area it occupies is smaller. The lower portion of the illustration below offers negative image versions in case this may play a part. To avoid implicating the surroundedness principle I have removed the conventional broad borders from the four versions. The Gestalt principle of smallness would suggest that it should be easier to see the vase rather than the faces in the two versions on the left below.

 

 

Then there is the principle of surroundedness, according to which areas which can be seen as surrounded by others tend to be perceived as figures.

 

Now that we are in this frame of mind, interpreting the image shown above should not be too difficult. What tends to confuse observers initially is that they interpret the white area as the ground rather than the figure. If you couldn't before, you should now be able to discern the word 'TIE'.

 

7. Common Fate (Perceptual Grouping and Perceived Object Shape)

 

Objects are grouped together to the extent that they are perceived as "traveling" together. This is most literally true when they are all moving in the same direction or along some common path.

 

8. Pragnanz  The over-riding law of Gestalt Grouping is that we group objects to obtain the "best" or most parsimonious interpretation. Unfortunately, this term is very hard to translate from the German.

 

Top-down vs. Bottom-up processing

 

We must get clear on the distinction between top-down and bottom-up processing.

 

The notion of "bottom-up” implies effects seen early in processing, where our previous experience or acquired conceptual frameworks about the world plays little role.

 

For abilities like object recognition, word recognition, and face processing, however, our previous experience and acquired arsenal of concepts is not only very important, but influences our perception; This then is top-down processing.

 

Interestingly, top-down effects are most clearly seen when they are absent. The very same arrangements of chess pieces on a game board (or even the pattern of Xs and Os in a game of tic-tac-toe) are actually either perceived as meaningful units (for an expert who has background learning which admits a meaningful interpretation) or as random (for one who lack such a background).

 

Because of the role that the Gestalt plays, knowledge, perception and memory are affected.  Notice that knowledge, perception and memory for meaningful configurations are superior to that for random ones.

 

Similar effects can be measured for the ability to recognize crudely scrawled letters or mumbled phonemes when they occur in the context of a word or “meaningful” sentence.  This is why people were able to “hear” all sort of things when music recordings were played in reverse (back-masking).  It misses the point to ask, “But is that really what’s there?” since the implication of the research is that it’s never “there,” but only up here (I’m pointing to my cranium now.)

 

 



[1] http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=WnEYHQ9dscY

 

[2] Hamlet Act 3 scene 4

 

HAMLET

How is it with you, lady?

 

GERTRUDE

Alas, how is it with you,

That you do bend your eye on vacancy

And with the incorporal air do hold discourse?

120Forth at your eyes your spirits wildly peep,

And, as the sleeping soldiers in the alarm,

Your bedded hair, like life in excrements,

Starts up and stands on end. O gentle son,

Upon the heat and flame of thy distemper

125Sprinkle cool patience. Whereon do you look?

 

HAMLET

On him, on him! Look you, how pale he glares!

His form and cause conjoined, preaching to stones,

Would make them capable.

(to GHOST) Do not look upon me,

130Lest with this piteous action you convert

My stern effects. Then what I have to do

Will want true colortears perchance for blood.

 

GERTRUDE

To whom do you speak this?

 

HAMLET

Do you see nothing there?

 

GERTRUDE

Nothing at all, yet all that is I see.

[3] Note the necessity and universality of the common features among the mail list database is not explained by saying “Well that’s how the records “really are.”  The consistence is due to the single organizing function of the program in question.  Another program might organize the data according to quite a different template and yield radically different records.  Neither of the programs would be getting it “right” or getting it “wrong,” although one program might be more useful for certain purposes than the other.

[4] I am referring to autostereograms or single-image stereograms, which create the visual illusion of a three-dimensional image from a two-dimensional image. See: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Magic_Eye

 

[5] Now God or aliens from another planet may have very different forms of experience and thus different knowledge and truths, but the human task of inquiry doesn’t involve them- not yet at least.  Therefore, these are merely speculative concerns, not practical ones about which Kant, scientists or you and I need to worry.

[6] Some of this figures into and can even be used to justify certain claims arising from post-modernism.

[7] Nelson Goodman’s Languages of Art, p. 7)