Faith and Irrationality; Kierkegaard

 

Until the time of Kierkegaard philosophers pretty much presumed that we want/ ought to believe all and only what is rational.  (Anselm, Aquinas, (Pascal[1]*), Clifford, James, Kant, Advocates of the Problem of Evil).  Whether to believe in God was completely a rational decision.

 

In contrast, the Danish philosopher, Soren Kierkegaard (1813 – 1855), claims that belief in God is not, nor can it be rational, but that doesn’t make it a bad thing.

 

  • Religious faith is not nor can it ever be a “rational” matter
  • Kierkegaard referred to himself as an anti‑philosopher (Anti-Hegelian)
  • Brooded over the nature of “faith;” performs a sort-of conceptual analysis.

 

The time and country he lived in were largely Christian.  But his countrymen were complacent in their religious belief from Kierkegaard’s perspective; religious belief amounted to sort of a daily passionless habit.

 

When Kierkegaard claims to be an anti-philosopher, this is better understood as being an anti-Hegelian.  The philosophical system advanced by Georg Hegel (1770 – 1831) was widely popular and of growing influence during Kierkegaard’s lifetime.  In this system, the individual was of little or no importance.  The only significance the individual achieved was as an aspect of constantly unfolding Absolute Spirit.  Occasionally an individual would arise who embodied an important movement in the progress of history (a Napoleon, for instance,) but the vast majority of us, with our petty existence and daily trials and tribulations, are of no significance to the cosmic story of consciousness. This necessarily anonymizes the individual, mutes the individual, his struggles, choices, his uniquely lived life, his very existence-as-existing.

 

Further, while Hegel had taught that all apparent contradictions (the thesis with its antithesis) are subsumed into an evolving dynamic history, into a synthesis, Kierkegaard the individual, and on behalf of the individual, wanted to testify to the struggle of choice confronting the individual (Either/ or), choices which are unavoidable in any self-reflective, lived life.  As we shall see, we individuals, like Abraham from Hebrew scriptures, can resolve the conflict and paralysis only by making a choice.

 

Both of these factors contribute to Kierkegaard's analysis of “Faith.”

 

Also, it didn’t sit well with Kierkegaard that Hegel is philosophizing about Christianity while never seriously thinking about being or living as a Christian.

 

“It is the existing spirit who asks about truth, presumably because he wants to exist in it, but in any case, the questioner is conscious of being an existing individual human being. In this way, I believe I am able to make myself understandable to every Greek and to every rational human being.

If a German philosopher follows his inclination to put on an act and first transforms himself into a superrational something, just as alchemists and sorcerers bedizen themselves fantastically, in order to answer the question about truth in an extremely satisfying way, this is of no more concern to me than his satisfying answer, which no doubt is extremely satisfying - if one is fantastically dressed up.

 

But whether a German philosopher is or is not doing this can easily be ascertained by anyone who with enthusiasm concentrates his soul on willing to allow himself to be guided by a sage of that kind, and uncritically just uses his guidance compliantly by willing to form his existence according to it.

 

When a person as a learner enthusiastically relates in this way to such a German professor, he accomplishes the most superb epigram upon him, because a speculator of that sort is anything but served by a learner's honest and enthusiastic zeal for expressing and accomplishing, for existentially appropriating his wisdom, since this wisdom is something that the Herr Professor himself has imagined and has written books about but has never attempted himself.  It has not even occurred to him that it should be done.

 

Like the customers clerk who, in the belief that his business was merely to write, wrote what he himself could not read, so there are speculative thinkers who merely write, and write that which, if it is to be read with the aid of action, if I may put it that way, proves to be nonsense, unless it is perhaps intended only for fantastical beings.[2]

 

Ouch!

 

So if the fantastic musings of Herr Philosopher are too speculative and abstract to be of practical assistance to us individuals as we try to make our way through the world, to whom should we turn for guidance?  Here Kierkegaard suggests, to the story of Abraham.

 

Story of Abraham

 

So what is real faith about?

 

Because he had an unique relationship with God, Abraham is known to the faithful of the Abrahamic religions as the “Father of Faith.”  Kierkegaard examines the story of Abraham to discover what genuine “religious faith” is since those who use the word often point to this story as illustrative.   Kierkegaard is engaged in a sort of "conceptual analysis" of "faith."  Kierkegaard concluded that complacent, thoughtless, routine is NOT real faith.  And the story of Abraham can help us to see why that it.  Kierkegaard turns to the story of Abraham. 

 

The Biblical figure of Abraham is said to be the “Father of Faith” and heroically exemplary of religious faith for Christians.

