Traditional Account of Knowledge
John Locke and the Causal Theory of Perception
Primary
and Secondary Properties
Locke’s
View in Sum and Implications
Consequences for
Philosophy (et al.)
Opens the door to
Radical Relativism
What do you know?
I
· I know I have a hand.[1]
· I know that Paris is the capital of France.[2]
· I know that gold’s atomic number is 79.[3]
· I know that a rook can move horizontally or vertically on the chess
board. [4]
· I know what a rose smells like.[5]
· I know how to ride a bike.[6]
· I know where is live.[7]
· I know who I am. (most days).[8]
But all these really refer to importantly
different “ways of knowing” or “kinds” of knowledge. In Western philosophy, we have concentrated
mostly of “propositional” knowledge. By
the way, a “propositional belief” is a “that” belief: I believe that… The “proposition” is what comes after the
“that.” (e.g. that the Earth revolves
around the sun, that Tuesday comes after Monday; that square root of four is two).
So much emphasis on propositional knowledge has
lead to the impression that all knowledge is propositional and
that anything worth knowing can be expressed in propositions. (Those “that” phrases I was talking
about.) I think this is problem[9],
and this is one of the things we’ll talking about throughout the semester.
Traditional Account of Knowledge
Plato argues that knowledge is best understood as
“true, justified belief.” That is, to
say that Jose knows that Mary is guilty of cheating on her quiz is to say:
Kn= TJB.
This is referred to that the “Traditional Account
of Knowledge.” As I say, this has been
widely accepted as THE correct understanding of knowledge for the better part of
Western history. More recently it has
been challenged and we will be looking both at the traditional account of
knowledge and its challenges throughout the semester. Today, however, I want to concentrate on how
the traditional understanding of knowledge along with empiricist models of mind
have come to influence contemporary popular conceptions of what can and what
cannot count as knowledge. In the second
half of my lecture today I will be looking at Active Theories of perception and some of its consequences for
knowledge, truth and justification.
Key to understanding Platonic thought is the
distinction between appearance and reality.
Not everything that appears to be true is true, not everything that
appears to be good is good and for Plato, it even followed that not everything
that appears to be beautiful is beautiful.
If this is so, then the role of philosophy is to help us the distinguish
between the truth and mere appearance of truth, goodness and the mere
appearance of goodness, and beauty and the mere appearance of beauty. Epistemology is the branch of philosophy
which addresses the first of these, while Ethics and Aesthetics deal with the
second and third of these.
So how do we acquire knowledge? How do we avoid deception and error? Plato suggested that the senses are
deceptive, and that the most reliable knowledge came from reason and
introspection. He can point to the
reliability of math and geometry to prove his point. Note that mathematical truths can be known
with absolute certainty. We do not need to update calculus textbooks nearly
as often as we need to update physics and biology texts. This confidence in reason and distrust of the
sensory is characteristic of one of the two great traditions in Western
epistemology: Rationalism.
But Plato’s best student and best critic was the
philosopher Aristotle. In contrast to
Plato, Aristotle held that the best way to come to know objective truth, indeed
the ONLY way to come to know objective truth, is via sensory experience. This is the second of the two great
traditions: Empiricism.
These two viewpoints battled against one another
for the next 2000 years. Historically
the was St. Augustine, who was a rationalist, and, in contrast, St. Thomas
Aquinas, an empiricist.
Early Modern Philosophers[10]
Continental Rationalists: |
British Empiricists: |
•
René Descartes French- 1596-1650 •
Baruch Spinoza Portuguese/Dutch 1632-1677 •
Gottfried Leibniz German- 1646-1716 |
•
John Locke English 1632-1704 •
George Berkeley Irish 1685-1753 •
David Hume Scottish 1711-1776 |
Over time Empiricism came to dominate philosophy
in the United Kingdom, and eventually the United States. It is this tradition, I contend, that has had
the greatest influence on contemporary popular thinking about knowledge, truth
and justification in the United
States. There are several features of
this view that I would like to highlight and ask you to examine. The first of these is the nature of
perception.
John Lock (1632 -1704) was one of the three
“British Empiricists” of the Enlightenment period.[11] As am Empiricist, Locke was committed to the
idea that there were no such things as “innate ideas” and that the best, indeed
the only way, to come to know objective truth was via sensory experience.
·
The only way to come to know
the world is through sensory experience.
·
Agrees with St. Thomas
Aquinas- that, “Nothing is in the mind without first having been in the
senses.”[12]
·
Locke claims that we start
life with a blank slate, "tabula
rasa[13]."
Further, Locke rejects the “direct realism” or
“naïve realism” of pre-Modern philosophy. Rather than contend that we directly
grasp reality in perception, Locke, like Descartes, claims we grasp only our
mental representations of reality. We
get the “video feed,” but do not see the world outside directly. The question then becomes” How can we go from
knowledge of our perceptions (the video feed) to knowledge of extra-mental
reality (the world outside)?
