Problem of
Evil: Logical
Problem of Evil
Problems with Non-traditional Responses
Responses: Traditional - Theodicy
Challenges
to these Theodicies
Extended Reponses To
Challenges to the Freewill Theodicy:
Hume’s Empirical
Critique of Theism.
The Best of All Possible Worlds
William Rowe: Perdue University
Two Versions: The Logical Problem of Evil and
Empirical Problem of Evil
What is meant by "evil?" Proponents of the argument suggest two
distinct kinds of evil.
1. Moral
Evil- Wickedness. The evil that
humans do or will to do.
2. Physical Evil- pain and suffering. (This can include both human suffering and the
suffering of non-human animals.) Physical
evil might be brought about by wicked willful action (result from moral evil) or it may not be the result of moral evil such as the
suffering that result from natural disasters, sickness, etc.
The Logical Problem of Evil version claims that
Evil is logically incompatible with the existence of the O-God.
That is, it is logically impossible that the universe contain
evil (so specified) and the O-God.
Evil coexisting with the O-God is as logically contradictory as there
being a married bachelor, they claim, and thus inconceivable. Therefore, given that there IS evil, we can
be absolutely certain that there is no O-God.
1. If O-God existed then He would want to
eliminate all evil |
From the definition of O-God, specifically, Omnibenevolent |
2. If O-God existed then He could eliminate all
evil. |
From the definition of O-God, specifically, Omnipotent |
3. If O-god existed then
evil would not exist. |
From 1 & 2 |
4. Evil does exist. |
Evident from our experience of the world. |
5. The O-God does not exist. |
From 3 & 4 (Modus Tolens) |
Gottfried Leibnitz had claimed:
If the O-God exists, then this is the best of all
possible worlds.
The O-God exists.
(He gave a separate, independent ontological proof.)
Therefore:
This is the best of all possible worlds.[1]
However, the Problem of Evil starts with the same conditional
premise, but…
Logical Problem of Evil suggests that
If the O-God exists, then this is the best of all
possible worlds.
This is NOT the best of all possible
worlds. (We could easily imagine a
better one.)
Therefore:
The O-God does not exist.
Three possible Non-traditional or Non-orthodox
Responses.
1. Deny that God is omnibenvolent. This would explain the evil. God is in some part malevolent ir indifferent.
2. Deny that God is omnipotent. This would explain the evil. He simply is not powerful enough to eliminate
all evil. (This was William James’ view[2].)
Note: #1 &
#2 concede
that there is no O-God. They
acknowledge that evil gives us sufficient reason to believe that there is no
O-God. However, they counter that this
is not sufficient evidence that there is no God whatsoever. It is worth mentioning that William James
himself went with option 2. He believed
that evil was sufficient evidence that that O-God does not exist, but not
sufficient evidence that there was no God whatsoever. James maintained that if there did exist a
god, he clearly only had limited power.
3. Deny that evil is real. (Like Baruch Spinoza, one might claim that
what we call evil might be called good from another perspective and that all
things ARE good from God's perspective.
Or like some Christian Scientists who claim that evil is an illusion
which does not fool the spiritually mature.)
These are non-orthodox because these contradict the
traditional view of God and evil taught by the major Western monotheist
religions (Judaism, Christianity and Islam).
Problems with these responses.
1 & 2 would be deemed heresy by most Western
monotheistic religions. Also, they may
render a "god" who falls short of a "fit object of worship."
(i.e. an imperfect, dependent being)
#3 would also be deemed heresy. Monotheistic religions claim that evil,
whatever its ontological status, is a real force in the world to be resisted
and opposed- e.g. feed the hungry, heal the sick,
comfort the lonely, etc. Moreover we are called to
oppose evil on God’s behalf.
Also, what would "Omnibenevolent" mean
if not "opposed to human suffering or human wickedness?" What would it mean to say that God is all
good, but NOT opposed to child abuse? Such
a response weakens our grasp on the meaning of “good” as well as “evil.”
Further still, the difference between illusory
suffering and real suffering is unclear since it would seem
that suffering is perception dependent.
If I think that I am in pain, then I’m in pain.
Responses: Traditional - Theodicy
Theodicy: An attempt to defend the
character of God against the problem of evil. An attempt to provide is a
morally sufficient reason (MSR) which explains why the O-God permits evil or
otherwise why the existence of the O-God and the existence of evil are
logically compatible. All theodicies
appeal to some “good” which is supposed to justify, counterbalance, or
out-weigh the evil.
We will briefly look at the four most prevalent
theodicies offered. Each attempts to provide a morally sufficient reason why and
All-Good, All-Powerful and All-Knowing God would/does permit evil. To succeed they must show the good secured by
evil justifies and quantity and quality of the evil we see in the world.
1.
Free Will Theodicy‑ God
permits evil because evil is necessary for free will.
God permits evil because evil is necessary for free
will. Free Will is a great good, necessary for morally praise-worthy
actions. It provides human beings with
responsibility. We become “co-creators”
with God and this is a great gift; this is the source
of human dignity. Further, only free
beings can enter into a loving relationship with God.
But even so, shouldn’t God intervene, at least in
some cases, when the misuse of the freedom results in grave suffering?
No, proponents of this Theodicy say, because “real”
responsibility requires “real” consequences.
