Pascal’s Wager

 

Non-Evidential Reason to Believe “That God Exists”

Blaise Pascal (1623-1662)

Pascal's Wager

Game Theory

The Table of Options when it Comes to Theistic Belief

The Best Option Is Belief

Calculating the Rationality of a Bet

Problems

"You bet your life" - William Lycan & George Schlesinger (1989)

Two Additional Objection

Pascal's Prayer

Epilogue: Dim View of Natural Theology

From Pensees

 

Non-Evidential Reason to Believe “That God Exists”

 

What we looked at initially were attempts to show that there is sufficient evidence to prove that the proposition “God exists.” is true.  Next we looked at attempts to show that there is sufficient evidence to prove that the proposition “God exists.” Is false.  What we will be looking at next are attempts to show that, despite the fact that there is NOT sufficient evidence to prove the proposition “God exists.” is true, it is nevertheless reasonable to believe the proposition anyway.  I classify these as “non-evidential reasons to believe that God exists.”

 

http://www.iep.utm.edu/p/pasc-wag.htm

 

Blaise Pascal (1623-1662)

 

"Belief is a wise wager. Granted that faith cannot be proved, what harm will come to you if you gamble on its truth and it proves false? If you gain, you gain all; if you lose, you lose nothing. Wager, then, without hesitation, that He exists."

 

Pascal's Wager

 

Pascal’s Wager is an instance of Game Theory – a means of deciding what to DO by trying to figure out likely outcomes of all possible courses of action.  The reasonable choice is the one with the greatest chances for the best success.

 

 

Game Theory‑ a heuristic for decision making where one considers all the possible courses of action that are under one's control and postulates how each would turn out in each possible scenario or events beyond one's control (attaching the relevant costs/benefits and probabilities).  The “right” (i.e. rational) choice is the one that is most likely to have the best consequences in all of, or most of, the most likely scenarios.

 

http://joelvelasco.net/teaching/hum9/pascalswager.pdf

 

The Table of Options when it Comes to Theistic Belief

 

There are two possible states of affairs which are beyond my control (or knowledge)

 

1. God exists.

2. God doesn't exist.

 

Can't control these

 

There are two courses of action which are (to some degree) within my control.

 

1. Believe

2. Do not believe[1]

 

This makes for a very simple Game Theory matrix:  The top row lists the variable you cannot control.  The left column lists the variable you can control and from which you must select what to do.  Note then that for Pascal, there is no way to “sit on the sidelines” when it comes to the question of God.  Each one of us is either living the life of a believer or living the life of a non-believer.  We've made a choice. And his point is, regardless of what choice we've made, it's a wager.  The only question that remains is “What is the most prudent wager to make?”

 

 

God Exists

God Does Not Exist

I Believe in God

Infinite Joy (Heaven)

Nothing (Makes no difference)

I don’t Believe in God

Infinite Misery (Hell)

Nothing (Makes No Difference)

 

Four possible choice scenarios:

 

  1. If I believe God exists and I’m right; I will go to Heaven.
  2. If I believe God exists and I’m wrong; there’s no penalty.
  3. If I do not believe in God and God exists; I’m wrong, I will go to Hell.
  4. If I do not believe in God and I’m right; there’s no reward.

 

Best Option is the Rational Bet

 

Pascal claims that the best option (most reasonable course of action) is to believe because the best that can happen is you go to heaven and the worst is that nothing will happen.  With belief, you have a shot at the best and avoid the worst.  With non-belief, you have no shot at the best and you risk the worst.  Thus he urges us, “Wager, then, without hesitation, that He exists.”

 

Pascal gives non-evidential reasons to believe that God exists; He claims that that the evidence does not settle the matter of the existence of God one way or the other.  So Pascal’s Wager does not prove the existence of God; it just says that to believe in God is rational because it is the best bet.  The conclusion is NOT "God Exists." But rather, "It is rational, reasonable to believe that God exists."

 

Still…

 

Initial Objections:

 

Is God happy with the wagerer, who believes in God just because it seems a better bet? 

