Cosmological Arguments: Vertical

St. Thomas Aquinas (1225 – 1274)

 

Cosmological Argument: an a posteriori[1] (empirical, dependent on experience) argument which attempts to prove the existence of God by claiming that God is a (transcendent) theoretical entity needed to cause or explains[2] some observable feature of the world.

 

William Lane Craig is a contemporary philosopher who champions the Kalam version of the Cosmological argument.  This version relies on the premise that the universe is NOT infinitely old, but rather it is only finitely old.  Thus, it is NOT a “vertical” type of cosmological argument, but rather an “horizontal” type of cosmological argument. (I am imagining a horizontal timeline extending from the present backward to some finite point in the past.  The Kalam argument suggest that since the universe cannot be infinitely old, it must have had a “beginning” in time and thus a creator.)

 

Kalam: William Lane Craig’s formulation/ video production: http://www.reasonablefaith.org/kalam?src=email

 

But Thomas Aquinas’s version does NOT rely on the notion that the universe is only finitely old (contra Kalam).  Aquinas is willing to accept, for argument’s sake, that the universe is eternal with no beginning in time.  As a Christian, Aquinas does not believe this of course.  As a matter of faith, he believed that the universe was created by God at some point in the finite past.  However, Aquinas, did not think that this could be proven philosophically[3][4][5] and so he does not use this claim in his versions of the cosmological argument.

 

The early modern philosopher Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646 -1716) offers a cosmological argument that is more of an epistemological argument.  He is reasoning to the thing he believes necessary to explain the world.  He suggests that the proposition “The Universe exists.” is true and is not a self-explanatory proposition.  Since the world is not self-explanatory, there must exist something that is.

 

But Thomas Aquinas’s versions do not rely on The Principle of Sufficient Reason (contra Leibniz et al.).  St. Thomas Aquinas’ cosmological arguments are traditional metaphysical arguments.  He is reasoning to the thing which causes the world (NOT the reason that explains the world a-la- Leibniz).  The world is not “self-caused.” (Indeed, nothing is or could be.)  Therefore, it must be caused by something that is uncaused.  And this uncaused cause must exist simultaneously with its effects.  Thus, he offers “vertical” cosmological arguments.

 

It’s hard to do “a little Aquinas”

 

Most contemporary philosophers know that Aquinas believed that the existence of God, the immortality of the soul, and natural moral law could be established through purely philosophical arguments.  Nevertheless, often his arguments are very badly misunderstood by those philosophers.  William Lane Craig explains it this way in the opening paragraph of his chapter on Aquinas in Craig’s doctoral dissertation on the Cosmological Argument.

 

Underrated by non-Thomists and overrated by Thomists, Thomas of Aquino (1225-1274) is one of those philosophers whom nearly every­body quotes, but whom few understand.  Probably more ink has been spilled over his celebrated “Five Ways” for proving the existence of God than over any other demonstrations of divine existence, and yet they remain largely misunderstood today.  No doubt this is because these five brief paragraphs are so often printed in anthologized form and are therefore read in isolation from the rest of Aquinas's thought.  To take these proofs out of their context in Aquinas's thought and out of their place in the history of the development of these arguments will tend only to obscure the true nature of these proofs.  A proper understanding of Thomas's proofs necessitates read­ing them in their immediate context, ferreting out of his other works the basic epistemological and metaphysical principles they presuppose, comparing them to similar versions which Aquinas formulated else­where, and relating them to their historical context, particularly to the proofs propounded, by Aristotle, the Arabic philosophers, and Maimonides. Few modern philosophers of religion who are not already committed Thomists seem to have sufficient interest in the thought of a medieval theologian for such an admittedly arduous task.  But this can only result in neglect of Aquinas's important contributions to the philosophy of religion or to shallow expositions of his thought, mingled with positive misunderstandings.

 

In time, the work of Aristotle waned in influence with much of his work falling into obscurity in the West.  By contrast, his teacher Plato became the more influential philosopher.  Over the next several centuries Plato's philosophy grew into a kind of a new religion called "Neo-Platonism."  This world view stressed all the major themes of Plato: the mind/body dualism, the supremacy of the intellect, the frail and corrupting nature of "the body."  But it also added the idea that one might be able to achieve a "mystical" union with permanent transcendent reality through meditation and reflection.