·
Points out that there is the
(1)
world and
(2)
there are ideas
about the world.
·
This places critical
importance on determining: What is the connection between reality and
our minds?
The
Problem of Perception and the External World
Whoever wishes to become a philosopher must learn
not to be frightened by absurdities.
------Bertrand
Russell, Problems of Philosophy
These skeptical worries enter Western Philosophy
with a vengeance with Descartes et alia.
·
Are things as they seem?
·
Are there objects
independent of me?
·
Are there other minds?
·
And even if there are…
·
…how could I ever know any
of these things?
Direct
(“Naïve”) Realism: Physical objects are
directly (“immediately”) perceived. We
don’t need to justify an inference from sensory experience to physical reality
because physical objects are the objects of sensory experience.
Representationalism
(indirect realism): The
immediate objects of experience represent the physical objects which cause
them.
Sense
Data Theories: The objects of immediate
experience are sense data—private, non-physical entities, “ideas.”
Phenomenalism:
Physical objects are
reducible to the occurrence of the immediate objects of experience,
Scholasticism embraces a direct realism while
modern philosophy largely rejects it.
But with representational realism immediately comes skepticism about the “External World.”
How then to avoid skepticism: give good reason
for our commonsense belief that there is an “external world? We must then explain the relation between our
experience and “physical objects.”
Phenomenalism for instance, suggests that what we
call “physical objects” are “logical constructions” out of
sense-data—”permanent possibilities of sensation” (Mill). We must also explain the relation between our
sense data and us—and other people’s sense data and them. Neutral Monism suggest that physical objects
and “selves” (minds) are constructed out of the same (“neutral”) items, but in
different ways.
To this end, Locke offers his “Causal Theory of
Perception.”
Causal Theory of Perception ‑ the world interacts with out perceiving
organs and causes our ideas in our minds; Locke’s use of the word “idea” is
very broadly- nearly any mental item can count as an idea, a concept, a memory
or even a simple sensation such as “salty taste.”
So then, the world causes our ideas about
(perceptions of) it.
Note: our ideas about reality are different from
reality itself; ideas are mental but reality is extra mental.
It is therefore crucial to examine the connection
between the two: perceptions and extra-mental reality in detail. What is
the relationship between our ideas and the world? How does the one give us knowledge about the
other? His concerns are not really that
different from those of Rene Descartes
here; however, Locke’s resolution is
radically different. Unlike Descartes,
who sought absolute, indubitable certainty (justification must be apodictic) ,
Locke was after something more modest: probability/ plausibility. Like good scientists today, he was not
looking for beliefs that could be proven true beyond a shadow of a doubt. Rather he is content to call knowledge those
things we can demonstrate true beyond a reasonable doubt.
Our
Mental Ideas and the Extra-mental Reality: Some Important Distinctions
Our “ideas” come in two varieties according to
Locke:
Simple ideas are ideas that cannot be broken down into any component
parts. For example, the idea of “white”
is simple. I cannot explain “white” to
you; I can only show examples of white and hope you get it. Simple ideas arise from simple sensations.
Complex ideas are ideas that can be broken down into component
parts. For example, the idea of
(perception of) a unicorn. I can
explain the idea of an unicorn to you.
To explain a unicorn all one must do is take the ideas of a horse,
white, and a horn and combine them in a certain way. The “idea” of an apple (i.e. one’s perception
or experience of an apple) might include the simple ideas of red, round, sweet,
solid, etc.[14]
Primary and Secondary Properties:
Our experience of objects reveals two kind of
properties: Primary Properties and Secondary Properties.
Primary
Properties
·
Genuine properties of
objective, extra-mental reality.
·
These are the qualities of
the object independent of who or whether anyone is perceiving the object. Thus
these are independent of perception.
These intrinsic features, those it really has,
including the "Bulk, Figure, Texture, and Motion" of its parts.
(Essay II viii 9) Since these features
are inseparable from the thing even when it is divided into parts too small for
us to perceive, the primary qualities are independent of our perception of
them. When we do perceive the primary qualities of larger objects, Locke believed,
our ideas exactly resemble the qualities as they are in things.
Secondary
Properties
·
Properties of our peculiar
experience of reality, that is, of our perception.
·
They are NOT properties of
the object at all.
·
These properties only occur
in the mind of the perceiver and only at the moment of the perception. They endure only as long as the perception
endures. Thus these are perception
dependent.
These are qualities not in the thing itself, but
rather the powers it has to produce in us the ideas of
"Colors, Sounds, Smells, Tastes, etc." (Essay II viii 10) In these cases, our ideas do not
resemble their causes. Indeed,
the actual causes are in nothing other than the primary qualities of the
insensible parts of things.