 

http://plato.stanford.edu/search/searcher.py?query=Kierkegaard

 

http://kingjbible.com/genesis/22.htm

 

 

1 And it came to pass after these things, that God did tempt Abraham, and said unto him, Abraham: and he said, Behold, here I am. 2 And he said, Take now thy son, thine only son Isaac, whom thou lovest, and get thee into the land of Moriah; and offer him there for a burnt offering upon one of the mountains which I will tell thee of. 3 And Abraham rose up early in the morning, and saddled his ass, and took two of his young men with him, and Isaac his son, and clave the wood for the burnt offering, and rose up, and went unto the place of which God had told him. 4 Then on the third day Abraham lifted up his eyes, and saw the place afar off. 5 And Abraham said unto his young men, Abide ye here with the ass; and I and the lad will go yonder and worship, and come again to you. 6 And Abraham took the wood of the burnt offering, and laid it upon Isaac his son; and he took the fire in his hand, and a knife; and they went both of them together. 7 And Isaac spake unto Abraham his father, and said, My father: and he said, Here am I, my son. And he said, Behold the fire and the wood: but where is the lamb for a burnt offering? 8 And Abraham said, My son, God will provide himself a lamb for a burnt offering: so they went both of them together.

 

9 And they came to the place which God had told him of; and Abraham built an altar there, and laid the wood in order, and bound Isaac his son, and laid him on the altar upon the wood. 10 And Abraham stretched forth his hand, and took the knife to slay his son. 11 And the angel of the LORD called unto him out of heaven, and said, Abraham, Abraham: and he said, Here am I. 12 And he said, Lay not thine hand upon the lad, neither do thou any thing unto him: for now I know that thou fearest God, seeing thou hast not withheld thy son, thine only son from me. 13 And Abraham lifted up his eyes, and looked, and behold behind him a ram caught in a thicket by his horns: and Abraham went and took the ram, and offered him up for a burnt offering in the stead of his son.

 

Review

 

Fear and Trembling (1843) centers on the biblical story of Abraham. Abraham, childless after 80 years, prays for a son. God grants his wish, and Abraham has Isaac. Years later[3], God orders Abraham to kill his son.   

 

Abraham prepares to kill Isaac, but at the last second God spares Isaac and allows Abraham to sacrifice a ram instead.  Fear and Trembling however, includes four different retellings of the story, each with a slightly different viewpoint presumably to acknowledge the torment that a real Abraham (and Isaac) would have gone through.

 

  1. In the first version, Abraham decides to kill Isaac in accordance with God’s will. Abraham convinces Isaac that he’s doing it by his own will, not by God’s. This is a lie, but Abraham says to himself that he would rather have Isaac lose faith in his father than lose faith in God.

 

  1. In the second version, Abraham sacrifices a ram instead of Isaac. Even though God spares Isaac, Abraham’s faith is shaken because God asked him to kill Isaac in the first place.

 

  1. In the third version, Abraham decides not to kill Isaac and then prays to God to forgive him for having thought of sacrificing his son in the first place.

 

  1. In the fourth version, Abraham can’t go through with killing Isaac. Isaac begins to question his own faith due to Abraham’s refusal to do what God commanded.

 

So Abraham had a son, Isaac whom he loved deeply.  How does Abraham interpret God's request that Abraham take his son out and kill him?  Kierkegaard is inviting us to imagine what the real Abraham and the real Isaac must have been going through.  Their struggles their choices and by extension the challenge of the human condition.

 

It is a mistake to think Abraham merely had to decide whether to do God’s will or not.  Certainly, that would have been difficult enough, and many interpreters of the story leave it at that.  Some suggest only that Abraham had to decide whether he would do the will of God (at great personal cost) or not, and since he was willing to do God’s will, he passed the “test” and in so doing demonstrates heroic faith.  But Kierkegaard suggests that this reading misses perhaps the most important feature of the choice confronting Abraham and thus overlooks his truly heroic act.  Abraham first had to decide what that “voice in the night” meant.

 

Various interpretations are open to Abraham.  He must choose to interpret and that choice cannot be “rational” or based on evidence since it is the making of the choice which will determine WHAT the “evidence” is evidence of.

 

"Voice" in the night might be evidence of:

 

1. God’s sincere desire?

2. God’s test of Abraham’s morality?

3. A demonic trick?

4. Abraham’s own insanity?

 

Abraham's choice (and only his choice) determines what this voice is evidence of.