 

Plato and Neo-Platonism were widely influential in the Mediterranean, especially in the early Christian communities.  First Century Jewish theologians living in Alexandria seemed to have been influenced by these views as were early Christians.  Notice in the Book of John in the New Testament we have Jesus identified with "The Word" of God (Gr. Logos).  This capitalizes on the earlier Jewish notion that God creates the world through spoken word.  Like Plato, this seems to identify spirituality with "Idea," Word, Law and Command.  The Greek equivalent is "Nous" or "Logos."  Philosopher and Church Father, St. Augustine (354 – 430) in particular, who was tremendously influential in the development of Christian Doctrine, credits Platonism with helping him understand and accept the Christian Religion.  He claimed that the most significant cause of his resistance and rejection of Christianity was his materialistic conception of God. (e.g. If God existed, He had to exist as a body, thus limited by space and time.)  Augustine credits Platonism with enlightening him from this "physicalism" by allowing him to conceive of immaterial spiritual reality. [6] 

 

All this to say that the early medieval period was highly Platonist/ Neo-Platonist in nature making it inhospitable for Aristotelean ideas.  Aristotle’s philosophy, by contrast, had fallen into neglect and disarray in the second generation after his death and remained in the shadow of the Stoics, Epicureans, and Academic skeptics throughout the Hellenistic age.

 

But, while Aristotle was lost to the Latin west of this period, he was not lost to Arab philosophers and theologians.  They had inherited Greek ideas once they conquered Egypt and they brought their translations and commentaries on Aristotle’s philosophy through the Arab West into Spain and Sicily by the later Middle Ages, which became important centers for this transmission of these ideas to the Neo-Platonic Christian West. The Arabic theologians and philosophers also brought with them the cosmological argument along with the legacy of Aristotle to the Latin West with principle encounters in Muslim Spain. Christians and Jews lived side by side with Muslims in Toledo, and it was inevitable that Arabic intellectual life should become of keen interest to them. A linchpin making this transmission possible was the Jews.  Hebrew was so close to Arabic that Jewish thinkers, many of them writing in Arabic, translated Arabic works into Hebrew and Latin. And the Christians in turn read and translated works of these Jewish thinkers.

 

But recall that Aristotle disagreed with much that Plato had taught.  This set up a challenge: How to make Aristotle’s Philosophy compatible with the established and dominant Neo-Platonist Christian theology.  Aquinas takes on this challenge.

 

Tries to synthesize:

 

1.       Christian Neo-Platonism (St. Augustine) & Pagan Aristotelianism

2.       Faith & Reason

3.       Theology & Philosophy

 

In general, Aquinas’ work sought to demonstrate that that if one is a good/efficient philosopher one can/will know that God exists.  Hence faith and reason, theology and philosophy, far from being antagonistic, actually complement each other.

 

His arguments for the existence of God fit nicely within this framework and are based on one originally drafted by Aristotle.

·         Aquinas works with a model originated by Aristotle.

·         Aristotle did not believe in a creation, but did argue for the existence of an unmoved mover.

 

Aquinas works this model into his “5 ways” Quinque Viae

 

Prefatory Remarks About the 1st Way: Argument from Motion

 

Both Aristotle and Aquinas talk of an unmoved mover. But the notion of movement was somewhat broader then we would understand it today.   Aristotle believed and Aquinas accepted that any change was a movement from potentially X to actually X.  For instance, if I have a pot of water that is actually cold, it is nevertheless potentially hot.  (It is hot in potency, though not in actuality.)  That is, it could be moved to being hot.  But to move it from potentially hot to actually hot, there must be something which moves it.  In other words, there must be something which actualizes the pre-existing potentiality. 

 

I will continue to reference movement since this is the word that Aquinas is using as did Aristotle. But bear in mind that each had a broader view.  Each has metaphysical commitments to doctrines of “potentiality and actuality.”  This means they were more talking about an unchanging changer or an unactualized actualizer.  Aquinas refers to God as pure act: Actus Purus.  God has no potential.  Imagine being God’s high school guidance counselor. 😊

 

First Argument ‑ Argument for Motion

 

