William Clifford and “The Ethics of Belief”

William James and the Forced Wager[1]

 

Note that we have seen that theists and atheists alike have suggested that evidence should guide our decision as to whether or not to believe.  But what should we do if evidence does not (or cannot) decide the matter?  Can any beliefs be considered “rational” or justified without evidence?

 

             W.K. Clifford says “No.”

             William James says “Yes.”

 

William K. Clifford (4 May 1845 – 3 March 1879)

 

In “The Ethics of Belief” William Clifford argues for an evidentialist point of view (i.e. that it is irrational to believe without sufficient evidence).

 

EVIDENTIALISM-

 

Claims that it is irrational to believe anything without evidence; the only good reason to believe anything is sufficient evidence.

 

However, Clifford goes beyond this claim.  He claims that it is not only irrational to believe without sufficient evidence; it is immoral to believe without sufficient evidence.  He claims that “it is a sin against mankind.”  He argues his case in his essay.

 

He starts by telling the story of a ship owner whose ship was to make journey from Europe to U.S..  The ship owner sold tickets to make journey, that is he believed (acted as if) the ship would make the journey.  Specifically, he acted as if he knew the ship would make the journey.  He did this despite the fact that he had some doubts about whether the ship was really sea-worthy or not.  However, he chooses not to act on those doubts (i.e. not investigate the truth of the matter), but to act on his belief that it would.  The ship sank and everybody aboard died.

 

Clifford says that the ship owner was guilty.   But guilty of what?  Guilty of believing without sufficient evidence.  Since beliefs are powers to act, they are not merely private matters, but always public and subject to moral evaluation.  They are subject to moral evaluation not merely in terms of the content of the belief, but also as to whether or not they were "justly acquired.  To act on a belief one is not entitled to is a sin, a stolen power, Clifford claims.  And the only thing that entitles one to a belief, entitles one to that “power,” is sufficient evidence.  Thus, the only moral way to acquire a belief is to believe on the basis of sufficient evidence alone.

 

He points out that even if the ship had not sunk, the ship owner still would be guilty of the same “crime.”

 

A second example he gives concerns rumors about a group of people who lived on an island.   They were accused of mistreating children among other things.  After the charges were filed and their reputations were destroyed, a careful examination was made and it was found that there was no basis for these rumors in the first place.  Further, Clifford points out that

 

“(n)ot only had they been accused on insufficient evidence, but the evidence of their innocence was such as the agitators might easily have obtained, if they had attempted a fair inquiry.”

 

Again, claims Clifford, because people believed without sufficient evidence and acted on these illegitimate beliefs, other were needlessly harmed.  Afterwards, these false accusers were rightly regarded as dishonorable men according to Clifford, not because they did not believe their own accusations, but because they had no right to believe their own accusations.  As Clifford says,

 

“Their sincere convictions, instead of being honestly earned by patient inquiring, were stolen by listening to the voice of prejudice and passion.”

 

So again, it is necessary to evaluate the morality of a belief, both in content and as to whether or not it was justly acquired.  To believe without sufficient evidence is to steal something to which one is not entitled.  The only thing that entitles you to the power of your beliefs is sufficient evidence. 

 

Clifford says that to believe without sufficient evidence is immoral and wrong not only when it has immediate bad consequences, but also because:

 

a. it perpetuates an attitude of superstition and an intellectual laziness with regard to investigation in the individual.  This, in an of itself, is a character flaw, and thus a moral failing.  Further, even if it does not harm people immediately, it will doubtless harms others down the line.

 

b. in the larger scope it breeds a culture of superstition, and what I tolerate in myself I tacitly endorse for all of society.  (See above.)

 

c. beliefs are always a basis of action and thus they always have social consequences; how one acquires beliefs is morally relevant since morality is concerned with behavior and we ought to behave/ believe responsibly.

 

d. it robs society of the “engine of inquiry.”  That is, our main motivation for finding the answers is realizing we don’t have them.  Simply appropriating whatever beliefs we want to have halts the progress of science and consequently, humankind.  Hence it is a sin. (Clifford would point to the comparably little progress that was made in science, medicine, technology, etc. during the middle ages because of people’s gullibility and satisfaction with unjustified beliefs.)