Two
ways to tell the Difference Between Primary and Secondary Properties:
1. To change a primary quality of the object you
have actually have to change the object itself, but to change a secondary
property one need only change the conditions of perception.
2. Primary properties can be experienced by more
than on sense, but secondary properties can be experienced by one sense alone.
Consider the idea (perception) of an apple:
It is a complex idea composed of, among other
simple ideas, the ideas red, round, sweet, and solid.
According to the criteria
Locke provides, which of the apple’s perceived properties are primary (really
“in” the apple, and which are secondary (perception dependent, having no
reality apart from perception)?
·
Red is secondary- (I would
no longer see red if I were to change the lighting or I stared at a bright
green poster board. Also I have access
to the color of things through only one sense: vision.)
·
Round is primary- (I would
have to cut or smash the apple to change its shape. Also, I have both visual and tactile access
to the shape according to Locke.)
·
Sweet- secondary.
·
Solid- primary.
Locke’s View in Sum and Implications:
Thus, for Locke, we gain knowledge of the
objective world via the simple and complex ideas caused in us by the objects
and they inform us of the primary
properties of the object as well as provide us with the secondary
properties given to us in experience.
But this means that we must be careful about distinguishing primary and
secondary when making claims about reality.
There is no point is arguing about whether an object has a secondary
property or not, or to what degree.
Notice there is no point to us arguing about whether the soup is “too
salty” or not since the very same soup may cause in me a “too salty” secondary
property, but in you cause a “not salty enough” secondary property. Salty taste is a perception dependent,
secondary property. Further, it might
not even cause that sensation in me the next time I taste it if, for instance,
I drink something even saltier than the soup in the meantime. [15] As such is it not the proper subject for
serous or scientific discussions. [16]
Since secondary properties are not actually
properties of objects, but rather merely properties of the perception of
objects, they are not fixed nor stable.
If we had evolved differently, say as sentient vegetation, “salty taste”
would not happen at all. Had we all
evolved like snakes, “sound” wouldn’t happen at all. Though sound
waves would continue to be just as they are. Therefore, serious inquiry (science)
should confine itself to primary properties.[17]
Note: This view
of knowledge suggests that what can be known of objective facts and perhaps
math. But if you are not talking about
these matters, you are not in the business of saying anything true or
false. Everything else is relegated to
“matters of opinion.” More on this
later.
What are the primary properties properties of?
Locke realized that there must be some “ground”
for these properties. That is, the
primary properties must be property of something. Properties cannot exist on their own. (i.e. What is solif and round?”) So his
answer is that primary properties (these extra-mental, non-perception-dependent
properties), were properties of “Physical Substance.”
Physical Substance: (Stuff) – but we can know very little about
physical substance as such since we never directly perceive it. We only perceive our perceptions and they are
merely properties of substance, not the substance itself.
Locke uses and old metaphysical notion of substance:
that of which one predicates.
Nevertheless, since we do not directly perceive physical substance,
there really isn’t much more that we can know about it. Locke says of physical substance that it is
“something that I know not what.”
Therefore: Our ideas are caused by the physical substance; all ideas are mediated
by your senses; what causes the ideas is the physical substance that never
directly have contact with. While our
mental experience is rich with both primary and secondary qualities, the objective
world can only be said to possess the primary properties. Secondary properties would name subjective
experiences only, not the stuff of serious scientific inquiry or discourse
pertaining to objective truth.
Locke’s Causal Theory of Perception
You have an object (say an
apple) and it interacts with our perceiving organs (say our eye) and causes
in us the perception of an apple.
While the
perception has the secondary properties of red and sweet as well as the primary
properties of round and solid, the actual apple has only the primary properties
of round and solid.
Note then that we see with Locke the beginning of a delineation of the
domain of meaningful, legitimate inquiry and dispute. We see that knowledge is best regarded as propositional
disputes regarding the primary qualities of physical substance. All else is dubious and probably not
something about which we can meaningfully dispute or argue. Shortly after Locke we see Hume explicitly stating
as much:
"When we run over libraries, persuaded of these
principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume; of
divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain
any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain
any experimental reasoning concerning matter of act and existence? No.
Commit it then to the flames: For it can contain nothing but sophistry and
illusion." [18]
Logical Positivism
Logical Positivism followed the linguistic turn[19] in
philosophy. Once it was realized that
truth is a relation which holds between sentences and the world, many
traditional questions of philosophy were recast into questions about the
relations between our language and our experience of reality. Logical Positivism marks a development in
this historical moment of Philosophy.
See: (http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/6q.htm)
Linguistic
Tasks:
There are many uses of language, that is, we
achieve all sort of ends with language:.
(e.g. Assertions, Commands, Questions, Interjections, Poetry
Recitations, etc.) If we accept the
"Traditional Account of Knowledge" which claims that “knowledge”
equals “true, justified propositional belief,” the only sort of sentences that
express knowledge claims must be assertions.