Free will is such a good thing that it is worth the
price. This theodicy is most often used
as an explanation for moral evil.
2.
Soul Making Theodicy‑
God makes the world a rough, dangerous, violent place because only in such an
environment can we develop our character and make something noble of ourselves.
In a "perfect world" there would be no
need for, nor opportunity for, ministry, charity, bravery, generosity,
perseverance, etc. No one ever came back
from Club Med a better human being. But
people do come back from boot camp better human beings. Boot camp is not paradise, but the roughness
serves a noble worthwhile purpose. Further,
these opportunities for soul making are worth the price. This theodicy is most often used as an
explanation for physical evil.
3.
Knowledge of Good & Evil.
In a perfectly good world, we would be surrounded by goodness but utterly
ignorant of it since we would have nothing to contrast it with. Consequently, God permits evil because it is
necessary in order for us to come to know the
difference between Good & Evil and that knowledge is worth the price.
4.
Evil
is Necessary for there to be any good at all.
Some have argued that
even an omnipotent God could not create "good" without at the same
time allowing for evil. Only God is
perfect. So, whatever he creates will
necessarily have flaws. Good and evil
are logical counterparts they claim, (like big and small; even an omnipotent
God could not create a big thing without as the same time allowing the
something small exist). Therefore, for
there to be anything that is big, there must be something
that is small. So too they claim,
for there to BE any good there must BE evil.
The only way to avoid evil would be to not create anything as all. But that is less good than creating a world that
contains some evil.
Challenges to these Theodicies
A)
1,2,& 3 is it really worth the price?
"It's not that I don't accept God, it's the
world created by him I don't and cannot accept."[3]
Alyosha recounts the horrible story of general who
has a surf boy thrown to his hounds and torn to bits while the boy’s mother was
forced to watch.
"Is there in the whole world a being who would
have the right to forgive and could forgive? I don't want harmony. From love
for humanity I don't want it. I would rather be left
with the unavenged suffering. I would rather remain with my unavenged suffering
and unsatisfied indignation, even if I were wrong. Besides, too high a price is
asked for harmony; it's beyond our means to pay so much to enter on it. And so I hasten to give back my entrance ticket, and if I am an
honest man I am bound to give it back as soon as possible. And that I am doing.
It's not God that I don't accept, Alyosha, only I most respectfully return him
the ticket."[4]
"That's rebellion," murmered
Alyosha, looking down.
The
Brothers Karamazov: Ivan and Alyosha, Book V - Pro and Contra,
Chapter 4 - Rebellion.
"Imagine that you are creating a fabric of
human destiny with the object of making men happy in the end, giving them peace
and rest at last, but that it was essential and inevitable to torture to death
only one tiny creature - that baby beating its breast with its fist, for
instance - and to found that edifice on its unavenged tears: would you consent
to be the architect on those conditions? Tell me, and
tell me the truth!"
"No, I wouldn't consent," said Alyosha
softly.[5]
B)
Contra #1. Evil is not
necessary for free will; only the possibility
for evil. There a possible world in which
humans do not behave immorally. An O-God would have created that world, not
this one. Therefore, the theodicy does
not work- explain why and O-God would permit evil. We still should believe that no O-God exists.
C)
Contra #2. While “first order” evils (like sickness and
famine) allow for the possibility of “second order” goods (like charity and
compassion) that also allow for the possibility of second order evils such as selfishness,
indifference, cowardice, etc. There is a
potential infinite regress here‑ about levels of goodness; pain (1st
order) allows for compassion (2nd order) but also indifference (2nd
order). Does indifference allow for some
3rd order good? Even if it did, this
would open the door to some 3rd order evil, and so on?
Seems no answer to pointless suffering or suffering
that actually destroys a person’s faith and morals.
Seems no answer to the suffering of very small
children, especially when they die young.
Yes, that I have an opportunity to be compassionate to them seems like a
nice thing for me, but how does it justify the suffering to them? Seems like I’m sort of using them, but they
are getting nothing out of it.
Seems no answer to the suffering of non-human
animals.
Therefore, the theodicy does not work- explain why
and O-God would permit evil.
D)
Contra #3. How much evil would be necessary? Presumably, not as much as we have. For instance, if we lived in a world in which
everything were red we would indeed be ignorant of redness
since we had no medium contrast. However how much non red would really be
necessary in order for us to understand red and non-red?
A small patch of blue should suffice. It seems we have far more
evil than would be necessary for us to understand the difference between
good. Therefore, the theodicy does not
work- explain why and O-God would permit (surplus) evil.
One might claim that suffering is relative. If this is the case then were God to
eliminating all current examples of suffering, there could still be (perceived)
suffering. (Imagine the world where the
most horrible suffering were cold soup.) Sounds pretty
good… to us. But this is only because in
our world far worse things than cold soup can occur. But for all we know there
are other worlds where the most imaginable suffering in this world would be
cold soup by comparison. This suggests that if any suffering is
justifiable, we are not in the position to know that the maximum amount of
suffering we see in this world is more than is necessary.
Still, does that really address the issue. Isn’t it an impossibly pale response to those
who are suffering? Or the victims of
wickedness?
Further, it can be argued that, just as a world in
which there was only horrible suffering would be really
(objectively) bad, whether or not any resident of that
world knows it or could know it, a world in which there was NO
horrible suffering would be really (objectively) good (better than this one),
whether or not any resident of that world knows or could know it.