 

Imagining getting to heaven and exclaiming, “OMG,, I can’t believe I won!”

 

 

Pascal himself notes that this is a problem and says that once convinced by his argument one ought to surround oneself with believers and immerse oneself in the culture of belief so that the right, genuine belief develops.  In other words, if you are convinced that belief is more prudent than non-belief, engage in those activities that will help you achieve belief.

 

Calculating the Rationality of a Bet

 

But the rationality of a wager depends upon a number of different factors.  First, what is the cost/ investment?  Second what is the pay off?  And third, what are the chances for success.  The best bet is one with no cost, high pay off and great odds for winning.  The worst bet would be one with high costs, low pay off and poor chances of winning.

 

Notice, while I rarely play the lottery, I would be irrational to turn down a FREE lottery ticket, no matter how high the odds or how low the pay off.  Similarly, it would be irrational to turn down free earthquake insurance on my house, even though here in Miami, the chances of us having an earthquake are very low. So, when deciding to play the lottery or buy insurance I need to consider these factors to determine the rationality.

 

We might render the values something like this:

 

The Probability of Winning times (the sum of the Pay Off minus the investment) equals the Rationality of taking the bet.

 

(Pr W)* [(Pay Off) – (Investment)] = Ra of Betting

 

But this means that, to consider the rationality of the argument, we must consider these factors with respect to belief in God.

 

1.       What is the cost of the bet?

Pascal suggest it is nothing, or next to nothing.  But is that true?  Wouldn’t it require that we give up certain things (sin/ fun) and make certain sacrifices (attend weekly services)?

2.       What is the pay off?

3.       What are the odds for success?

He offers two options, but that does not necessarily mean that that the odds are 50/50.

 

Problems:

 

William Lycan & George Schlesinger (1989) "You bet your life", in Reason & Responsibility, 7th edition (ed. Joel Feinberg, Belmont CA: Wadsworth).

 

Lycan and Schlesinger first consider a couple of problems with Pascal's argument

 

Q: 1. Does Pascal's argument turn on a 50% chance that God exists‑ the existence of God may not be a 50/50 chance?

 

A:  No.  They respond that it doesn’t matter since the pay-off is infinite.  So long as there is any chance at all it is worth it.

 

(Pr W)* [(Pay Off) – (Investment)] = Ra of Betting

 

(Pr W)* [(∞) – (Investment)] = Ra of Betting (i.e.∞)

 

Q: 2. Which God do you believe in?

 

A: They respond that:

a.) you should, using the motivating logic of the argument itself,  believe in the God with the best heaven and the worst hell and thereby get an opportunity for the best while avoiding the worst and

b.) one that has some historical weight behind it.

 

Q: 3.  What if it is on the pains of martyrdom?

 

What if you are living in the age of persecution?  Would this wager give you the right answer in a time that you must be willing to die for your faith?  If not then this argument is not going to give you the right kind of belief that will get you into heaven (i.e. if real faith requires that one be willing to die for one’s belief).

 

A: They respond that:

 

a.) we are not living in the age of religious persecution and

 

b.) even if we were, any finite amount of suffering is worth the investment when the possible pay-off is infinite.

 

Again:

 

(Pr W)* [(Pay Off) – (Investment)] = Ra of Betting

 

(Pr W)* [(∞) – (Investment – i.e. less than ∞)] = Ra of Betting (i.e.∞)

 

Two more not considered in "You bet your life":

 

Q: 4. Could you actually make yourself believe or not believe something?  Beliefs are involuntary (for the most part)

 

Pascal suggests that you can make yourself believe by immersing yourself in the religion, but that doesn’t always (ever?) work.  I recall speaking with a former protestant minister who left the ministry after a number of years.  I asked him why and he said that he woke up one morning and “God was gone.”  He felt bad about this and in fact regretted losing his faith in God, but he had lost his faith despite the fact that he was immersed in the culture of belief.

 

Q: 5. Is such a “Jealous God” worthy of worship?