Traditional Account of Knowledge: "knowledge” equals “true, justified
propositional belief (Kn=TJB)
Assertions: The sort of sentence that has a truth value. Only this sort of sentence is meaningful
according to positivism because only this sort of sentence actually informs us
(conveys information).
These are to be distinguished from
Pseudo-assertions.
Pseudo-assertions: The sort of sentence that may appear meaningful at first but in fact is
not. It does not have a truth value and
does not provide us with information.
Keep in mind that when we speak of a sentence
having a “truth-value” we do not mean that the sentence IS true, but only that it
is either true or false- has one of the two possible truth values.[20] What the Logical Positivists point out is
that, before wasting a lot of time arguing about whether a given sentence is
true or false, we should first make sure that it is an assertions; that is, we
should first make sure that it is even the kind of sentence than could be
true or false.
Assertions usually take the form of declarative
sentences (i.e. sentences having a certain grammatical structure –subject-
verb- predicate), but not all declarative
sentences are assertions.
Consider for example:
“In
the swirling vortex of love, a candle burns.”
This IS a
declarative sentence.
____Candle
│burns ________
\
a \in
Vortex_____
\the \of \swirling
love
This is NOT an assertion. (To check, ask yourself, “Is it true? Does there indeed burn a candle in the
swirling vortex of love?- Or is it
false? Has the candle in the swirling vortex of love gone out? Is there a light bulb there now? A neon sign instead perhaps? Perhaps a more environmentally friendly LED?)
I doubt anyone would be willing to say that this
sentence is true or false. Rather, they
would say that it is neither true nor false. Thus it is NOT an assertion. It neither informs nor misinforms. It lacks either “true value,” instead having
none.
But note: the sentence
“In the room next-door a candle burns.”
This IS an assertion.
What’s the difference? Not the grammar. The grammar is identical to the first
sentence. Both are declarative sentences
with a subject and predicate.
____Candle
│burns ________
\ a \in
room_____
\the \next-door
Further, consider these:
Kwai
gives you all the goodness of garlic.
This
product was scientifically formulated to help you manage your hair-loss
situation.
History
is the unfolding of consciousness to itself and for itself where the Absolute
presents itself as an object and returns to itself as thought.
We
did a nationwide taste test and you know what?
Papa John’s won big time!
It
is our destiny to rule the world.
With
our Lightspeed Reading Program, you will virtually read 2, 3, 4, even up to 10
times faster.
With
Elastizine you’ll see an average of 28% increase in younger looking skin.
Love. It’s
what makes a Subaru a Subaru.
How many declarative sentences are contained in
the following? How many assertions?
Hey Ladies! How
would you like to have drop-dead gorgeous skin without surgery? How would you like being stopped by customs
agents because you look younger than you Passport date? Well that’s what happens to users of Amino
Genesis. While other manufactures
recycle the same old stuff and call it new, Amino Genesis has cracked Nature’s
code.
Have trouble
getting to sleep but can’t take a sleep aid?
Millions do. That’s why the
hottest new sleeping pill is not really a sleeping pill at all. Relicore PM.
Take Relicore PM and get a restful sleep you need. Relicore PM, in the diet and sleep aid
aisles.
Have you tried everything to lose weight? Sweaty exercise is boring and takes too much
time. Crazy diets don’t work and always
leave you feeling hungry and deprived.
Wish there were another way? Well
now there’s Tone and Trim. Based on years of research, this
revolutionary new break-through technology was scientifically formulated by a
leading medical doctor to help you lose those unwanted inches without diet or
exercise. Just take two small capsules a
day, one before breakfast and one before bed, and voilá! You’re on your way to s slimmer sexier
you! Tone and Trim is all natural; there’s no stimulants and no danger
of harmful side effects. Tone and Trim works with you body’s own
calorie burning mechanisms like a super turbo boost, leaving you leaner and
more vitalized. Can’t believe any
weight-loss program could be so simple and easy? Believe it!
Don’t waist your time on crazy fad diets or strenuous exercise that
doesn’t work! Lose that ugly fat and
have the body you’ve always dreamed of with Tone and Trim. What are your
waiting for? Pick up the phone and call
today. Don’t let another day go by
without your Tone and Trim body!
The one 20th century philosopher A. J.
Ayer actually mentions in his Language, Truth
and Logic is:
“The Absolute enters into but is itself incapable
or progress or change.”
This was a sentence taken from the philosophical
writings of F. H. Bradley. In Ayer’s
view, it is a perfect example of nonsense.
More problematic, it is nonsense masquerading as “philosophy.” The
unwitting take it seriously and even dispute whether it is true or not. What a waste of time!
But how do you tell a genuine assertion when you
see one? Not the grammar. So then what?
The criterion, used by Logical Positivists to
determine if a sentence is a meaningful assertion is called the "Criterion
of Verification."