E)
Contra #4. (Same as D and…)
If we understand "evil" merely as
suffering and wickedness, then the claim that any world where there is
"good" there must be "evil" is simply false. We can imagine a Garden of Eden where there
is no suffering. Here we have goodness
without evil (i.e. suffering, perhaps wickedness). Similarly, Earth before the evolution of sentient
creatures contained neither moral nor physical evil. So, the claim that any would God creates
would have to contain evil is simply false when evil is understood as moral and
physical evil. Therefore, the theodicy
does not work- explain why and O-God would permit evil as defined. It only appears to work by changing the issue.
Extended Reponses To Challenges to the Freewill
Theodicy:
1.
No such possible worlds are
actualizable by God alone, even an omnipotent God. Such worlds are only co-create-able with the
free agents themselves. (Alvin Plantinga)
Imagine two possible worlds, one where Professor Harris is needlessly
cruel to a student and other where he is not.
What could God do to create the first world and avoid the other? Nothing.
It’s up to Professor Harris to cooperate with God to create the first one
and not the other.
2.
Given the above, there may in
fact be no such possible worlds. So,
even if God could know in advance which potential free beings would only do
what it moral, it may be that as God
surveys all possible free beings he sees that none of
them do only what is right.
3.
If an action is really free however, even an omniscient being cannot know in
advance. The objective truth IS, what even an omniscient being knows, is that
the choice is not yet made. (Richard Swinburne)
4.
Some have argued that God need
not create the best of all possible worlds. (McCord Adams) Maybe some better possible world does exist;
it just not our world, and we are in no position to complain since were the
other world the only one which existed, we would not be “better off” since we
would not exist at all. God has no
obligations to people who do not exist. Therefore,
God harms no actual existing person by creating them, even if they do not
always do what’s right.[6]
Some have suggested that the evil and suffering we
confront makes sense only when taken in context with the promise of an afterlife.
Evil doers are brought to justice and the suffering in this world is
inconsequential when compared with the infinite bliss of the afterlife.
But the afterlife answer was called “a very curious
argument” by the philosopher Bertrand Russell in Why I’m Not a Christian.
•
“If you looked at the matter
from a scientific point of view, you would say, ‘After all, I only know this
world. I do not know about the rest of the universe, but so far as one can
argue at all on probabilities one would say that probably this world is a fair
sample, and if there is injustice here then the odds are that there is
injustice elsewhere also. Supposing you got a crate of oranges that you opened,
and you found all the top layer of oranges bad, you would not argue: ‘The underneath
ones must be good, so as to redress the balance.’ You would say: ‘Probably the
whole lot is a bad consignment;’ and that is really what a scientific person
would argue about the universe. He would say: ‘Here we find in this world a
great deal of injustice, and so far as that goes, that is a reason for
supposing that justice does not rule in the world; and therefore, so far as it
goes, it affords a moral argument against deity and not in favor of one.’”
Nevertheless, that there is any evil at all still
requires some justification.
J. L. Mackie talks about various attempts to
explain existence of evil; finds that all the explanations give up one of the
properties of God
Mackie raises the problems that maybe concept of
omnipotence is incoherent; the very idea of all powerful is maybe an incoherent
idea. Can an omnipotent being create a
creature whom it cannot control (a Free willing being)? No matter how you answer it would seem to
lead to a contradiction.
Could God create a rock so heavy that he couldn't
lift it? No matter how answer question seem to be denying God's omnipotence; the Greek's had a
similar idea. That is why they held that
either there is an unmovable object or irresistible force, but not both.
Each of the Theodicies we have examined is trying
to show that there is a Morally Sufficient Reason (MSR) that explains why the
O-god would permit physical and/or moral evil. So far, they all seem to have problems. But some have taken a different tact in
response to the Logical Problem of Evil.
They suggest that even if we have not found a MSR for evil, that, in and
of itself, does not demonstrate that there could not be any. The
Logical Problem of evil claims that the existence of the O-God is impossible
given evil. But this is the equivalent
of saying that a MSR is impossible. Yet
the proponent have not demonstrated that. But they cannot know that.
Apologists, unlike theodicies, do not claim to know
what the MSR is evil, merely that there might be one. They attempt to defend theism by countering
that there still might be some reason that a 0-God permits
evil and that we just haven't thought of yet.
The fact that, as far as we know, there might be some MSR demonstrates
that we cannot know the co-existence of the O-god and
evils are logically impossible.
The Theodicist's
response to the Logical Problem of Evil seems to rest here:
“For any evil E, there is a greater good
that even an omnipotent being could not bring about without allowing E.”
Since we cannot prove this above claim is false, (It may very well be false, but it
is not clear that we can prove it to be so.) the logical problem of evil
fails. Keep in mind that even and
Omnipotent Being is limited by the laws of logic. So, we cannot know that there is no greater
good logically entailed by any given evil E.
Now, it is readily admitted that it is pretty easy
to say that there are some evils which do not entail any greater good that we can think
of.
But that is not to say that there are none conceivable.
[7]
Therefore, the Logical Problem of Evil fails to prove
what it claimed to prove.
Hume’s Empirical
Critique of Theism.