The first and more manifest way is the argument from motion. It is certain, and evident to our senses, that in the world some things are in motion. Now whatever is in motion is put in motion by another, for nothing can be in motion except it is in potentiality to that towards which it is in motion; whereas a thing moves inasmuch as it is in act. For motion is nothing else than the reduction of something from potentiality to actuality. But nothing can be reduced from potentiality to actuality, except by something in a state of actuality. Thus that which is actually hot, as fire, makes wood, which is potentially hot, to be actually hot, and thereby moves and changes it. Now it is not possible that the same thing should be at once in actuality and potentiality in the same respect, but only in different respects. For what is actually hot cannot simultaneously be potentially hot; but it is simultaneously potentially cold. It is therefore impossible that in the same respect and in the same way a thing should be both mover and moved, i.e. that it should move itself. Therefore, whatever is in motion must be put in motion by another. If that by which it is put in motion be itself put in motion, then this also must needs be put in motion by another, and that by another again. But this cannot go on to infinity, because then there would be no first mover, and, consequently, no other mover; seeing that subsequent movers move only inasmuch as they are put in motion by the first mover; as the staff moves only because it is put in motion by the hand. Therefore it is necessary to arrive at a first mover, put in motion by no other; and this everyone understands to be God.[7]

 

1.       Begins with an observation.  (Viola! There are moved objects.)

2.       In order for any object to be moved it has to be moved by another.

a.       Both of these propositions are evident through experience.

 

Can it be an infinite system (no end)?

 

Yes…

For every moved object N, it is moved by another moved object N -1, which in turn is moved by another moved object N -2, and so on, and so on, and so on.

 

But…

 

Can this be the whole of the story where every mover is a moved mover?

 

No.

 

Imagine a bicycle chain that formed a circle. And we can only see a portion of the chain at a time. Notice in our imagined situation there is no first link. It is infinite in the sense that there is no end. No first and no last.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 


Each link in the chain is moving. And each link in the chain is moving and being caused to move by being pulled by the succeeding link. In other words, link A is moving because it's being pulled by link B which is moving because it's being pulled by link C etc.  If this were a chain with 10 links, then link J is moving because it's being pulled by link A.  So on this model, we know what the proximate cause is for each individual moving link. What we don't know however is what's causing the entire chain to move.

 

The links themselves have no ability to move other things on their own.  This ability must be transmitted to the links in the chain by something outside the chain (transcendent of the system) that does have the ability to move things.  Now that thing which is transmitting the ability to move things to the links is itself moved by something, and thus borrows this power from something else, or does not.  If it's borrowing its ability to move the bicycle chain links from something else, we have the beginnings of an infinite regress. The only thing that can stop the regress would be something that transmits the ability to move things, but does not need to borrow that ability from something else.  This is why Aquinas concludes that, in addition to the moved movers we observe on a daily basis, there must exist something we do NOT see, an unmoved mover.  Indeed, the very existence of moved movers confirms the existence of the unmoved mover.  There would be no motion at all were there not an underived source of motion, that is, an unmoved mover.

 

The suppositions that there only exist moved movers is unsatisfactory as an account of reality, since it leaves us with an “infinite regress” and irreducible mystery. 

 

Therefore:

 

3.       It cannot be that every moved object is moved by another moved object.

 

Well then that either leads us to the position that there are NO moved objects (absurd) or that some moved objects are moved by an unmoved mover which is radically different from that which we observe on a daily basis.  We observe the “links” in the chain (the moved movers), but this observation rationally compels us to hypothesize that which we do NOT directly observe, something radically different than the other moved objects, something outside the chain (transcendent). This outside mover-force Aquinas calls a Prime Mover and that is God.

 

The unmoved mover is “Prime” in the sense of being the current source of all current motion.  All the links exhibit derivative motion.  If there is derived motion than there must be a source of motion which is underived.

 

4.       Therefore there exists an Unmoved Mover.[8]

 

Now, as previously noted, while Aristotle and Aquinas are represented most frequently as arguing from literal “motion,” the argument can be fashioned with reference to any and all sorts of change.  A change is a “motion” from what a thing was to what it subsequently became.  But for a thing to be changed (e.g. move from potentially hot to actually hot) it must be changed/ moved by another (e.g. an actually hot fire).  But, since this is so, in addition to changing changers, there must be something which is actual, but did not and does not change. (An Unchanged changer.)

 

And of course Aquinas is surely delighted that this proof seems consistent with certain scriptural passages.

 

Every best gift, and every perfect gift , is from above, coming down from the Father of lights, with whom there is no change, nor shadow of evil.

James 1:17

 

God did this so that they would seek him and perhaps reach out for him and find him, though he is not far from any one of us. For in him we live and move and have our being.’