Criterion
of Verification: "If a sentence is unverifiable, even in
principle, then it is meaningless; it is not an assertion; it is neither true
or false."
Oxford philosopher A.J. Ayer (1910-1989), is the person probably most
responsible for helping to make this movement so widely know. In Ayer’s Language,
Truth and Logic he claims that a genuine
assertion can be true or false in only
one of two ways. Statements or
propositions (assertions) may be true or false by definition (analytic or what
18th Century philosopher David Hume[21]
would have called “relations of ideas,”)
or they may be true or false as a statement of observable fact (empirical or
what Hume would have called “matters of
fact and existence”).
For example, the claim “All bachelors are unmarried.” is true by
definition. And the claim “Some
bachelors are married.” is false by definition.
This is because the predicate “unmarried” only restates part of what is
meant by the subject term. Since
“bachelor means “unmarried male,” to say that a bachelor is married
would be logically inconsistent and therefore false.
Notice the truth or falsity of such claims can be known a priori (independent of
experience).
A priori: Known or justified independent
of experience.
If you came to my office and told me that your friend is in the
hallway and that he was a married bachelor, I would not even have to get up
from my desk to KNOW that there was no married bachelor friend of yours in the
hall. I can know this independent of any
particular experience (a priori).
Now suppose you claimed that “All bachelors are unmarried.” and I
expressed a doubt about this. I tell you
I want you to prove it to me. I
suppose you could go door to door and
do a survey: Knock, Knock, Knock. Excuse
me sir are you a bachelor? You are? I
see, but let me ask you now then, are you also
an unmarried male?”
But this would be a colossal waste of your time.
For claims like “All bachelors are unmarried.” we need take no poll to verify nor do any
sort of experiments, etc.. We need only
to know the meaning of the terms involved in order to know whether they state a
truth or a falsity. This is why they can
be known a priori. This is why Hume
called them "Relations of Ideas."
Relation of Ideas: Definitional-a priori, Analytic, A=A, trivial (usually),
non-augmentative (usually). Ex: “All
vixen are foxes.” But (perhaps) also
math and geometry.
Now if you came to my office and told me you brought your pet unicorn
to campus and asked me to come out into the hallway to see you pet unicorn, I
would be VERY skeptical and maybe think you’re a little crazy. However, I could not know a
priori that there was no unicorn in the hallway. That’s because there is nothing about a
unicorn that is a logical contradiction.
The reason I think that there are no unicorns is based on experiences
(We’ve looked and never found one.) so it is always possible that some future
experience would undermine this belief.
If I really wanted to make sure there was no unicorn out in the hallway
I would
have to get up from my desk and
poke my heard out into the hall. I don’t
expect to see anything, but there is the possibility that when I did I’d say, “Damn, would you look at that.”
The claim “All bachelors are unhappy.” on the other hand is not true
“by definition.” “Bachelor” does not
contain the concept of “Unhappy.” If
this sentence is true at all it is true as a matter of fact about the world
(and if it is false, it is false as a matter of fact about the world). To discover the actual truth-value (T or F) of the claim we would have to conduct
an empirical study. Since the claim “All
bachelors are unhappy” and the claim “It is not the case that all bachelors are
unhappy.” are both logically consistent, we cannot know which of them is true
(accurately states a fact about the world) a priori.
Since the predicate is NOT merely a restatement of the subject
concept, but rather a different concept entirely, the sentence is said to be “synthetic.” It weds two distinct ideas. Take for example “All Swans are white.” Swan does not MEAN white bird. We easily imagine a swan with of a different
color. So the only way to see whether
this synthesis in fact holds is to go and to look. Incidentally, it was widely believed that all
swans were white. Then it was discovered
empirically that there was a species of black swans. Notice that experience of the world is what
grounded the synthetic claim in the first place and it was experience of the
world which overturned and disconfirmed that same claim.
Matters of Fact: Empirical, Synthetic, A=B, interesting (usually), augmentative
(usually). Ex: “All Swans are white.”
Loosely speaking these are scientific claims.
If however, the truth of a sentence can be determined neither from the
meaning of the words (a priori) nor by employing the scientific method
(empirically) then the sentence fails the criterion of verification. The sentence is devoid of cognitive content
and is literally nonsense according
to the Positivists. This would be true
for such pseudo-assertions as “Kwai gives you all the goodness of garlic.” but
also of such claims as “An immaterial soul exists.” or ethical sentences
containing such terms as “ought,” “should,” “good,” or “bad.” They are non-sensical and therefore not
sentences which impart knowledge.
Consequences for Philosophy (et al.):
Many (all?) the traditional philosophical answers to traditional philosophical
questions seem to fail the criterion.
For example:
Natural Theology
e.g. “There is a God.”- Not a relation of ideas nor a matter of fact
Turns out to be meaningless on these grounds.