Hume: Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (Part XI, 210)
To those who claim the evil is necessary in ANY world, Hume
is making two distinct replies. First, a
world without sentient creatures would contain neither moral evil nor physical
evil. So the
claim that any world would have to contain some
evil is simply false, at least when “evil” is understood as suffering and/or
wickedness. Further, we could easily
imagine a possible world in which there were some sentience and volition, but
not nearly as much suffering or wickedness (one where animals have
greater powers than merely those strictly required, or an environment with a more
stable, friendly climate, for instance).
What then shall we pronounce on this occasion? Shall we say
that these circumstances are not necessary, and that they might easily have
been altered in the contrivance of the universe? This decision seems too
presumptuous for creatures so blind and ignorant. Let us be more modest in our
conclusions. Let us allow, that, if the goodness of
the Deity (I mean a goodness like the human) could be established on any
tolerable reasons a priori, these
phenomena, however untoward, would not be sufficient to subvert that principle;
but might easily, in some unknown manner, be reconcilable to it.
Here Hume is saying that, for all we know, maybe the better
world he is envisioning is in fact impossible.
That is, if we had independent reason for thinking that
there is a God and that He is omnibenevolent and omnipotent, that is, if we had
the kind of absolutely certain knowledge
afforded by a sound a priori argument for God’s existence, then
we might have to conclude with Leibnitz that, appearances to the contrary, this
is the best of all possible worlds. God
knows why it could not be any better, but we do not.
But let us still assert, that as this goodness is not
antecedently established, but must be inferred from the phenomena, there can be
no grounds for such an inference, while there are so many ills in the universe,
and while these ills might so easily have been remedied, as far as human understanding
can be allowed to judge on such a subject. I am Sceptic enough to allow, that
the bad appearances, notwithstanding all my reasonings, may be compatible with
such attributes as you suppose; but surely they can
never prove these attributes. Such a conclusion cannot result from Scepticism, but must arise from the phenomena, and from our
confidence in the reasonings which we deduce from these phenomena.[8]
But absent strong
evidence for an O-God, we are left to ask then, are the ills of this world evidence
of such a being or evidence of the absence of such a being. Fact-set “F” is evidence for hypothesis H if
F is more probably given H and given ~H.
So, F provides
evidence for H when:
Pr (F + H) > Pr (F + ~H)
What Hume is suggesting is that the suffering in
nature and seeming indifference of nature is just what you would expect if
there were no God, but not at all what you would expect if there were a God. Consequently, these constitute empirical
evidence for atheism and against the hypothesis of theism.
The Empirical Problem of Evil: given the existence of evil God is (highly) improbable;
So this
version of the argument claims that while the co-existence of evil and the
O-God might be logically possible, it is nevertheless unreasonable to
believe there is an O-god given evil and far more reasonable to believe that
there is no such being. (Remember, it is
logically possible that there are aliens from outer space living
underneath my house who only come out at night when I’m sleeping, but it would
be unreasonable for me to believe such a crazy thing, given the wealth of
evidence to the contrary.)
Imagine someone called into a Talk Radio host and
said:
"Neil, I knew that there was going to be an
earthquake in Haiti on that day and I could have warned everybody, but I
didn't.”
"Well then, you are a monstrous
person!" Neil responds.
"No, no, I'm not. I have a really good reason why I didn't tell
anyone."
Now is it possible
that this person:
1.
knew about the earthquake,
2.
could have warned us but didn't
and
3.
that he has a really good reason why he didn't?
I suppose it
is possible. But is it likely?
No.
It is far more likely that either this person
didn't know, or that he couldn't have told or that he is a rotten person for
not having done so.
Well, the theist is in exactly
the same position. She is
claiming that the Universe contains a person who knew about the earthquake,
could have warned us (even subtly) and didn't but has a really good reason why he didn't. Is it possible? Perhaps. But the empirical problem of evil claims that
it is implausible and therefore, irrational to believe such a thing. It is rational to believe what the evidence most strongly suggests, that there is no O-God.
Remember, it is logically possible that there are
aliens from outer space living underneath my house, who only come out at night
when I’m sleeping, but it would be unreasonable for me to believe such a crazy
thing, given the wealth of evidence to the contrary.
The Best of All Possible Worlds
Leibnitz claimed:
If God exists that this is the best of all possible
worlds.
God exists.
(He gave a separate, independent ontological proof.)
Therefore:
This is the best of all possible worlds.
As previously stated, the problem of evil starts
pretty much with the same conditional, but rather than a modus ponens, does a
modus tollens.
Logical Problem of Evil suggests that
If God exists that this is the best of all possible
worlds.
This is not the best of all possible worlds. (We could easily imagine a better one.)
Therefore:
God does not exist.
The empirical problem of evil is suggesting that the
probably that God Does Not Exists and the probability that this is the Best of
all Possible World are inversely proportional.
Empirical Problem of Evil
If God exists that this is the best of all possible
worlds.
This is not the best of all possible worlds. (We could easily imagine a better one.)
Therefore:
God does not exist
The empirical problem of evil claims that premise
#2, while not logically necessary, it highly, highly probable. It follows then that the conclusion is
likewise highly, highly probable. This
puts the theist in the position of claiming that the conclusion is false,
despite being probably true.
Alternatively,
The antecedent probability of evil (horrendous
suffering) existing on the hypothesis of God is very, very low.
Evil (horrendous suffering) exists.