 

Thus Clifford concludes:

(Belief) is desecrated when given to unproved and unquestioned statements for the solace and private pleasure of the believer.... Whoso would deserve well of his fellows in this matter will guard the purity of his belief with a very fanaticism of jealous care, lest at any time it should rest on an unworthy object, and catch a stain which can never be wiped away....

 

If [a] belief has been accepted on insufficient evidence [even though the belief be true, as Clifford on the same page explains] the pleasure is a stolen one.... It is sinful because it is stolen in defiance of our duty to mankind. That duty is to guard ourselves from such beliefs as from a pestilence which may shortly master our own body and then spread to the rest of the town....

Clifford concludes his essay with:

It is wrong always, everywhere, and for every one, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence."

Problems

 

1. What, precisely, is sufficient evidence? (big problem for evidentialists)

 

2. When do we know that we have sufficient evidence?

 

3. Is evidence an objective relation (between states of affairs) or is it a subjective relation (relies on subjectively ordered belief systems and interpretation)?

 

4. Doesn’t this lead to either an infinite regress or ultimately unjustified “evidence?”  That is. if for belief A to be rational and justified I need to have some evidence belief B, and in order for belief B to be rational and justified I need to have some evidence belief C, and  so on and so on, I have a vicious infinite regress.[2] 

 

Clifford offers no number/percentage that gives basis of how much is sufficient evidence.

 

William James and the Forced Wager  (do not mix up with Pascal);

 

William James (January 11, 1842 – August 26, 1910)

 

American Pragmatists and Philosopher[3] responds the Clifford in his own essay, “The Will to Believe.”

 

 The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy

 

James actually agrees with some of what Clifford has to say, but he says that there are certain situations, in which it is proper, rational to believe without sufficient evidence.

 

These situations we may term “Forced Wagers

 

There are 4 features to a genuine forced wager:

 

1. They are “forced.”  It must be a situation which one is forced to choose; compelled to believe/ make a choice to act as if.

 

2.  They are (genuine) “wagers.”  It must be a situation where there is not enough evidence one way or another.

 

These two features explain why it is called a Forced Wager.

 

3. Options must be live options; choice must be among or between live options; what are live options for you depends on what you actually/practically could choose, could live with.

 

4. It must be a momentous choice; a choice that is going to make a lot of difference in your life; it must make a difference on how you live your life.  The choice is unlikely to occur again so this will likely be the only chance you have to make it. (Sort of now or never.)

 

Consider: Is there life beyond death or not?

 

  1. Suppose this is indeed a forced decision.

I must today either believe in the reality of life beyond death (act as if) or NOT believe in the reality  of life. (Disbelieving and simply remaining agnostic is functionally/ pragmatically equivalent.)

 

  1. Suppose for argument’s sake this is a wager.

There seems to be some evidence for life-after-death (say near death experiences) and evidence against it (nearly everything we know about the biology of consciousness and personal identity).

 

  1. Suppose further that this question represents two genuine options for me. I am such that I could believe that I will survive biological death (act as if) and I could also not believe that I will survive my biological death.

 

  1. Finally, suppose for me that the consequences of believing one way or the other on this issue will be momentous.

That is, let’s say that I will be much happier, much less anxious, if I believe in life beyond  death than I would be if I disbelieve in life beyond death (act as if not).

 

So, in this scenario

 

  1. I must choose (Forced)
  2. There is not enough evidence one way or the other. (Wager)
  3. I could pursue either option. (Live)
  4. Believing one of the options available to me is more satisfying to me, accords more with my hopes and desires, gives me more happiness, and generally, solves more of the practical problems that confront me in my life than if I were to disbelieve in life after death. (Momentous)

 

Then, according to James, I am justified in believing that there is life beyond death.

 

And note that, while remaining in doubt will not make me quite as unhappy as I would be if I positively disbelieved in life beyond death, remaining in doubt will not make me as happy as I would be if I were to believe in trans-mortal survival.  This certainly does not provide evidence that my belief is true.  But it does, he thinks, show that my belief is rational.[4] 

 

“He who refuses to embrace a unique opportunity loses the prize as surely as if he tried and failed. Per contra, the option is trivial when the opportunity is not unique, when the stake is insignificant, or when the decision is reversible if it later prove unwise. Such trivial options abound in the scientific life. A chemist finds an hypothesis live enough to spend a year in its verification: he believes in it to that extent. But if his experiments prove inconclusive either way, he is quit for his loss of time, no vital harm being done.