 

He cannot derive meaning, significance or guidance from it since it is HE who GIVES it its significance and meaning.  After his choice of interpretation, he must further choose how he will respond to the (newly created) “evidence.”

 

Kierkegaard is pointing out that, contrary to what we might initially suppose, we do not base our choices on evidence, but rather the other way around; we base evidence on choices.  The voice is not evidence of anything until it is given an interpretation.  What interpretation it is given is a free (undetermined) choice for which Abraham is totally responsible.  Further, he can get no rational assistance in making such choices.  But the most important things in his life rest on this choice, yet no choice is “reasonable” (or unreasonable for that matter) until after one makes the choice.

 

This is why Kierkegaard is considered the founder of Existentialism.

 

Existentialism – school of thought founded by Kierkegaard which stresses individual personal choice and responsibility;  major and minor decisions made in life are one’s choices; one is free to choose whatever one will; complete freedom, but therefore total responsibility rests with the individual.  These choices are matters of creative self-definition.

 

Further still, these are the most important choices of his life.  Abraham's world (his son, his relationship with God, his relationship with his wife, his progeny) was riding on this choice. 

 

When confronted with this need to choose he must therefore make a Leap of Faith

 

Leap of Faith: a passionate commitment that one makes without regard to reason, evidence or argument.

 

This is precisely what Abraham does and this is why he is a hero of faith.  This then is the nature of true faith.  It results from the recognition of the futility of reason and the necessity for personal unaided choice.  He is therefore not merely hero of faith, but emblematic of us all and the human condition we find ourselves in.

 

Abraham's world, everything important to him (his son, his relationship with God, his progeny) was riding on this choice.  So these free “existential” choices are the most important choices confronting us in life.  And Abraham is (as we are) compelled to choose.  As Existentialist philosopher, Jean-Paul Sartre (1905 – 1980) would later say, “Man is condemned to be free; because once thrown into the world, he is responsible for everything he does.”

 

One cannot get evidence for God because something can only count as evidence for God if one has already chosen to accept it relative to an evidentiary framework which already includes God.  Why then is he a Christian?  The only honest answer he (or anyone for that matter) can give is because he chooses to be one- NOT because of supposed evidence for or against.  There is the unknown, and we can respond to the unknown “God” or “Not God but this is a free choice on our part

 

“But what is this unknown something with which the Reason collides, when inspired by its paradoxical passion, with the result of unsettling even man’s knowledge of himself? It is the Unknown. It is not a human being, in so far as we know what man is; nor is it any other known thing..[4]

 

In Chapter 3 of Philosophical Fragments, Kierkegaard talks about “The Absolute Paradox.” Kierkegaard holds that paradox is “the passion of thought.” We want to discover something that we cannot think, even though this will be “the downfall of thinking” according to Kierkegaard.  That which we cannot think is “the unknown,” and the unknown is God (“the god”).  Therefore, Kierkegaard thinks it foolish to try to prove that God exists, since the very attempt to do so presupposes the preconceived conception of God one is working with exists. 

 

We would not try to construct a proof that something exists if we thought it might not exist. Further, we must begin with a presupposed notion of the divine nature in order to attempt any such “proof.”  Kierkegaard argues that the existence of something is never the conclusion of a proof; rather, it is the starting point.  For example, he claims that Napoleon’s existence cannot be the conclusion of an argument starting from his works or deeds, because we it wound need to start with “his works and deeds” presupposing that he, Napoleon exists and it is he who performed the works and deeds.

 

Similarly, God’s existence cannot be the conclusion of an argument based on God’s works.  To argue that the events in the world must derive from an all good being assumes that the events are all ultimately good and this assumption is based on the belief that there exists an all-good being who is the author of these works. 

 

Further any a posteriori proof this proof will always leave us in suspense, give us only a tentative hypothesis as we continue to accumulate more, potentially relevant, evidence which may undermine the supposed proof.  Perhaps a personal tragedy will undermine our belief that the things of the world are the works of a good God.

 

“So let us call this unknown something: God.  It is nothing more than a name we assign to it. The idea of demonstrating that this unknown something (God) exists, could scarcely suggest itself to Reason.  For if God does not exist, it would of course be impossible to prove it; and if he does exist, it would be folly to attempt it.  For at the very outset, in beginning my proof, I would have presupposed it, not as doubtful, but as certain (a presupposition is never doubtful, for the very reason that it is a presupposition), since otherwise I would not begin, readily understanding that the whole would be impossible if he did not exist. But if when I speak of proving God’s existence, I mean that I propose to prove that the Unknown, which exists, is God, then I express myself badly.   For in that case, I do not prove anything, least of all an existence, but merely develop the content of a conception.