Therefore:
Evil provides strong disconfirming evidence against
the hypothesis of God, relative to the hypothesis of No God.
William Rowe: Perdue
University
·
Friendly
Atheist
o Is confident that there is
no God, based on the evidence he has surveyed so far. Nevertheless, he is open to the idea that
further evidence may change his mind.
·
Believes
that one might rationally believe in God, but personally believes that the
weight of evidence (Problem of Evil) is telling.
A. The Argument
1. An all-powerful, all-knowing and perfectly good would not permit an evil
unless he had a justifying reason to permit it.
2. There exist horrendous evils
that an all-powerful, all-knowing and perfectly good
being would have no justifying reason to permit.
Therefore
3. An all-powerful, all-knowing and perfectly good being does not exist.[9]
Rowe
believes that the first premise of this argument is certainly true and the second premise is, independent grounds for
belief in God aside, very
probably
true. If he is right, then the
conclusion of the argument follows inductively from its premises. Thus, it follows that the conclusion of the
argument is, grounds for belief aside, very probably true. This is why Rowe
says that the argument is not an attempt to show that God does not exist. It is an attempt to show that, positive
arguments for God aside, it is very likely that God does not exist and hence
atheism is rationally justified (over theism and agnosticism).
B. Defense of Premise 2
The
bulk of Rowe’s efforts are devoted to establishing that (independent grounds
for theist belief aside) premise 2 is very probably true. He takes premise 2 to be equivalent to the
claim that there are pointless evils in the world. He defines a “pointless” evil as an evil that
an all-powerful being could have prevented without forfeiting some outweighing
good. According to Rowe, what makes
premise 2 likely is the enormous amount of apparently
pointless, horrendous suffering in the world.
He gives two examples of such suffering.
I’ll add two of my own offered by Paul Draper.
Example One:
A fawn
is horribly burned in a forest fire caused by lightening. It lies on the forest floor suffering for
five days before death relieves its suffering.
Example Two:
A five year-old-girl is brutally beaten, raped and strangled
in Flint, Michigan on New Year’s eve a few years ago.
Example Three:
A
cement mixer truck driver rushes home so he can have lunch with his wife. He runs to the truck to return to work, not
realizing that his 3-year –old child is playing behind his truck. He backs up and kills his own child.
Example Four:
A
nine-year old girl and her mother are on their way to visit the girl’s
grandmother for the first time. A van
has a blow-out, crosses the median strip, striking their car head on. The girl is paralyzed from the neck down and
her mother is killed.
If
these were the only examples of apparently pointless, horrendous suffering in
the world, then perhaps, Rowe says, one could reasonably believe that none of
them are in fact pointless. But Rowe
emphasizes that the world contains an abundance of cases like these. The idea that EVERY SINGLE one has a point-
that an all-powerful being could not prevent even a single one without
forfeiting a outweighing good- strikes Rowe as absurd,
“quite beyond belief.” This is why Rowe believes that premise two is very likely
true.
Objections to Rowe: Can We Know That There Are
No MSRs?
Rowe’s
argument turns on the truth (or likelihood) of a Negative Existential,
specifically the claim that there are no morally sufficient reasons –MSR- for an
O-God to permit evil. Some have argued
that just because we do not know of any morally sufficient reasons why an O-God
would permit all the evils we witness, this does not demonstrate conclusively
that there are none.
Sometime
referred to as the "Noseeum" defense.
Note: This is a defense, not a theodicy because it does NOT attempt
to give the reason (e.g. free will, soul making, etc) why an O-God permits evil; it only attempts to salvage
the rationality of belief in the face of evident evil. In other words it
merely is trying to show that the Empirical Problem of Evil is NOT sufficient
to justify atheism.
Howard-Snyder
and Bergmann’s Critique of Rowe’s Argument[10]
They
accuse Rowe of assuming an unjustified noseeum
argument. Recall that the key premise (#2)
of Rowe’s argument is the following:
(2) There exist horrendous evils
that an all-powerful, all-knowing perfectly good being would have no justifying
reason to permit.
Advancing
this amounts only to the following:
a. So far as we can tell there is no morally
sufficient reason (MSR) for an all-powerful, all-knowing, perfectly good being
to permit the horrendous evils like E1, E2, etc..
c. Therefore it is much more likely than not
that there is no justifying reason for an all-powerful, all-knowing, perfectly
good being to permit the horrendous evils like E1, E2 etc..
But
"c" only follows from "a" on the presumption of an unstated
premise:
b. More likely than not, we’d know about a MSR
if it existed.
But,
they argue, we have no reason to belief or accept "b."
H&B
call the above necessary assumed but unstated premise (b) the “Atheist Assumption.”
They
reject it on the grounds that we really have no idea what reasons an omniscient,
omnipotent and morally perfect being might have for permitting
horrendous evil and so have no idea of how likely it would be that we would
detect such a reason if one existed.
They offer a Rowe “Chess- Kasparov” analogy. They point out that a chess master may make
moves that seem like mistakes to non-chess-masters simply because
non-chess-masters lack the cognitive wherewithal to rightly appreciate the
wisdom of the moves.
Therefore,
we have no way to establish the atheist noseeum
assumption
You can
distinguish between good noseeum arguments and bad ones
by the fact that in good ones, it is also true that, more likely than not, if
there were the thing in question we would detect it
(e.g. unicorns), whereas in bad noseeum arguments, we
do not have ground fro claiming that, more likely
than not, if there were the thing in question we would detect it.