 

Thus, in science we seldom if ever have forced wagers and so in science we should not form beliefs without sufficient evidence.  But belief in God is another matter, James suggests.

 

For many, though not for everyone, belief in God is a forced wager:

 

  1. Not enough evidence one way or the other.
  2. Must choose [only 2 choices : live like a believer (acting as if) or like a non believer (not acting as if) - Everyone is making one or the other choice right now.]
  3. Live options (at least for some/most people religious belief is a live option).
  4. Choice is a momentous choice.  It will make a great difference in your life (again, at least for some/most people).

 

Given such situations it is reasonable (practical) to consider pragmatic reasons to believe.  Ask which of the live options will be most useful in living one’s life and then believe (act as if) that.  Both James and Clifford are working with similar notion of belief; belief is a basis of an action.  The belief is more or less identical to the practical behavior it engenders.  To believe something is the same thing as being willing to act in accord with it.   Both Clifford and James are interested in the practical differences belief makes. 

 

James says if both options are undetermined by evidence, choose that belief (theory) which will help you get on with your life; for most people religious belief is of superior practical value than atheism; answers more of our questions, James suggests.  For these individuals at least, believing in God without sufficient evidence is both rational and moral.  Indeed, wouldn’t it be irrational/ crazy NOT to believe in God?  After all, you could be wrong no matter what you do, so you might as well pick the option that makes you happier.

 

James is a member of an American School of thought known as Pragmatism.

 

Pragmatism:  An American philosophical school of thought that assesses the truth or meaning of theories or beliefs in terms of the success of their practical application.

 

Pragmatists go beyond the normal claim that whether a theory is useful in organizing and predicting experiences is a good test of truth, to the more extreme claim that all we mean by claiming a theory is true is that it is useful in organizing and predicting experiences.  This implies that theories can be true for a while and then stop being true, though not all pragmatists wanted to take their theory that far.  They did all agree that what counts most in a good theory, be it scientific, educational, psychological, moral or religious, is whether or not it was useful in solving relevant problems.

 

Scientists evaluate theories in virtue of their explanatory power.  James is suggesting that this amounts to the ability the theory demonstrates to solve the problems we are trying to solve and unify our experiences (into a coherent narrative).  He therefore claims that we should apply the same standard of evaluation to religious beliefs to see if they merit our rational assent.

 

He believes belief in God does merit assent, at least for many people, because for many religious belief assists in solving the practical problems we have in life.  He acknowledges that believing in God might not have pragmatic value (may be burdensome) for some people. Also, for some it may not be a live option.  In either of these cases, religious belief without sufficient evidence would NOT be rational, according to James.

 

However, contra Clifford, James claims that it is not immoral or irrational to believe without sufficient evidence when it is a forced wager and the pragmatic value for belief outweighs the pragmatic value of non-belief.

 

So, in these situations one must decide what one will believe and this cannot be an intellectual decision.  This is itself what James calls a “passional” decision meaning that whichever option you chose, neither is intellectually required to remain consistent with what is already known, nor is either inconsistent with what is already known. (i.e. It is a wager.)  If it is indeed a wager, then both belief and nonbelief is empirically adequate and thus the choice between them cannot be intellectually compelled.

 

It is similar to deciding between one or the other of two equally empirically adequate hypotheses. Imagine a physician with a patient who presents symptoms for two different diseases. In either case treatment is urgently called for, but the treatment for the one is inconsistent with the treatment for the other possibility.  The physician must act.  A decision to merely remain in paralyzing doubt and do nothing on the issue runs the risk of losing the patient MORE than does the choice to act on one or the other of the two hypotheses.  Remaining in doubt in forced wagers runs the same risk of “losing the truth” as James puts it.