 

Pascal’s concept of God does not offer a guarantee a God that is worthy of worship; Anselm offers a God that is worthy of worship, but Pascal’s God could be a spiteful, vengeful egomaniac.  Such a being would not merit worship even if he could command it.

 

Nevertheless…

 

Perhaps this argument is just good for those who are on the fence about a traditional religious faith and want to feel more “rational” about believing without evidence.

 

But if it cannot give rational justification for belief in (a particular) God to one who is NOT on the fence, then is does not give rational justification to one who is on the fence either.  Either it is a sound argument or it is not.

 

Pascal himself entitles this:

 

                “A letter to incite to the search after God.”

 

Pascal's Prayer

 

Curiously, Pascal himself seems to have had his faith grounded in a profound personal religious experience. 

 

Pascal's Prayer : The Memorial

 

Epilogue

 

He took a somewhat dim view of Natural Theology and philosophical attempts to prove the existence of God.  He suggests that at best they lead to philosophical abstractions and not to the God of the Bible, the dynamic living God that scripture names, the God of Abraham, God of Isaac, God of Jacob, but rather to “the God of the Philosophers and the learned.”  What's worse, they may even contribute to a prideful arrogant attitude on behalf of humans and rather than leading to an acknowledgement of our dependence on God give us a sense of prideful self-sufficiency.

 

Following his profound religious experience in 1654, Pascal abandoned mathematics and physics for philosophy and theology. His most influential work, the Pensees, was never completed, but a version of his notes for that book were published in 1670, eight years after his death.

 

From Pensees: OF THE NECESSITY OF THE WAGER

 

Who then will blame Christians for not being able to give a reason for their belief, since they profess a religion for which they cannot give a reason? They declare, in expounding it to the world, that it is a foolishness, stultitiam[2] and then you complain that they do not prove it! If they proved it, they would not keep their word; it is in lacking proofs that they are not lacking in sense. "Yes, but  although this excuses those who offer it as such and takes away from  them the blame of putting it forward without reason, it does not  excuse those who receive it." Let us then examine this point, and say, "God is, or He is not." But to which side shall we incline? Reason can decide nothing here. There is an infinite chaos which separated us.  A game is being played at the extremity of this infinite distance where heads or tails will turn up. What will you wager? According to reason, you can do neither the one thing nor the other; according to reason, you can defend neither of the propositions.

 

Do not, then, reprove for error those who have made a choice; for you know nothing about it. "No, but I blame them for having made, not this choice, but a choice; for again both he who chooses heads and he who chooses tails are equally at fault, they are both in the wrong. The true course is not to wager at all."

 

Yes; but you must wager. It is not optional. You are embarked. Which will you choose then? Let us see. Since you must choose, let us see which interests you least. You have two things to lose, the true and the good; and two things to stake, your reason and your will, your knowledge and your happiness; and your nature has two things to shun, error and misery. Your reason is no more shocked in choosing one rather than the other, since you must of necessity choose. This is one point settled. But your happiness? Let us weigh the gain and the loss in wagering that God is. Let us estimate these two chances. If you gain, you gain all; if you lose, you lose nothing. Wager, then, without hesitation that He is.

 

"That is very fine. Yes, I must wager; but I may perhaps wager too much." Let us see. Since there is an equal risk of gain and of loss, if you had only to gain two lives, instead of one, you might still wager. But if there were three lives to gain, you would have to play (since you are under the necessity of playing), and you would be imprudent, when you are forced to play, not to chance your life to gain three at a game where there is an equal risk of loss and gain. But there is an eternity of life and happiness. And this being so, if there were an infinity of chances, of which one only would be for you, you would still be right in wagering one to win two, and you would act stupidly, being obliged to play, by refusing to stake one life against three at a game in which out of an infinity of chances there is one for you, if there were an infinity of an infinitely happy life to gain. But there is here an infinity of an infinitely happy life to gain, a chance of gain against a finite number of chances of loss, and what you stake is finite. It is all divided; where-ever the infinite is and there is not an infinity of chances of loss against that of gain, there is no time to hesitate, you must give all. And thus, when one is forced to play, he must renounce reason to preserve his life, rather than risk it for infinite gain, as likely to happen as the loss of nothingness.