But
since we cannot know (make justifiable inferences about) the probability of
detecting MSR’s if they existed, we cannot justifiably claim that the
probability is high (or low or midland, etc.)
Another
way to put this is:
Our
sample is : Possible MSR (goods) that we can think of.
Our
target is: All possible MSR (goods) that exist.
We have
no reason to think that our sample is a representative sample.
Rowe’s reply:
1. If what they said were
right, then NO amount of suffering could ever justify the claim that there is
no loving God.
But, that’s absurd.
2. Rowe’s claims it is not
merely a “noseeum” argument. He’s not merely saying that he doesn’t “see” any justifying goods, but rather, he
cannot even conceive any such good.
3. Rowe attacks the “Chess-
Kasparov” analogy (that a chess master may make moves that seem like mistakes
to us- non-chess masters). God isn’t playing Chess. God has a strong moral reason for providing
us with the reason for permitting horrendous suffering (help us bear the
burden).
Therefore, we DO have reason to suppose that
if there were MSR’s (and an O-God), we’d know about it.
A good parent would explain to the child why
she is permitting her child to suffer.
Ans even If, in fact, God could not explain his MSR, He would at least
give us His comforting presence (as with a parent).
J. L. Schellenberg [11]
J. L.
Schellenberg tries to get around objection of Theistic Defense (e.g. We can’t know
the conclusion of the noseeum.) against the Negative
Existential (There are no morally sufficient reasons for O-God to permit
evil.). Just because we can't think of
any morally sufficient reasons for permitting horrendous suffering does not show
that there aren't any nor even that there probably aren't any.
G=
O-God exists
E=
Horrendous Evil/Suffering Exists
M=
Morally Sufficient Reasons for Allowing Evil exist.
This
is, basically Rowe’s argument. The
problem is premise 2.
1. G ->
( ~M ->~E) |
Definition
of God and Evil – Certainly True |
2. ~M |
Very Probably
True |
Therefore: |
|
3. G ->~E |
1&
2 Modus Ponens - Very Probably True |
4. E
->~G |
Transposition
- Very Probably True |
5. E |
In
evidence |
6. ~G |
4&5
Modus Ponens - Very Probably True |
Thus:
The
probability of the claim (If G then ~E) is very high.
But E
Therefore:
The
probability of G is very low./ The probability of ~G is very high.
1. Pr (G -> ~E) =
++
2. E
Therefore
Pr(~G) = ++
But how
can we demonstrate that ~M is probably true?
(Conversely, that M is probably false?)
While #2
may not be necessarily true, it need only be true for the argument to
work. Schellenberg drops the “unless he
has a sufficient reason…” clause. Also,
it helps to read E as “this evil”
does not exist.
The
challenge for the theist then is to show that Pr(G ->
~E) is low which is the same as claiming that the Pr(M)
is (very) high.
Schellenberg
offers 3 reasons for thinking 2 is true.
1.
Because E is just so horrible (intrinsically
bad). The worse an evil is, the more
reasonable the claim that an O-God would eliminate it. The real force of the problem of evil is not merely
that we can’t imagine MSR, but the horrendous ugliness of the evil itself.
2. God
is maximally empathetic person[12]. Empathy provides motive to end the
suffering. The stronger the empathy, and
the worse the suffering, the greater the motivation. Therefore, we have very good reasons for
thinking the O-God (max-empath) would have great motivation to eliminate the
worst suffering.
3.
Horrific Suffering is instrumentally bad. (ie.
Prevents the occurrence of known goods - character development, relationship
with God, etc.)
Paul Draper’s Criticism
E is
evidence for H when:
1. E is true and
2. the antecedent probability
of E being true given hypothesis H is greater than the antecedent probability
of E given the hypothesis ~H.
For
instance, Casey Anthony did not tell police or her family that her daughter was
missing. This is a fact in evidence
(E). This E is more probably given the
hypothesis that she was involved in her daughter’s disappearance and death then
on the hypothesis that she was not involved in her daughter’s disappearance and
death. Therefore, her not telling the
police and her family is evidence of her involvement.
Pr (e/h) > Pr
(e/~h)
Sch is
committed to the idea that the horrendous suffering is not equally probable on
both the hypothesis “that God exists” and the hypothesis “that God does not
exist.” Specifically, he's committed to
the idea that the existence of horrendous suffering is more probable on the hypothesis of ~ God
than on the hypothesis of God. Only if
the existence of horrendous suffering is antecedently more probable on the
hypothesis of atheism relative to the hypothesis of theism can this count as
evidence in favor of the former and against the latter.
Draper
argues that Sch does not show that Pr (horrific
suffering/ atheism) > Pr (horrific suffering/
theism) It may be true, but Sch does not demonstrate why we should think it
is.
For
horrific suffering to be really strong evidence for atheism one must show that
horrific suffering is much more likely given no god.
If
Sch’s argument is not a logical problem of evil, then he must demonstrate the
probability of horrific suffering given atheism is not low, at least not as low
as the probability of horrific suffering given theism.
General Problems with
Probability and Modus Tolens Arguments
P >
Q
~Q
Therefore
~P
But
this standard inference pattern fails if one fails to consider the initial
probabilities of the constituent claims.