Acts 17: 27 & 28

 

Second Argument ‑ Argument from Causality

 

The second way is from the nature of the efficient cause. In the world of sense we find there is an order of efficient causes. There is no case known (neither is it, indeed, possible) in which a thing is found to be the efficient cause of itself; for so it would be prior to itself, which is impossible. Now in efficient causes it is not possible to go on to infinity, because in all efficient causes following in order, the first is the cause of the intermediate cause, and the intermediate is the cause of the ultimate cause, whether the intermediate cause be several, or only one. Now to take away the cause is to take away the effect. Therefore, if there be no first cause among efficient causes, there will be no ultimate, nor any intermediate cause. But if in efficient causes it is possible to go on to infinity, there will be no first efficient cause, neither will there be an ultimate effect, nor any intermediate efficient causes; all of which is plainly false. Therefore, it is necessary to admit a first efficient cause, to which everyone gives the name of God.[9]

 

1.       Begins with an observation.  (Voila! There are causes and effects.)

 

2.       Now every effect has its cause.  We know that some causes, indeed all the causes we witness, are the effects of some previous causes.  They are caused causes.

 

Could this chain of caused causes extend infinitely backwards in time?  Yes. says Aquinas,

 

(Brief Aside) Accidentally Ordered Causal Series and Essentially Ordered Causal Series

 

Aquinas and Dun Scotus, borrowing from Avicenna and Aristotle, say that causes may be ordered in two ways: essentially or accidentally.  As a case of essentially ordered causes the medievals typically gave the example of a man pushing a stone with a stick.  Accidentally ordered causes were continually exemplified by a father begetting a son, who in turn begets a son.

 

These two examples will serve for discussing the three differences which Scotus proposes between essentially and accidentally ordered causes:

 

1.       In essentially ordered causes, the second depends on the first precisely in the very act of causation. This is not so in accidentally ordered causes.

 

2.       In essentially ordered causes, there is causality of another nature or order, since the higher is more perfect. This is not so among accidentally ordered causes.

 

In a series of accidentally ordered causes, because they are all of the same kind, they happen to have to order that they do accidentally.  It is An accident of history that they enjoy the particular ordering that they do.. Their actual, historical order is accidental.  In other words,  it could be the hand pushing the stick that pushes the stone, but it could have just as easily had been the stick pushing the hand pushing the stone.  These are all derivative causal forces, and where the derivative cause derives its causal efficacy from the causal efficacy from its (accidental) causal predecessor.  This is what it means to say that they are all of the same order. They are all derivative causes.

 

3.       All essentially ordered causes are simultaneously required to cause the effect; accidentally ordered causes can be successive.

 

In terms of the two examples the differences are as follows:

 

First, in the very act of pushing a stone, the stick depends on the man to cause it to push; but while it is true that Isaac depends on Abraham for his existence, he requires no direct help from Abraham in begetting Jacob.

 

The second difference is clear.  There is a sense in which the hand-stick-stone “system “really form a single simultaneous moving system of intermediate efficient causes ultimately deriving their causal efficacies from the ultimate uncaused efficient cause, however distant it may be removed from the hand and the stick.  This ultimate cause is a different, superior, type of cause from which, ultimately, the hand and the stick derive the efficacy to posh the stone.  Abraham and Isaac, however, are both fathers; neither is a superior type or kind of cause.

 

Finally, the third difference is present in the examples, according to the medievals, because at the very moment the stick pushes, the man pushes with the stick.  As noted above, there is a simultaneous unity to the series of the intermediate derivative efficient causes.  Distinguishing the hand, the stick, and the stone are merely to distinguish nodes in a singular causal chain. They really do not exist as causal forces independent of one another.  By contrast, it is obvious that Isaac does not beget Jacob at the very moment Abraham begets Isaac.

 

Aquinas and other medievals suggested that accidentally ordered causes, might, for all Philosophy can tell,  regress to infinity.  But essentially ordered causes cannot.  They must terminate in a cause of a different and superior kind.  Arguments to show this were based on the three differences mentioned above.  For instance, consider the third difference: Since all essentially ordered causes are required simultaneously, if there were an infinite regress among them, there would, at one moment, be an actual completed infinite set of causes.  But the medievals felt Aristotle had shown this to be absurd. The existence of a completed infinite series is a metaphysical impossibility.  Therefore, there can be no infinite regress among essentially ordered causes.  The sequence must come to a stop at some first cause—which we call God. 😊

 