 

James notes a distinction between: “Pursuing Truth” and “Avoiding Error”

 

These are two philosophical “commandments” that we ought to follow.  However, the pursuit of truth may lead us into error; and the avoidance of error may cause us to miss the truth.  By “pursuing” or “gaining” truth, he means gaining the power to act, that is, the power of believing something to be true.  But when I do this, I run the risk of falling into error.  Notice, I could avoid all error by not believing anything at all and remaining agnostic.  But this is a practical impossibility since it is the equivalent of never acting at all.  On the other hand, I could gain all kinds of “powers” simply by believing whatever I liked.  But this would be unwise.  So which goal should I pursue when?

 

James argues that in wager situations where the option between gaining and losing the truth is not genuine (i.e., not living, not forced, not momentous), we ought to follow the “avoid error” strategy.  Withhold believe and refrain from acting.  But in wager situations where the option between gaining and losing the truth is genuine (i.e., living, forced, and momentous), we should then pursue the truth even at the risk of falling into error.[5]  James’ thesis is that we should allow our passional/ willing nature to determine our beliefs if and when we find ourselves in a Forced Wager.  If it is not a forced wager however, James will agree with Clifford

 

But even to withhold belief in a genuine forced wager is itself a passional (not intellectually-required) decision. Note that for James, the decision to remain in doubt on the issue and is “attended with the same risk of losing the truth.”    Therefore, I should pursue/ gain truth and believe and it would be crazy (irrational) for me not to.  After all I could be wrong in any case.  I might as well risk error and be happier.

 

The Forced Wager

 

“Our passional nature not only lawfully may, but must, decide an option between propositions, whenever it is a genuine option that cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual grounds; for to say, under such circumstances, ‘Do not decide, but leave the question open,’ is itself a passional decision — just like deciding yes or no — and is attended with the same risk of losing the truth.”[6]

 

James distinguishes two positions: Absolutism and Empiricism[7]

 

For the absolutist, we can know the truth, and we can know that we know it.  We can be absolutely certain that we know the truth on the basis of the “objective evidence” for it.

 

For the empiricist, by contrast, our beliefs can be true, but we can never know with certainty that they are true.  The empiricist believes that we can get closer and closer to the truth through scientific inquiry into the facts of experience and through logical thinking.  However, the empiricist doubts that we can ever be certain that our beliefs are true even if they are, as a matter of fact, true.

 

The empiricist does not accept the absolutist requirement of certainty based on “objective evidence.”  This sets the bar too high for empirical (observational) beliefs.  It would seem that James denies that there is “objective, absolutely reliable, evidence” for our beliefs.  He mentions many examples of conflicting certainties, i.e., claims put forward by one person as certainly true that are then held to be certainly false by someone else.  This suggests that a “feeling of certainty” is more a subjective state than an objective fact.

 

In sum:

 

Consider beliefs based on observation of & thinking about evidence.

 

Can we be certain that the evidence before us is all the relevant evidence there is? No, we can’t.  Can we be certain that some future experience will not undermine an empirical belief we now hold? No, we can’t.  Can we be certain that our observational methods and our ways of thinking are infallible? No, we can’t.  Thus, we can’t be certain that our beliefs based on observation of and thinking about evidence are true.

 

One Final Note about the Connection Between Belief and Action

 

Sometimes there is an additional connection to belief and actions.  Some genuine options have the property that belief in the hypothesis contributes to making it true.  They can be self-fulfilling prophecy.  Note that believing the chemo treatment will work is what makes me subject myself to it, and, potentially, get cured.  If I believed that treatment will not work (act as if, forgo the treatment) then it certainly will not work.  If we believe we can make a difference in society, work for Civil Rights, say, it is far more likely that it will  be true that we do make a difference.  If we always sat back and waited for all the facts, the world would pass us by.  James says “Act as if what you do makes a difference.”

 

In Section IX of his essay, James discusses the need to believe without sufficient evidence in three areas:

 

1.       Moral questions: Moral beliefs exist. Which moral beliefs shall I adopt? Is there a real difference between good and evil? Are some actions right and others wrong? For example, is it right or wrong to harm another person without good cause? According to James, questions like these cannot be decided on intellectual grounds. But they MUST be decided.  So we must decide them on “passional” grounds.