If the lottery is fairly drawn
I will lose (highly probable)
I don’t lose.
Therefore
The lottery was not fairly drawn. (highly probable)
Let’s
stipulate that premise one is very probably true. The odds of winning this lottery are 10000000
to 1. But if I win the lottery, does this
fact alone give us good reason to believe that the lottery was rigged in my
favor? No, because, while the initial
probably of me winning is very low, the initial probability of someone rigging
the lottery in my favor is very, very low.
If the lottery was not rigged in your favor you would not win (b/c such slim chance).
You win the lottery.
Therefore
The lottery was rigged in your favor.
We
would agree that the first premise is probably true, But if the initial probability of the
conclusion. that someone rigged lottery in your favor is also very low so much [
Pr (w/lot rigged) = !!! low], This winning the lotto does not provide you
with reason to think that the lotto was rigged in your favor.
Or
again. Consider:
Art
Thief “Pierre”
If Pierre were innocent, then his ring would
not be inside the display case at the scene of the crime.
His ring was found inside the display case at
the scene.
Therefore
So Pierre is not innocent
P >
[Pr (Q)= --]
~Q
Therefore
Pr (~P) = ++
/(or Pr (P)= --
Skilled Art Thief “Pierre”
P
> [Pr (Q)= --] ~Q Therefore |
~P
> [Pr (Q)= ---] ~Q Therefore |
Pr (~P) = ++
(or Pr (P)= -- |
Pr (P) = +++
(or Pr (~P)= --- |
While
the probability of his ring being at the scene is low, in the case where he is
a skilled art thief, the probability of his ring being at the scene given that
he is not innocent is even lower. If he
is skilled, then the probability would be very, very low that he would leave
behind his ring.
Examples
of Modus Tolens arguments which fail because they do
not take into account confirmation theory.
The
same mistake can take place with Modus Tolens
arguments for or against God.
Example
of Similar Empirical Argument in Favor of the Probability of
Theism
Fine
Tuning Argument:
If the
universe were such that God does not exist (P), then the world is not fine tuned for complexity. (Q)
The
world IS fine tuned for complexity. (~Q)
Therefore
God
does exist. (~P)[13]
Hume
makes the claim that the pattern of pain and pleasure is more consistent with a
Universe that is indifferent to our pain or suffering.
Analogous
argument:
Theo is
a father who had little exchange with his children. He eventually runs off and does not provide
for their welfare.
F (=
Known fact about the behavior of Theo with respect to his kids.)
L (=
Hypothesis that Theo loves his kids.)
IH (=
Theo is indifferent to the welfare of his kids.)
Now, the initial probability (IP) of IH is at
least as high as that of L
And
Pr (F/L) is much lower than Pr
(F/IH)
Therefore
F
confirms IH above L (without appeal to other evidence).
D1. O:
statement reporting what we know about pain and pleasure
D2: HI=
the hypothesis of indifference:
neither the nature nor the condition of
sentient beings on earth is the result of benevolent or malevolent actions
performed by non-human persons.
D3: T=
Theism
D4: N=
Metaphysical Naturalism
D5: Pr (x/y) >! n means “independent of the observations and
testimony upon which our knowledge of O is based, the epistemic probability
that X is true on the assumption that y is true is much greater than n.
D6: The
intrinsic probability of a statement is its probability independent of all
evidence
–i.e., the probability it has only in virtue
of its content.
The more complex the hypothesis, the lower the
lower the IP. The more “and’s” (x and y
and z) the lower, the more “or’s” (x or y or z) the
higher. EX: You have a dog vs. You have
a brown dog named Spot. Note: Draper
keeps HI very flexible for this reason thus giving it a higher IP.
D7: An
instance of pain or pleasure is biologically
useful just in case it causally contributes to the biological goals of
survival or reproduction and its doing so is not
accidental.
D8: An
instance of pain or pleasure is biologically
gratuitous just in case it is not biologically useful.
D9: O1
a statement that we know about biologically useful pain and pleasure of moral
agents.
D10: O2
a statement that we know about biologically useful pain and pleasure of
sentient beings that are not moral agents.
D11: O3
a statement that we know about biologically useful pain and pleasure.
P1: O
is known to be true (some statement about the pain and suffering in the world)
P2: Pr (O/HI) >! Pr (O/T)
P2. HI
is at least as probable intrinsically as T.
Therefore
(SC)
:Other evidence held equal, HI is much more probable
than T
P4: HI
and T cannot both be true.
Therefore
(C)
Other evidence held equal, T is very improbable. (It
is understood that ~(P&Q) and Pr (P) is !!!high,
the Pr (Q) is !!! low.
Defense of Premise Two
a. O is
logically equivalent to O1&O2&O3.
b. Pr(01/HI>!Pr(O1/T)
c. Pr(02/HI&01>Pr(O2/T&01)
d. Pr(03/H&01&02I>!Pr(O3/T&01&02)
Therefore:
e. Pr(O/H)>! (Pr(O/T)
NB: for
any Pr (a & b & c/ d) = Pr
(a / d) * Pr (b/ a & b) * Pr
(c/ a & b & d)
The
more complicated the theory, the lower it’s probability (were
the probability of the various parts is individually less then
one).
a.)
from the assumption of HI, you might very well expect that pain and pleasure
play the same role as other things in the life of bio creatures, but given the
moral status of suffering, on the assumption of T, you would have less reason
to feel confident that pain and pleasure play the same role in the life of bio
creatures.