Thus a model consisting exclusively of caused causes would be unsatisfactory for precisely the same reason as before.  This model leads to an infinite regress.  Even an infinite chain of (intermediate derivative) caused causes requires a cause of a different order, i.e., that which provides causal efficacy without having to borrow it from some previous cause, in short, an uncaused cause.  Again we must suppose something radically different from the sort of causes we see on a daily basis, an Uncaused Cause, which causes the system of causality.  This something is radically different, transcendent, outside the system; A FIRST EFFICIENT CAUSE ‑ GOD

 

Third Argument ‑ Argument of Contingent Objects

 

The third way is taken from possibility and necessity, and runs thus. We find in nature things that are possible to be and not to be, since they are found to be generated, and to corrupt, and consequently, they are possible to be and not to be. But it is impossible for these always to exist, for that which is possible not to be at some time is not. Therefore, if everything is possible not to be, then at one time there could have been nothing in existence. Now if this were true, even now there would be nothing in existence, because that which does not exist only begins to exist by something already existing. Therefore, if at one time nothing was in existence, it would have been impossible for anything to have begun to exist; and thus even now nothing would be in existence--which is absurd. Therefore, not all beings are merely possible, but there must exist something the existence of which is necessary. But every necessary thing either has its necessity caused by another, or not. Now it is impossible to go on to infinity in necessary things which have their necessity caused by another, as has been already proved in regard to efficient causes. Therefore we cannot but postulate the existence of some being having of itself its own necessity, and not receiving it from another, but rather causing in others their necessity. This all men speak of as God.

 

I chose to render this argument of Aquinas as a Reductio ad Absurdum:

 

A redutio ad absurdum is an argument technique where one begins by assuming what one wishes to disprove and then shows how, by valid inference, it leads to an absurdly false claim.

 

We know from logic that, when a valid argument has a false conclusion, then at least one of the premises is false.   If we end with falsity, there must be falsity in our premise set, presumably the assumed premise we are seeking to discredit.

 

 

Premise

Justification

1

There are contingent objects.

Viola! (This rests on observation.)

2

Everything which exists is contingent.

Atheist Assumption #1- that there is no Necessary Being-

 

Of course, Aquinas does not believe this is true.  But does his belief in the existence of a Necessary Being rest only on his Christian Faith, or is it grounded in Reason as well?

3

Everything could go out of existence.

Follows from the conjunction of #1-Definition of Contingent & #2 that everything that exists is contingent.

 

4

All real possibilities occur in an infinite amount of time.

Metaphysical Principle-

 

It seems to follow from reason that, given enough time anything possible would happen. If after an infinite amount of time, it still hasn’t happened, then it was never really possible in the first place.

5

An infinite amount of time has occurred.

Atheist Assumption #2- If one does not believe in creation, then time stretches infinitely backwards because there is no beginning.  If there was no creation therefore the universe is infinitely old.

 

Of course Aquinas does not believe this is true.  But does his belief rest only on his Christian Faith, or is it grounded in Reason as well?

6

All real possibilities have occurred.

 

Follows from 4&5

7

Everything has gone out of existence. –Nothing exists.

Follows from 3&6

8

There are no contingent objects

Follows from 7

9

There are contingent objects and there are no contingent objects.

Conjunction of 1&8

 

The conclusion here is a logical contradiction, and thus, (absurdly) false.

 

When a valid argument has a false conclusion, then at least one of the premises is false.

 

Therefore, Aquinas says that there must be something which has necessary existence (premise 2 MUST be false).[10]  And that necessary being is GOD.

 

Principle of Sufficient Reason: (From William Rowe)

 

Rowe suggests that all cosmological arguments depend on the Principle of Sufficient Reason.  For what it’s worth, I agree that it is operative in Leibnizian type cosmological arguments, but not the other two kinds (i.e. Kalam and Aristotelian/ Thomistic)

 

Two Parts:

 

P.S.R =

 

a. there is an explanation for every object.

b. there is an explanation for every positive fact (why it is as it is and not other than it is).

 

Imagine the Universe is an eternal string of contingent objects (e.g. Chickens) so that history is an infinite series of contingent objects producing other contingent objects. (e.g. Chickens making chickens).  While every link in the chain would have an explanation, that is, while every contingent object would be explained by the model (satisfies PSR part “A”), there would still be something left unexplained by this model of reality, namely, “why is it that there are and always have been contingent objects (chickens)?”(PSR part “B”)  Thus, if PSR is true, then there must be a necessary being, in addition to the contingent beings we witness.