 

For it is no use to say it is uncertain if we will gain, and it is  certain that we risk, and that the infinite distance between the certainty of what is staked and the uncertainty of what will be  gained, equals the finite good which is certainly staked against the  uncertain infinite. It is not so, as every player stakes a certainty to gain an uncertainty, and yet he stakes a finite certainty to gain a finite uncertainty, without transgressing against reason. There is not an infinite distance between the certainty staked and the uncertainty of the gain; that is untrue. In truth, there is an infinity between the certainty of gain and the certainty of loss.  But the uncertainty of the gain is proportioned to the certainty of the stake according to the proportion of the chances of gain and loss.  Hence it comes that, if there are as many risks on one side as on the other, the course is to play even; and then the certainty of the stake is equal to the uncertainty of the gain, so far is it from fact that there is an infinite distance between them. And so our proposition is of infinite force, when there is the finite to stake in a game where there are equal risks of gain and of loss, and the infinite to gain. This is demonstrable; and if men are capable of any truths, this is one.

 

"I confess it, I admit it. But, still, is there no means of seeing the faces of the cards?" Yes, Scripture and the rest, etc. "Yes, but I have my hands tied and my mouth closed; I am forced to wager, and am not free. I am not released, and am so made that I cannot believe.  What, then, would you have me do?"

 

True. But at least learn your inability to believe, since reason brings you to this, and yet you cannot believe. Endeavour, then, to convince yourself, not by increase of proofs of God, but by the abatement of your passions. You would like to attain faith and do not know the way; you would like to cure yourself of unbelief and ask the remedy for it. Learn of those who have been bound like you, and who now stake all their possessions. These are people who know the way which you would follow, and who are cured of an ill of which you would be cured. Follow the way by which they began; by acting as if they believed, taking the holy water, having masses said, etc. Even this will naturally make you believe, and deaden your acuteness.  "But this is what I am afraid of." And why? What have you to lose?

 

But to show you that this leads you there, it is this which will lessen the passions, which are your stumbling-blocks.

 

The end of this discourse.- Now, what harm will befall you in  taking this side? You will be faithful, humble, grateful, generous, a sincere friend, truthful. Certainly you will not have those poisonous pleasures, glory and luxury; but will you not have others? I  will tell you that you will thereby gain in this life, and that, at  each step you take on this road, you will see so great certainty of  gain, so much nothingness in what you risk, that you will at last recognise that you have wagered for something certain and infinite, for which you have given nothing.

 

"Ah! This discourse transports me, charms me," etc.

 

If this discourse pleases you and seems impressive, know that it is made by a man who has knelt, both before and after it, in prayer to that Being, infinite and without parts, before whom he lays all he has, for you also to lay before Him all you have for your own good and for His glory, that so strength may be given to lowliness.

 

234. If we must not act save on a certainty, we ought not to act on religion, for it is not certain. But how many things we do on an uncertainty, sea voyages, battles! I say then we must do nothing at  all, for nothing is certain, and that there is more certainty in  religion than there is as to whether we may see to-morrow; for it is  not certain that we may see to-morrow, and it is certainly possible  that we may not, see it. We cannot say as much about religion. It is not certain that it is; but who will venture to say that it is certainly possible that it is not? Now when we work for to-morrow, and so on an uncertainty, we act reasonably; for we ought to work for an uncertainty according to the doctrine of chance which was demonstrated above.[3]

 



[1] By the way, note that Pascal is claiming here that there are only two options: belief and non-belief.  For Pascal, atheism and agnosticism are functionally equivalent for this “game.”  Whether you are an atheist or an agnostic, you are a “non-believer” and the consequences would be the same.

[2] 1 Corinthians 1:21King James Version

21 For after that in the wisdom of God the world by wisdom knew not God, it pleased God by the foolishness of preaching to save them that believe.

[3]  Pascal, Blaise Thoughts 84-87 Translated by W. F. Trotter