 

Generally speaking, it is a difficult matter to prove that anything exists; and what is still worse for the intrepid souls who undertake the venture, the difficulty is such that fame scarcely awaits those who concern themselves with it.  The entire demonstration always turns into something very different and becomes an additional development of the consequences that flow from my having assumed that the object in question exists.  Thus, I always reason from existence, not toward existence, whether I move in the sphere of palpable sensible fact or in the realm of thought.  I do not for example prove that a stone exists, but that some existing thing is a stone.  The procedure in a court of justice does not prove that a criminal exists, but that the accused, whose existence is given, is a criminal.

 

So he’s decided to be a Christian.  Is he done now?  Hardly.  It’s not even as simple as that.  What does that MEAN?  He must further choose (and continually choose) what being a Christian is/means.  Note, being a Christian might mean willfully killing your innocent child.

 

One is not “done” choosing when one makes a choice to be “X” because, while “X” names a “kind” you are an INDIVIDUAL.  You may choose to be X, but you must live as THIS X, and only you decided what being “this X” means.  This is the case for any role: father, mother, son, citizen, Christian, etc. No one is a generic mother. father, philosophy teacher, philosophy student, etc..  As individuals making our way through the world, we must choose to be a particular not a generic.  None of these common nouns name “fixed essences” or, even if they do, then you are not essentially any of them.  You are one by choice alone.

 

Even one’s assigned features mean nothing until one chooses for them a meaning.  For instance, I am 5’ 7’’.  Some might say that I did not choose to be this height and there are many other features that are assigned to me and thus, much about me are features that I do not freely choose.  But the existentialist would counter by asking, “And what, precisely, does being 5’ 7” mean?”  Afterall, I am not “generic” 5’7’ any more than I am generic philosophy instructor; I am THIS 5’7”  and I choose for myself what that means, that is, what role I choose to allow it to play in my life.

 

Should you be a Christian?

 

Kierkegaard would ask, “Why are you asking me?”  You have to choose what you will be; this is what makes it an “existential” choice.  You create yourself through such leaps and choices.  The idea that each of us must “discover” who we “truly are” couldn't be more wrong-headed from an Existentialist perspective.  We are not a set, fixed anything.  We are the product of our own creation.  The real question I must answer is “Who / how do I choose to be (Today)?”

 

To further demonstrate the disconnect between faith and reason, Kierkegaard notes that sometimes Christianity requires the embracing of two things that are mutually impossible, irrational.  For instance, Abraham believed that he would kill Isaac AND that through Isaac, Abraham would go on to have many descendants.

 

In Sum:

 

Kierkegaard claims that religious faith is of the same character as are any of the really important decisions we make in life.  They are not made on evidence; they are non-rational choices, commitments made irrespective of evidence, argument, or reason.  We believe in God (or believe in NO God) simply because we choose to; such beliefs can't be based on evidence.   (Note this is not unlike the choice to live a moral or immoral life; this is not evidence based.  We can always rationalize after the fact, but the reality is that we simply choose to be who we choose to be.)

 

As previously stated, we must not imagine that once an existential choice is made, it is over.  Each day requires we make ourselves anew.  For Kierkegaard, the Christian life calls for constant reaffirmation.  Everyday it is a struggle to be a Christian.  In the same way, just because I did not cheat the last time I had an opportunity to does not mean that is the choice I am compelled to make today. 

 

Since every day we are free to define ourselves, everyday we are compelled to answer for ourselves “Who am I?”  Or, more correctly “who do I choose to be?”  “Human Nature” is no more “defined” than is “Christian Nature.”  I fool myself if I think that “I AM.” In some fixed and static way.  So long as I am alive, I BE in and active way, a way of dynamic choices.  And those very choices are HOW I “be.”  On this view, it is foolish to talk of “finding oneself.   There is no “thing” to find, no essential nature to discover; there is only the person to freely and creatively create.

 

The limitations of “Evidence” in Fixing Belief

 

As illustrations of the sort of thing he has in mind, consider two cases;  The "Bloody Gloves" in the O.J. Simpson murder case and the Shroud of Turin.

 

In the O.J. Simpson murder case, a key bit of "evidence" was a pair of bloody gloves:

 

Bloody Gloves:

 

 

 

One dark, cashmere-lined Aris Light leather glove, size extra large, was found at the murder scene, another behind Simpson's guest house, near where Brian "Kato'' Kaelin heard bumps in the night. Mrs. Simpson bought Simpson two pair of such gloves in 1990. DNA tests showed blood on glove found on Simpson's property appeared to contain genetic markers of Simpson and both victims; a long strand of blond hair similar to Ms. Simpson's also was found on that glove.