Note: “There is no God.” is equally meaningless on Positivist grounds.
Metaphysics
e.g. “Immaterial objects exist.
Aesthetics
e.g. The Miami City Ballet is a better ballet company than the San
Francisco Ballet.
Ethics
e.g. Abortions is wrong. (Or, Abortion is not wrong.)
Specifically, Metaphysical Theories, Theological Theories,
Epistemological Theories, Ethical Theories, Aesthetic Theories, seem to consist
of sentences that are neither relations of ideas nor matters of fact. Consequently, according to the criterion of
verification they are neither true nor false.
They are meaningless. It is not
clear what, if anything, could count a “Ethical Knowledge” for instance or an
“Ethical Truth” on their view. These
pseudo-assertions convey no knowledge, but rather at best are a kind of poetic
or emotive use of language. The realm of meaningful discourse is very narrowly
circumscribed.
Some Positivists claim that the reason for the seeming irresolvable
“disagreements” on ethical matters is simply that ethical judgments have no objective validity. Ironically, the Positivist accounts for these
‘disagreements” by, in an importance sense,
denying that there really every has been any. Note that a curious consequence of this view
is that there are no, nor have there ever been nor can there ever be any real ethical disputes. The Anti-abortion activist who says,
“Abortion is wrong!” and the Pro-reproductive rights activist who says,
“Abortion is NOT wrong!” don’t really disagree about anything (any
fact).
I think this a very narrow view of what constitutes meaningful
discourse. This think this is a totally
inadequate account of what’s going on in Ethics in particular and Philosophy in
general. However, I think a little
Positivism is a good thing. I think it a
very useful exercise to ask oneself, “What, if anything, could possibly prove
that claim true or false?” And if it
turns out that the answer is, “Nothing.”
then one has good reason to be deeply suspicious of the “claim.”
But my objection to Positivism is not merely the fact that, if
correct, it would largely put me out of work.
The criterion of verification is self-referentially incoherent. That is, the criterion fails itself. Take the sentence:
“If a sentence is unverifiable, even in principle, then it is
meaningless.”
This sentence above is neither a relation of
ideas (that is, a true-by-definition-tautology) nor is it a matter of fact
(that is, something that can be proven by employing the scientific
method). Thus either the criterion is
meaningless or false. There is no way
that it could be true.
Some positivists suggested that it be read as a
recommendation (a mild imperative).
“Regard as meaningless any sentence which is
unverifiable.”
But if it is only recommendation, we are free to
either accept it of reject it. Given the
excessively confining and impractical restrictions the criterion imposes on
“meaningful discourse” and inquiry, many (me) have chosen to reject it.
All experience is mediated by active mind. This was not appreciated until relatively
recently. (The myth of the “given” and
the “innocent eye” still persist today.)
Immanuel Kant and Active Mind
Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804) marks an important
development in Philosophy and conceptions of “Mind.” At this point in the history of Western
philosophy, two great opposing traditions had come to an impasse of sorts: Rationalism
and Empiricism had both seemed inadequate to account for human
knowledge. Rationalism seemed unable to
account for knowledge of our world of experience. Conversely, Empiricism seemed unable to
account for the necessary truths of math and geometry or even the universality
of the laws of nature. Taken to their
logical extremes, both seemed to end in skepticism (either Descartes’s or
Hume’s). Kant’s solution to the impasse
was to revision the very nature of knowledge and experience. The mind does not merely receive information in
the act of perception; the mind shapes that information and constructs
experience out of the raw sense data that the world provides. This is sometimes referred to as Kant’s
“Copernican Revolution” in Epistemology.
Rather than asking “Is knowledge/ understanding possible?” Kant asks “How is
knowledge/ understanding possible?”
Rather than asking “How does knowledge impress itself onto mind?” (passive
metaphor) Kant asks “How does mind construct knowledge?”
To accurately account for what is going on in
perception it is necessary to see human experiences as having different
content, but a consistent “form.” If we
were to abstract all content from human experience we would arrive at the pure
form of experience. Think of it a blank
template into which mind pours all sensory information and thus arrives at a
coherent experience. Alternatively think
of my (very old, MS DOS based) Maillist program that can organize records
according to one and only one pattern.
No matter what data it receives, it will always organize them in the
same fashion. In this case it was: First
Name, Last Name, Telephone Number, Street Address. Whether the data are for my mom, my sister,
the guy I knew from high school, the form of the record would always be: First
Name, Last Name, Telephone Number, Street Address. Even if the cat walked
across the keyboard it would be: First Name, Last Name, Telephone Number,
Street Address.
Thus I have knowledge of how my 100th record will
look (in broad outline) in advance of actually reviewing the 100th
record. That is, I have a
priori knowledge of the 100th record. My knowledge is not grounded in the
particular experience of my 100th record, though it is grounded in
experience in general. Though I don’t
know what the CONTENT of the record is, I know the form because when I am
referring to this program’s records, I am referring to products of its
organizing function which does not/ cannot change.
