Theology and Falsification:

 

Anthony Flew

 

Because religious “utterances” are not falsifiable, they are meaningless.

 

The assertion of any claim (“P”) is equivalent to the denial of its negation (“not-P”).

 

P = ~(~P)

 

Asserting "P" is logically equivalent of denying "not-P."

 

If there is nothing that a person denies (if “not-P” = “0”) then there is nothing that this person asserts either (“~~P” = “0” therefore P=0)

 

Since the theist will accept nothing as irrefutable evidence that the proposition “God exists.” is false, (~P = 0) then the statement is not really about any real or imagined experience.  Consequently this is not a genuine assertion.  Thus it is pseudo-assertion.  (P = 0) It is empty of cognitive content and meaningless according to Flew.

 

 

1.

If one asserts something (“P”), then one must deny something (not-P”).

Principle of Logic:  P = ~(~P)

2.

The theist denies nothing.

 

Follows from the fact that Theistic “belief” is, apparently, compatible will all possible experience; it is un-falsifiable since we cannot even imagine what would prove a theist wrong. It seem they would accept nothing as convincing evidence of God’s non-existence, etc.)

Therefore:

3.

The Theist asserts nothing.

From 1 & 2

 

God's “love” seems to be compatible with all of life's experiences- sickness, disease, horrible suffering, torture, death; if nothing could count as evidence against God's “love,” “justice,” “existence” then what does the purported assertion “God exists.” mean?  If a “loving God” allows me (or innocent children and animals) to suffer horribly when he could have stopped it then what sort of “love” is that?  What would he do if he didn’t love me?

 

Flew is really asking the Theist "What do you mean?" 

 

“How would the world look any different if there wasn’t a God after all?”  “Would it make any difference if what you were saying were false? If there was no God?”

 

Try this: Imagine that you are trying to convince a friend of yours that her abusive boyfriend did not really love her.  You begin gently enough.

 

You: “He never gives you gifts and flowers you know, even on your birthday.”

 

Your Friend: “Yes I know, but he loves me, he just doesn’t love me in that sort of way.

 

You: “He doesn’t take you special places, make you dinner, or care for you when you are sick.”

 

Your Friend: “Well, yes I know, but he does love me, just not in that sort of way either.

 

You: (getting exasperated) “But he goes out with other women, brings them candy flowers and gifts, leaves for days at a time without calling you or telling you where he is, takes your money and your car without asking you and hits you from time to time.”

 

Your Friend: “Yes but that doesn’t prove anything!

 

You: Doesn’t prove anything?  Then what do you think “LOVE” means?

 

You have to start asking yourself then, “What in the world does the sentence “My boyfriend loves me.”  mean to your poor deluded friend.  Either it’s simply false (as the evidence demonstrates) or she has some really weird notion of “love” so weird in fact that it really doesn’t have anything to do with what we normally mean by love and even she probably doesn’t know what she means by the phrase.

 

The Theist is in exactly the same spot, according to Flew. That’s the idea of “death by a thousand qualifications.”  Both your friend and the theist started out with perfectly intelligible claims.  “My boyfriend loves me.” and “God loves us.” But when presented with counter-evidence (his infidelity say or the horrible, preventable suffering everywhere around us) instead of saying, “Gee, I guess you’re right; he really doesn’t love me because “love” means “would be faithful.” “would prevent preventable suffering” they instead change the meaning of their words.  “Love doesn’t mean that.” they say. 

 

But note, by the end they’ve changed it quite a lot!  If "Love" doesn’t mean brings presents, doesn’t mean care for you when you’re sick, doesn’t mean be faithful or respectful, doesn’t mean treat honorably, doesn’t even mean “refrains from striking me”  WHAT THE HECK DOES IT MEAN?

 

Probably NOTHING AT ALL.

 

(So too with “God exists.”  If it doesn't mean anything we can see, hear, taste, touch, smell, weigh, then what does mean?)

 

Mitchell and Hare criticize argument (not on form) on content

 

R. M Hare

 

Hare denies premise 1;

 

Hare claims that many beliefs that are not falsifiable are, nevertheless, meaningful in the sense that they guide or actions.  The lunatic “believes” that all university dons are out to do him evil and no experience, real or imagined can dissuade him from that belief.  But the utterance is meaningful for him, not because he can conceive of a falsifying experience, but because it forms that basis for his subsequent behavior. (e.g. If he sees a University don approaching, he’ll cross the street.)  This is sort of a Jamesian/pragmatic account of belief where a belief is not merely holding a noetic attitude towards some propositional content, but rather a "power to act."

 

The Significance of “Blik

 

In “Theology and Falsification” Hare introduces the idea of a “blik.”  A blik, he maintains is unverifiable and unfalsifiable because it is the very framework by which we interpret one’s experience. 

 

A blik, as Hare conceived of them, cannot therefore be recommended by evidential reason (or criticized by evidential reason). 

 

Hare says: “ ... without a blik there can be no explanation; for it is by our bliks that we decide what is and what is not an explanation.” 

 

Or elsewhere:

 

“Certainly it is salutary to recognize that even our belief in so-called hard facts rests in the end on a faith, a commitment, which is not in or to facts, but in that without which there would not be any facts.”[1]

 

While unfalsifiable, the statement of a blik is meaningful because of the role they play in organizing perception and the behavior in which they result.  An example of a commonly held blik might be “Things don’t just happen for no reason whatsoever.”