 

Prosecution: Simpson lost the left glove at his ex-wife's home during the struggle and, in a rush, inadvertently dropped the right glove while trying to hide it; explained that evidence gloves didn't fit Simpson in a courtroom demonstration because the gloves shrunk from being soaked in blood and Simpson had rubber gloves on underneath.

 

Defense: The glove behind guest house was planted by Detective Mark Fuhrman, a racist cop trying to frame Simpson; blood on glove may have been planted by police; gloated that evidence gloves didn't fit; hair analysis isn't sophisticated enough to be trusted.

 

What were the gloves "evidence" of?  Well, from a Kierkegaardian point of view- nothing until you choose to believe.  If you choose to believe he is innocent, they are evidence of a corrupt police plant and frame job.  If you choose to believe he is guilty, they become evidence of Simpson’s  presence  at the scene and participation in the murder.  But again, it would be a mistake to assume the evidence determines what is rational to believe; it is what you choose to believe that will determine what "evidence" there is.

 

 

The Shroud of Turin:

The Shroud of Turin is a linen cloth bearing the image of a man who appears to have sustained wounds and to have died in a manner consistent with the story of the crucifixion of Jesus.  It is housed in the Cathedral of Saint John the Baptist in Turin, Italy.  Historical records only trace a provenance to about the 1300's.  At that time, numerous "holy relics" and "shrouds" were produced, but whereas these others, upon closer inspection could clearly be seen to be fakes, the Shroud of Turin was intriguing because it was not an obvious fake. 

 

 

In fact, the image on the shroud could not be made out very well until it was photographed (circa 1930) and the negative was looked at.  When the values are reversed, the image is much more recognizable and detailed.  Many argued that it was unreasonable to imagine a forger anticipating the invention of photography.  Other historical accuracies lead many to believe it to be genuine, that is, to be the cloth that covered Jesus of Nazareth when he was placed in the tomb of Joseph of Arimathea.  Some even suggested that this image was recorded on its fibers at the time of his miraculous resurrection.

 

In 1988, for the first time, the Catholic Church permitted radiocarbon dating of the shroud  by three independent teams of scientists.  Each concluded that that the shroud was made during the Middle Ages, approximately 1300 years after Jesus lived.  Almost immediately, spokesmen on behalf of the Roman Catholic Church acknowledged the results, acquiesced to the judgement of science, expressed their disappointment and pledged, nevertheless, the take care of the shroud as so many did find it inspiring nevertheless.

 

Sometime later, a group of Protestant theologians and scientists issued their own statement.  They criticized what they thought was an unnecessary and overly hasty acceptance of this scientific evidence about the age of the shroud.  They argued that if there were a resurrection (as the Catholic Church and other Christians are supposed to believe) and if there were at that time a great release of electromagnetic radiation or the like, (as may seem plausible) then we ought to expect that the radiocarbon dating process would give us the wrong, much younger, date.

 

So, radiocarbon dating suggests that the shroud is only approximately 700 years old.  What is that evidence of?  Does it prove that the shroud is a fake? Or does it prove that it is genuine and further is evidence of the resurrection of Christ?  Kierkegaard might claim, either.  It depends on you.  Both require your leap of faith.

 



[1] Pascal was not a big supporter of Natural Theology and rational arguments for the existence of God.  He was an advocate of “fideism” which emphasizes the importance of faith over reason in understanding God and living in accordance with God's word. Nevertheless, he offers reasons for thinking that Faith can be “rational.”

[2] Kierkegaard, Soren, Concluding Unscientific Postscript to the Philosophical Crumbs, edited and translated by Alastair Hannay, Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York

[3] Interestingly, it is unclear how old Isaac was then this incident is said to have occurred.  The phrases “a long time” in Genesis 21:34 and “some time later” in Genesis 22:1 suggest that a substantial amount of time elapsed between Isaac’s birth and the trip to Moriah. So, Isaac was certainly not an older man when he was to be offered as a sacrifice, but neither was he a toddler.  While he is often depicted as a youth, an important clue to how old Isaac was is Genesis 22:6.  As they climb the mountain, Isaac is the one carrying the large pile of wood, wood enough for a burnt sacrifice which would have been very heavy.

[4] Kierkegaard, Sören,( Johannes Climacus) Philosophical Fragments Chapter 3: The Absolute Paradox: A Metaphysical Crotchet 1844