On the assumption house builder who cares a
great deal about energy conservation, you might expect the roof to be about as
efficient as the rest of the house.
Vs/ the assumption that the house builder
cares a great deal about energy conservation and hates those roof solar heaters. Notice that this added detail may give you
some reason for thinking that the roof would NOT be as efficient as that rest
of the house. But this assumption is has less initial probability as it is more complex than its
rival.
b.) O2
the same sort of justification. We might
expect pain and suffering for moral agents, but no reason to think for sentient
a-moral beings.
c. On
the assumption of T we’d expect a lot less biologically gratuitous suffering
and a lot more biologically gratuitous pleasure.
Defense of Premise Three
Premise
3 is true because Theism is a specific supernaturalistic hypothesis while HI is
compatible with both metaphysical naturalism and a variety of supernaturalist hypotheses.
Defense of Premise Four
Premise
four is obviously true since God is, by definition, a benevolent being, and
thesis entails that both the nature and the condition of sentient beings on
earth results in part from God’s creation of the universe.
D.
Objections
1.
Premise 1 is false because of the success of the Free Will Theodicy. (Swinburne)
2.
Premise 2 is false because it is impossible to assess Pr(O/T).
(VanInwagen)
3.
There are no such things as intrinsic probabilities. Initial probabilities are subjective. (Otte/Hasker)
4.
Premise 2 is false because it is impossible to assess Pr(O/HI)
5. Even
if the e argument is sound, it has little significance because theists have
strong non-inferential evidence for theism (Plantinga).
[1] Candide (Candide, ou l'Optimisme) is a French satire by Voltaire in which Voltaire basically makes fun of this Leibnizian pronouncement. Candide’s teacher, Professor Pangloss, repeatedly assures Candide that "all is for the best" and that this is "the best of all possible worlds." This, despite the many misfortunes that befall Candide in the novel. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Vmc72fCJivA
[2] From: https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3143883/#fn5
“At the turn of the twentieth century, many of his colleagues were supporters of monistic or ‘absolute idealism’.5 Essentially, their metaphysical systems rested on the belief that all the elements in the universe contribute to some sort of unified and rational system, and that there is, ultimately, a benign grand plan underlying ‘the kosmos’ and all its events.6 For James though, the existence of real evil meant that such metaphysical assumptions were fundamentally flawed. One of the key facets of his metaphysics was that the universe is pluralistic not monistic; ‘an aggregate or collection of higher and lower things and principles’7 within which any god or benevolent spiritual agency is only one entity amongst many. The reason James gave for this was the existence of evil – if God is infinite, then He must also be ultimately responsible for this ‘excrementitious stuff’8 of the universe, and thereby lies a puzzle: If ‘the absolute’ is omnipotent, a being ‘upon which nothing alien can be forced, [why has it] spontaneously chosen from within to give itself the spectacle of all that evil rather than a spectacle with less evil in it?’9 As far as James was concerned, the solution to this conundrum was that ‘the only God worthy of the name must be finite,’10 and therefore relieved of responsibility for the evil parts of the world.
[3] The Brothers Karamazov Pg 294-205
[4] The Brothers Karamazov pg. 307
[5] The Brothers Karamazov pg. 308
[6] This line of argument has always seemed suspicious to me, sophisticated legalism which evades rather than resolves the issue. It is as if, due to the curious circumstances, no one exists to press charges. Therefore God is blameless. But surely this is a question of “character” not rights. What sort of God would create a broken and suffering world? Even if we grant that a “less than perfect world is logically necessary” the question would remain, “Why this less than perfect world?” "Why this evil?" We can (and do) quibble about the details.
[7] One way
around this might be to say that no “good” can be “greater” than some existent
evil. Thus this
claim would be false. One might show
that the whole project of counter-balancing evil with good couldn’t be made
out.
[8] Hume, David Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (Second Edition) ed. Richard H. Popkin, Hackett Publishing, 1998
[9]
But we might, nevertheless
retain faith in a Non-omnipotent God.
Rowe defines God as O-God. But
Cleanthes resolves the matter by lessening the attributes of God.
“If
we abandon all analogy to humanity, then we retain no conception of the great
object of our adoration. But if we
preserve human analogy then we cannot reconcile the evil in the world with
infinite attribute. But suppose the
Author Of Nature to be finitely perfect but far
exceeding mankind... benevolence governed by wisdom but limited by necessity
might produce just such a world”
[10] “Grounds for belief in God aside, does evil make atheism more reasonable than theism?” Howard-Snyder, Daniel & Bergmann, Michael In Michael Peterson & Raymond Van Arrogan (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion. Blackwell. pp. 140--55 (2003)
[11]
J. L. Schellenberg argues in book Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason that reasonable atheism is itself evidence
of God’s non-existence. If God does did
exist, why would he hide? One would
think that he would want a loving relationship with us and so would provide any
open-minded rational agent sufficient evidence of God’s existence.
[12] Side note: Can a perfect being empathize? Is suffering an imperfection? What might the experience of God be like?
[13] What if the claim was “If the lottery was not rigged in my favor I would not have won.”? The starting probability would be very low.