Another illustration of what Kant has in mind
here can be seen in those “Magic Eye” posters.[22] At one moment they look like flat two
dimensional images. The next they look
like a three dimensional image. What is
different from one moment to the next?
Is the poster giving you something different when it looks two
dimensional from what it is giving you when it look 3 dimensional? No.
What is different is what YOU are doing with the input from the poster,
the activity of you mind in perception.
But this is just a more noticeable example of what the mind does
constantly. The reason you see reality
as three-dimensional is NOT because “that’s how the world really is,” but
rather because that’s how your mind (and every other normal, healthy human
mind) is shaping the sense data.
Theoretical physicists might talk of reality in multiple dimensions, but
even they don’t perceive it that way.
They come to that understanding purely theoretically. Perhaps aliens from outer space perceive
reality in more dimensions. Perhaps’ s
God perceives it that way. But not
humans. Not now, not ever, says
Kant. We will always only “image” the
world as three dimensional. (And the
same thing goes for unidirectional time.)
Kant is very specific about what these forms and
categories of experience are, but I’ll only refer to a few for illustration
purposes.
Space and Time are the two pure forms of experience according to Kant.
All human experience will/ must conform to 3
dimensional Euclidian Space.
All human experience will/ must conform to
unidirectional time. (Past to present to
future).
For another example, think of visually ambiguous
images, specifically the “Duck/Rabbit.”
This phenomena shows why the old model of passive
perception is inadequate for understanding how perception works. For Locke, he thought it was enough to talk
about the object, the perceiving organ and the perception. On this view the object “impresses” itself on
the mind and the mind is simply the
inert passive recipient of the information.
We can
complicate this simple model a bit by talking about the object, the organ, the
retinal image, and the perception. But
again, on this model, the perception is understood as the inevitable product of
the retinal image. Mind plays no active
role.
But in the case of ambiguous images, the poverty
of this view is revealed. In the case of
the “Duck/Rabbit” image, I can see a duck or I can see a rabbit, that is I can
have the duck-perception or the rabbit-perception and which perception I have
cannot be explained in terms of the object, the organ or the retinal
image. When I have the duck-perception,
the object, the perceiving organ and the retinal image are the same as when I have the rabbit-perception. There must be some other factor that
explains the difference in perception, and that factor is the activity
of mind. The old Lockeian model
of mind simply cannot account for the phenomena.
Opens the door to Radical Relativism:
Kant believed that our (human) empirical
knowledge was universal (NOT RELATIVE) because the pure forms of experience and
the categories of thought were universal for all humans. Therefore, he was
certain that what is true for one human is true for all humans.[23]
BUT....one might object to Kant’s view.
For instance, what if we do NOT all put the world
together in basically the same way (e.g. woman according to a female template,
men according to a male template)? If
“Men are from mars and women are from Venus” then we are not experiencing the
same worlds because we are building our worlds, shaping our experience, with
the same input, but according to different templates. We are, in a very real sense, living in
different worlds, and truth must be relativized to groups of cognizers who
possess the same template. Rather than
univalent, truth becomes bivalent or, perhaps, multivalent. Truth is potentially as multifaceted as there
are minds, and no basis would exist for claiming that any particular worldview
was privileged among the plurality.[24]
This realization gave rise to the
Post-modernists’ notion that there is no one point of view from which Truth can
be determined. Imagine two groups of people, one who could only see the duck
and one that could only see the rabbit.
Which group is seeing what is “really there” and which group is wrong? Well of course we see in this example that
there is no reason to think that either group is privileged here. Further, the only reason we could have to say
that one of them has truth and the other has falsehood and is not seeing the
world “correctly” would be to advance a political, economic or social agenda.
We see with Empiricism in general and Locke in particular a focus on
propositional knowledge. The substance
of this knowledge is confined to empirical claims and logical tautologies. Claims not falling within the categories fall
outside the domain of knowledge and, consequently, serious inquiry. However A .J. Ayer’s and the Positivist’s
account of knowledge seems too narrowly circumscribed. They, in essence, created a club so exclusive
that it wouldn’t let them in.
We also noted that the passive model of perception coming to us from
Empiricism is flawed and inadequate to account for human experience and knowledge. The mind is active in perception and our
experience of the world is a result of that the world is giving us and what our
minds do with this input. The act of
perceiving the world is inseparable from the act of interpreting the
world. Kant offers this account, in
part, to answer the skeptical worries of both Rationalism and Empiricism. But we notes that he inadvertently opens the
door to entirely new challenge to those seeking absolute truth and universal
knowledge.
Despite the shortcomings of both Positivism and passive models of
mind, both remain extremely influential on contemporary popular understanding
about the nature and substance of knowledge and truth.