 

Essentially, this argument asks: “Why is there something rather than nothing?”

 

The (best/only) explanation is God:

 

The First Three of the Five Ways In Sum:

 

 

A Thomistic Reading

 

1.       System of objects exhibiting derivative motion can only exist given a source of motion which is not itself derivative.  Therefore, there must be some outside (transcendent) unmoved force-mover.

 

2.       System of objects exhibiting derivative causality can only exist given a source of causation which is not itself derivative. Therefore, there must be some outside (transcendent) uncaused cause.

 

3.       System of contingent objects (derivative being) can only exist given a source of existence which is not itself derivative. Therefore, there must be some outside (transcendent) necessary being.

 

A Leibnizian (PSR) Reading

 

1.       System of moved objects is not selfexplanatory therefore there must be some outside (transcendent) force-mover and that must be God.

 

2.       System of finite causality is not selfexplanatory therefore there must be some outside (transcendent) cause and that must be God

 

3.       System of contingent objects is not self-explanatory therefore there must be some outside (transcendent) object and that must be a necessary being God

 

We will not scrutinize the fourth and fifth ways here, but…

 

Fourth Argument – depends on there being objectively true comparative judgements.  Therefore there must be a best (Best).

 

Fifth Argument ‑ Teleological argument.  Universe exhibits intelligent direction, adherence to rational principle.  That can only be if it is directed by a being with intelligence and power, and that must be God.

 

His Fifth way is often interpreted as a sort of design argument similar to William Paley.  However, I do not believe that it is.  I see this as much closer to his others.  The universe (and objects in the universe) exhibit intelligence/ order/ Logos.  But this is a derived intelligence.  And if anything has derived intelligence, then there must be a source of underived intelligence to bestow it.

 

Objections to Cosmological Arguments in General and Aquinas’ Ways In Particular:

 

1. “Prime Mover,” “First Cause,” “Necessary Object”‑ Aquinas says we call these “God”, but taken individually, they certainly are not equivalent to the Theistic O-God.  Further, even taken jointly they may fall short of what religions teach.

 

Response:  Aquinas is trying to show, like any good empiricist, that it is more reasonable to believe in God, then to disbelieve or remain agnostic.  Given that we know the universe has a necessary source of being, movement and causality which is supremely good and intelligent, it is far more reasonable to be a theist than to be an atheist or to remain agnostic.

 

2. Principle of Sufficient Reason makes perfect sense when applied to objects and events within the universe.  But it makes no sense whatsoever when applied to the Universe itself as a whole.  The question “Why is there something rather then nothing?” is a pseudo-question and a category mistake.  It assumes that “the universe” belongs to the category of things with an explanation, but there is no reason to make that assumption.  We should accept the existence of the Universe as a Brute Fact.  If PSR is denied, specifically as a tool of metaphysics, the cosmological argument is defanged.

 

Jean Paul Sartre felt that the universe was "gratuitous" and Bertrand Russell claimed that the question of origins was tangled in meaningless verbiage and that we must be content to declare that the universe is "just there and that's all."

 

Response:  Why should we accept that the existence of the universe is indeed a brute fact?  Isn’t this an arbitrary stipulation manufactured just to avoid assenting to the existence of God?  Further, even some scientists are interested in asking –perhaps even answering the question: “Why is there something rather than nothing?”.  (e.g. The Grand Unification Theory Quest of some physicists.)

 

For instance Stephen Hawking once wrote:

 

“…if we do discover a complete theory, it should in time be understandable in broad principle by everyone, not just a few scientists. Then we shall all, philosophers, scientists, and just ordinary people, be able to take part in the discussion of the question of why it is that we and the universe exist. If we find the answer to that, it would be the ultimate triumph of human reason – for then we would know the mind of God.”[11] (emphasis added.)

 

Further still, it is not really clear that Aquinas’ argument turns on the Principle of Sufficient Reason.  Notice that Rowe invokes it, but Aquinas did not mention it.

 

3. Concepts like “move,” “cause,” “exist,” “time,” etc. are only concepts that arise from human intellect and perception and can only apply to human experience.  To try to apply these concepts to the world “as it is,” that is, to the world as uncategorized by the concepts of mind is illicit.  It is an attempt to use them outside their rightful/useful jurisdiction.