 

2.       Personal relations: Shall I marry this person?  Will the marriage succeed?

 

3.       Organized social action: Faith and trust in others makes organized social action and progress possible. Here, again, faith (the will to believe) is a creator of fact.

 

With respect to Clifford’s Evidentialism, James says…

 

-“...I have also a horror of being duped; but I can believe that worse things than being duped may happen to a man in this world; so Clifford’s exhortation has to my ears a thoroughly fantastic sound....Our errors are surely not such awfully solemn things.  In a world where we are so certain to incur them in spite of all our caution, a certain lightness of heart seems healthier than this excessive nervousness on their behalf.  At any rate, it seems the fittest thing for the empiricist philosopher.” 

 

James ends his essay with a quote from James Fitzjames Stephen[8]

 

"What do you think {31} of yourself? What do you think of the world?... These are questions with which all must deal as it seems good to them. They are riddles of the Sphinx, and in some way or other we must deal with them.... In all important transactions of life we have to take a leap in the dark.... If we decide to leave the riddles unanswered, that is a choice; if we waver in our answer, that, too, is a choice: but whatever choice we make, we make it at our peril. If a man chooses to turn his back altogether on God and the future, no one can prevent him; no one can show beyond reasonable doubt that he is mistaken. If a man thinks otherwise and acts as he thinks, I do not see that any one can prove that he is mistaken. Each must act as he thinks best; and if he is wrong, so much the worse for him. We stand on a mountain pass in the midst of whirling snow and blinding mist, through which we get glimpses now and then of paths which may be deceptive. If we stand still we shall be frozen to death. If we take the wrong road we shall be dashed to pieces. We do not certainly know whether there is any right one. What must we do? 'Be strong and of a good courage.' Act for the best, hope for the best, and take what comes.... If death ends all, we cannot meet death better."

 

Epilogue:

 

Similar to Pascal

 

1. Does not prove existence of god.

2. Depends on evidence being unconvincing in EITHER case.

3. Suggests that, at least to some extent, belief is voluntary.

4. Focuses on the practical benefits of belief.

 

Dissimilar to Pascal

 

1. Does not talk about “other-worldly” benefits.

 

(Note: Even if it turns out that God doesn’t exist, on James’ view, the believer still “wins” the wager since he has lived a lifetime rich in the pragmatic rewards of belief.  He won’t get Pascal’s heaven, but he has won anyway.)

 

2. James is making a bigger claim about the nature of belief and justification generally which has wider application than just Religion.

 



[1] William James is responding to William Klingdon Clifford’s 1877 essay “The Ethics of Belief”

[2] Alvin Plantinga makes this and other criticisms of Evidentialism, but also of any form of Foundationalism or Coherence Theory.

Either:

         the principle of belief justification justifies itself (and would therefore be viciously circular)

or

         it does not justify itself (and therefore be unjustified and incoherent).

 

[3] Actually, he was a psychologist too and his brother was the novelist Henry James.

[4] Of course one might take issue with each of the presuppositions of this thought experiment,  For instance, many would argue that this is not a matter of a forced wager at all, since there is so little evidence for life after death and so much evidence against it.

[5] There is a neat scene in the episode “Bliss” of the Star Trek Voyager series.  Most of the crew have fallen prey to a deceptive entity, which perpetuates itself by luring travelers to their own destruction and feeding on their starships.  Seven, immune to the deception, contacts the captain of another vessel which is now trapped inside the entity.  Seven proposes that he join her aboard Voyager and work with her to find a way for Voyager to escape. She tells him to drop his shields so that she could beam him aboard. He is reluctant to do this, since his ship's hull, like Voyager's, is losing its integrity and his shields are the only thing holding it together. He concludes that Seven herself may be a further hallucination produced by the entity, but Seven impatiently tells him that her scans predict the failure of his shields in 15 minutes; he can join her or die, confident in the knowledge that he was not deceived.

[6] Cf., William James, “Preface” to his The Will to Believe and Other Essays In Popular Philosophy and Human Immortality (bound as one), p. x.

[7] Note, James is using these terms differently than how we have defined them elsewhere in this course.

[8] Stephen, Jasmes Fitzjames, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity, p. 353, 2d edition. London, 1874.