[1] This might be considered “propositional knowledge, but there is a sense in which is it more fundamental then that. Note also that “I know I have a hand.” In the same way that “My dog knows he has a tail.” He does not/ cannot express this propositionally. This is a kind of “somatic knowledge.”
[2] This is a typical case of propositional knowledge.
[3] Note that this is a highly “theory laden” sort of knowledge. What does this “knowledge” amount to? Not very much if you have no command of the theory in which it occurs/ originates.
[4] This is a curious sort of “knowledge” since expresses a fact of our own creation. We created the game of chess and in so doing created rooks. This truth is truth because it is part of a coherent self-contained, coherent system of inter-defined terms.
[5] This is not propositional at all, but experiential. Arguably I can know all the truth propositions about a rose there are without knowing what a rose smells like.
[6] Again, not propositional. Rather this is “know how.”
[7] Knowing where is live might be understood as propositional knowledge. (I know that I live in South Miami.) But when you think about it, there is al lot more involved in this sort of knowledge. Finding my way home requires more them merely knowing a series of propositions for instance.
[8] Arguably this requires knowing what foods I like, who my parent are, brothers and sisters, my values and spiritual commitments, dances I dance, songs that I sing…
[9] Consider, knowing how a molecule bonds or folds requires knowing its shape, But we have only limited access to molecular shape verbally. We have far better cognitive access to this information visually and/or tactically. (3D models of molecules https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=yZ2aY5lxEGE)
[10] “Modern Philosophy dates from the 16th and 17th century because this period represents a sharp break with, indeed a rejection of, the classical world views of Plato, Aristotle and Scholastic thought. This same rejection characterizes much of contemporary Western philosophy.
[11] Locke was English. The two others were George Berkley (1685 –1753, Irish) and David Hume (1711 – 1776, Scottish)
[12] Note: The Peripatetic axiom: "Nothing is in the mind without first having been in the senses"
Latin: "Nihil est in intellectu quod non prius in sensu").
It is found in De veritate, q. 2 a. 3 arg. 19. Thomas Aquinas adopted this principle from the Peripatetic school of Greek philosophy, established by Aristotle.
[13] This reference may not be as familiar to you as it is to me. I can recall my grandmother talking about taking her “slate” to school. Children would learn their letters and arithmetic on handheld chalkboards, or “slates.” They were sort of the IPODs of the day and much cheaper than paper. A blank slate is merely a blank chalkboard, blank, but ready to be written upon, receive information. But then again, “chalkboard” too may be a faded cultural reference these day as well. Sigh.
[14] Incidentally this is how Locke explained how it is that we could think of some things that we have never directly perceived and were never in fact ‘in our senses.” We do so by merely recombining the component parts of the ideas of objects that we have directly perceived.
[15] “What about beauty?” one might ask. Is it “in the eye of the beholder?”
[16] Recall that Locke is writing at a time when it was still common for scientists to identify chemicals by taste.
[17] If a tree falls in the forest and no one is there to hear it...
[18] David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding Section XII, part 3
[19] Prior to the modern
era, Metaphysics was considered the "First" philosophy. That is, when building a comprehensive
philosophical worldview or a philosophical system, philosophers thought the
first questions to be worried about would be: "What is real?" "What exists?" But with the advent of Rene Descartes Meditations on the First Philosophy he
ushers in a new era where the first set of questions philosophical system
builders tackle are "How do I know?"
"Of what can I be certain?"
This is sometimes referred to as the "Epistemological Turn." This, however, was later followed in the 20th
century with the "Linguistic Turn."
If knowledge equals true propositional belief and if this can only be
expressed by language, this makes the questions of epistemology (What can I
know?) second order the questions of Philosophy of Language (What can I
say? -and perhaps, What can I not say?). Further it “truth” is a relation that holds
between our language and the world, again the Philosophy of Language become of
paramount importance.
[20] Some philosophers have
argued that the idea that there are only two possible truth values (T & F)
is artificially narrow. What is one to
do we a sentence like "France is Hexagonal." for instance? See: How To Do Things with Words By John
Langshaw Austin. Nevertheless, we shall set these objections aside for another
day.
[21] Note: This division is sometimes called Hume’e Fork, though Hume used it with regard to justification, not meaning. Hume’s Fork states that there are two and only two ways to justify a belief (i.e. as a relation of ideas or as a matter of fact). Hume predates Logical Positivism, but they borrowed his Fork.
[22] I am referring to autostereograms or single-image stereogram, which create the visual illusion of a three-dimensional image from a two-dimensional image.
[23] Now God or aliens from another planet may have very different forms of experience and thus different knowledge and truths, but the human task of inquiry doesn’t involve them- not yet at least. Therefore these are merely speculative concerns, not practical ones about which Kant, scientists or you and I need to worry.
[24] Some of this figures into and can even be used to justify certain claims arising from post-modernism.