 

For instance, David Hume argues that causation is a psychological, not a metaphysical, principle, one whose origins lay in the human propensity to assume necessary connections between events when all we really see is constant conjunction, contiguity and succession.  If apparent causation is a psychological propensity and not an objective fact, then we cannot reason to an objective "Uncaused Cause."

 

Immanuel Kant echoes Hume here, somewhat, by arguing that causation is a category of thought built into our minds as one of the many ways in which we constitute our experience to ourselves. This has the same, familiar result of limiting the jurisdiction of "causality" to the realm of human-experience-reality only and not the mind-independent world. 

 

Response:  This is an objection to metaphysics generally, not an objection to the particular arguments per se.  As such, a full response would require a general defense of metaphysics as a legitimate form of inquiry.

 

Finally:

 

I found the place in the Critique of Pure Reason where Kant says that the cosmological argument is dependent on the ontological argument and can therefore be dismissed as the latter was.

 

Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God:

 

"But no ens realissimum is in any respect different from another, and what is valid of some is valid of all. In this present case, therefore, I may employ simple conversion, and say, every ens realissimum is a necessary being. But as this proposition is determined a priori by the conceptions contained in it, the mere conception of an ens realissimum must possess the additional attribute of absolute necessity. But this is exactly what was maintained in the ontological argument, and not recognized by the cosmological, although it formed the real ground of its disguised and illusory reasoning."[12]


Modern Versions (sort of):

 

The “Fine Tuning Argument”

 

There are various versions of this argument proposed with greater or lesser sophistication.  I will merely outline the nature of the argument below.  What intrigues me here is that they seem rather similar to Aquinas’ notions asking, if not “Why is there something rather then nothing?” they ask “Why is there this something rather then any of an infinite variety of equally possible somethings?”  Further, even if we cannot discover the answer to that, doesn’t the type of universe we have itself give us a clue as to what lies beyond the boundaries of empirical investigation?

 

Begins with observations: Our Universe, with its present complexity is a Life-friendly universe.  (Viola!)

 

But, the more we know about all the many variables that went into the “Big Bang” the more we should see that OUR Universe as “fine tuned” for “life-friendly.”  Altering any one of the variables that account for the development of our universe, even slightly would result in a universe devoid of complexity and therefore even the possibility of life.  For instance, were the rate of expansion even slightly faster, the universe would never have developed large clops of stuff (solar systems, galaxies, planets, etc.), but rather be an endlessly expanding cloud of hydrogen gas.  Or, say the rate of expansion were only infinitesimally slower, the universe would have simply collapsed back on itself seconds later.

 

1.       Let us assume that it is a fact that that this life friendly universe (and only this life friendly universe) exists is a positive fact. 

 

2.       Since PSR claims that every positive fact has an explanation (sufficient reason for why it is so) then PSR commits us to the idea that there is an explanation for why this life friendly universe exists. 

 

But notice, nothing within the life friendly universe can explain this fact, since any and all things (causes, forces, principles) within the universe are precisely what were trying to explain. 

 

3.       This being the case, only something radically different (transcendent) can explain it.  And that we call God, as Aquinas might say. 

 

Well, of course there is a logical gap between “That which explains the Life-friendly Universe” and  “Jehovah” et alia, but that reason and experience commits us to the notion of a transcendent cause of a life friendly universe supports a theistic view of reality more than an atheistic view of reality.  Put another way, a life friendly universe is just the sort of thing you would expect given theism, but have no particular reason to expect it given atheism.  (Buying a one-way airline ticket under an assumed name is just the sort of thing you’d expect the suspect to do if he were guilty, but you would have no particular reason to expect this if he were not guilty.)  Therefore, while such arguments may or may not demonstrate that a Fine Tuner is a necessary theoretical presupposition of observable fact, if successful they would demonstrate that (these) observable facts confirm the Theistic Model more than they confirm the Atheistic Model.

 



[1] So as to contrast it with ab a priori Ontological Argument.

[2] I noted there is a difference between reasoning to the thing which causes the universe and reasoning to the thing which explains the universe.  The former is the unquestioning metaphysical project of Aristotle, Aquinas and the pre-modern philosophers in general.  The latter is the more epistemological project of Leibnitz and modern philosopher following him, utilizing as they do, the Principle of Sufficient Reason.