 

Hare seems to be agreeing with Flew in claiming that meaningful assertions about objective reality must be falsifiable; but his response to Flew holds that while theological utterances might appear to be assertions about objective reality, they are not really assertions about objective reality at all.  Rather, they are expressions or affirmations of frames of reference for interpreting data. They aren’t falsifiable, because verification and falsification can only occur within a frame of reference.

 

It is not clear why we hold the bliks we do, but according to Hare, we all do hold bliks.  In fact, if Hare is correct, we MUST hold bliks or else we cannot make sense of our experiences.  Perhaps we hold them for pragmatic reasons (i.e. this blik is more useful in solving my problems than its alternatives). Perhaps there are biological reasons we hold certain blik just as there are biological reasons which explain why most human perception conforms to Gestalt principles. 

 

But as Flew points out later on in his reply to Hare, this is certainly is not the traditional understanding of what a religious person thinks himself to be doing when uttering  “God exists.”   The Theist takes herself to be expressing a fact about the universe.

 

As Flew says,

 

“If Hare’s religion really is a blik, involving no cosmological assertions about the nature and activities of a supposed personal creator, then surely he is not a Christian at all?”

 

Also, let’s go back to what he says about lunatic (and our) bliks. 

 

Let us call that in which we differ from this lunatic, our respective bliks. He has an insane

blik about dons; we have a sane one. It is important to realize that we have a sane one, not no blik at all; for there must be two sides to any argument if he has a wrong blik, then those who are right about dons must have a right one.

 

Even if Hare has succeeded in showing that a blik does not consist in an assertion or system of them, nevertheless it remains very important to have the right blik.

 

But:

 

  1. If from any position a blik can said to be “right” or “wrong” then this presumes there IS a means of evaluating them.  At first blush this looks like “true” or “false” in the traditional, correspondence to objective reality” sense.  Alternatively one might retreat to a pragmatic justification of one over the other.

 

  1. Our (sane) blik about university dons IS falsifiable.  If we stumbled into a secret meeting of university dons conspiring to kill our lunatic friend by means of an elaborate scheme, we’d admit, much to our surprise, that university dons ARE out to get him after all.

 

When speaking about a normal blik about steal and a crazy one he claims:

 

“No amount of safe arrivals or bench-tests will remove my blik (that steal can spontaneously become malleable and/or fragile) and restore the normal one; for my blik is compatible with any finite number of such tests.

 

But this suggests that his blik is not just about steal, but rather about the reliability of induction and indeed he references Hume’s critique of induction.  In brief, Hume’s critique of induction runs something like this.  My belief that this bread that I am eating will nourish me and not kill me is justifies by two claims:

 

1. is has been nourishing in the past and

2. the universe will behave in the future pretty much according to patterns it has exhibited in the past. 

 

The first of these is verifiable by observation.  The second, what is sometimes understood as the “principle of induction,” cannot be verified, either by examining the meaning of the terms involved (as a relations of ideas), nor by observation (as a matter of fact).  Therefore Hume concluded that the principle of induction cannot be justified at all and therefore nothing depending on the principle of induction was justified either.

 

But Hume did NOT think that the principle of induction was a meaningless non-assertion.  He believed it to be true, as most of us do, but did not think was had justification for that belief.  And he worried that it might be false.

 

Hare concludes:

 

There is an important difference between Flew’s parable and my own which we have not yet noticed. The explorers do not mind about their garden; they discuss it with interest, but not with concern. But my lunatic, poor fellow, minds about dons; and I mind about the steering of my car; it often has people in it that I care for. It is because I mind very much about what goes on in the garden in which I find myself, that I am unable to share the explorers’ detachment.

 

Basil Mitchell

 

Mitchell attacks premise 2;

 

Theist accepts evil as (some) evidence against the existence of God, but does not accept it as final and conclusive evidence against belief.  The theist means exactly what you think he means; that God is omni...., etc.;

 

For Mitchell, the apparent indifference of God in the face of human suffering does indeed count as evidence against the truth of claims to God's love and concern.  What prevents the faithful from accepting it as final and conclusive evidence is the strength of his or her personal meeting/relationship with God.  Just as the resistance fighter is confused, frustrated and alarmed when the partisan seems to behave in ways inconsistent with the claim "He's on our side." nevertheless the phrase retains its meaning.  Indeed that why the resistance fighter finds the actions troubling.  A question arises at to when, holding out faith is just plain silly, but that's a question for another day.

 

Flew’s response to Mitchell

 

Flew claims the analogy fails because stranger in the parable is a mere mortal human being, not a deity.  That makes it easy to explain why the stranger does not always appear to be “on our side.” But an O-God does not human limitations.  Therefore there seems to be nothing seems excuse apparent unloving, indifferent behavior on His part. 

 

Mitchelll might counter that “faith” is the position of believe there is a reason we do not understand at this time.  The danger here is that while this might salvage the meaning of the utterances, it can make the faithful person seem silly and irrational.

 

My take:

 

I can think of a few things that they just overlooked, perhaps because they were not looking at the many empirically verifiable claims that actual world religions make.  I recall the old joke:

 

Old Joke:

 

Did you hear the cancelled Easter?

Yea, they found the body.

Ba bump bump.

 

I mean no disrespect.  I mean only to say that the claim of the resurrection is subject to evidential revision.  Also, if a die and don't meet God –or anyone else mind you- doesn't that prove there isn't one?  Christians, and others, claim that individual personal consciousness continues after that death of the body.  Now if that doesn't happen, then they're wrong.  Granted, the fact arrives too late to prove it to them, but that does go someway to fleshing out what these claims mean.



[1] R. M. Hare in Faith and Logic, ed. by Basil Mitchell (London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd., 1957), p. 192.