[3] Aquinas believed that many of the claims of revelation can be proven true by philosophy.  These he refers to a “Preambles of Faith.”  (e.g. There is a God.) But some of the claims of revelation cannot be proven by philosophy.  These he referred to as “Articles of Faith.”  (e.g. God is triune.)  However, while an Article of Faith could not be proven true by philosophy, neither could they be proven false by philosophy and one of the responsibilities of Christian philosophers, according to Aquinas, was to expose the flaws in any argument purporting to disprove an Article of Faith.  In no way, therefore, did Aquinas think that faith conflicted with reason.

[4] It is not entirely clear to me why Aquinas did not believe that the temporal finitude of the universe could be proven philosophically.  He was aware of Kalam proofs, and these would have been more consistent with his Christian faith than Aristotle’s claim that the Universe was eternal.  Aquinas does claim, I believe, that there cannot exist an actual infinite set, one of the key tenants of the traditional Kalam argument.  But it may be that he did not think an infinite past would entail accepting the reality of a completed infinite series. If past moment ceases to exist after they expire, then a set of all (past moments) would never exist all at once.  Alternatively, it may have been that he simply did not want to suggest that Aristotle had been wrong about such a fundamental feature of the natural world. But this need not concern us here.

[5]  The kalam argument became popular among Islamic philosophers in the Middle Ages, but not so much among Catholics. One notable exception was St Bonaventure (1221 – 1274) .

[6] And it still seemed to me most unseemly to believe that thou couldst have the form of human flesh and be bounded by the bodily shape of our limbs. And when I desired to meditate on my God, I did not know what to think of but a huge extended body -- for what did not have bodily extension did not seem to me to exist -- and this was the greatest and almost the sole cause of my unavoidable errors. (Confessions, V, ch X, sec. 19)

 

… soon understood that the statement that man was made after the image of Him that created him[155] was not understood by thy spiritual sons -- whom thou hadst regenerated through the Catholic Mother[156] through grace -- as if they believed and imagined that thou wert bounded by a human form, although what was the nature of a spiritual substance I had not the faintest or vaguest notion. Still rejoicing, I blushed that for so many years I had bayed, not against the Catholic faith, but against the fables of fleshly imagination. For I had been both impious and rash in this, that I had condemned by pronouncement what I ought to have learned by inquiry. For thou, O Most High, and most near, most secret, yet most present, who dost not have limbs, some of which are larger and some smaller, but who art wholly everywhere and nowhere in space, and art not shaped by some corporeal form: thou didst create man after thy own image and, see, he dwells in space, both head and feet. (Confessions,  VI, Chapter V, sec 155)

(Confessions,  VI, Chapter V, sec 155)

 

….13. And first of all, willing to show me how thou dost "resist the proud, but give grace to the humble,"[184] and how mercifully thou hast made known to men the way of humility in that thy Word "was made flesh and dwelt among men,"[185] thou didst procure for me, through one inflated with the most monstrous pride, certain books of the Platonists, translated from Greek into Latin.[186] And therein I found, not indeed in the same words, but to the selfsame effect, enforced by many and various reasons that "in the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God. The same was in the beginning with God. All things were made by him; and without him was not anything made that was made." That which was made by him is "life, and the life was the light of men. And the light shined in darkness; and the darkness comprehended it not." Furthermore, I read that the soul of man, though it "bears witness to the light," yet itself "is not the light; but the Word of God, being God, is that true light that lights every man who comes into the world." And further, that "he was in the world, and the world was made by him, and the world knew him not."[187] But that "he came unto his own, and his own received him not. And as many as received him, to them gave he power to become the sons of God, even to them that believed on his name"[188] -- this I did not find there. (Confessions,  VII, Chapter IX, sec 155)

 

[7] Aquinas from Summa Theologica I, 2, iii)

[8] I prefer this designation to “Prime Mover” since it is less likely to give rise to the misperception that Aquinas it thinking about something that is temporally or sequential “first.”  He means rather something which is “Ontologically” dependent in that moved object would not exist (are ontologically depended upon) the Unmoved movers, but not the other way around.

[9] Aquinas from Summa Theologica I, 2, iii)

[10] Of course, one might claim that the false premise is not Atheist Assumption #1, but rather, Atheist Assumption #2.  If the universe is not infinitely old, then an infinite amount of time has not passed and it need not be the case that all real possibilities have occurred.  But to give up on Atheist Assumption #2 is to admit that the universe had a beginning in time, which seems just as good as saying that the universe had a creator/cause.

[11] Hawking, Stephen A Brief History of Time, p 175

[12] Kant, Immanuel, The Critique of Pure Reason 2016 John Miller Dow Meiklejohn (Translator) p340