Lecture Supplement
for Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics:[1]
Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
Book I.
Happiness—The Good For Man:
A. Subject of Our
Inquiry:
Chapter 1. Ends and
Goods—The Good As the Aim of Action:
All human activities aim at some good, and some goods are
subordinate to others:
403 “Every art and every inquiry,
and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for
this reason the good has rightly been
declared to be that at which all things aim.”
[2]
[1094a]
-Aristotle distinguishes
“subordinate” ends (and actions) from the “master” ends.
Chapter 2.
Political Science is the Master Science of the Good:
“If, then, there is some end of
the things we do, which we desire for its own sake (everything else being
desired for the sake of this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake
of something else (for at that rate the process would go on to infinity, so that
our desire would be empty and vain), clearly this must be the good and the chief
good. [1094a]
-404 “And politics appears to be of this nature; for it is this that ordains which of the sciences should be studied in a state, and which each class of citizens should learn and up to what point they should learn them....” [1094a-b]
B. The Nature of
the Science [of Ethics]:
Chapter 3. The
Method of Political Science:
We must not expect
more precision than the subject-matter admits, and students of this study
must have reached the age of discretion:
404 “Our discussion will
be adequate if it has as much clearness as the subject-matter admits of, for
precision is not to be sought for alike in all discussions, any more than it all
the products of the crafts. Now
fine and just actions, which political science investigates, admit of much
variety and fluctuation of opinion, so that they may be thought to exist only by
convention, and not by nature. And
goods also give rise to similar fluctuation because they bring harm to m
any people; for before
now men have been undone by reason of their wealth, and others by reason of
their courage. We must be content,
then, in speaking of such subjects and with such premisses to indicate the truth
roughly and in outline, and in speaking about things which are only for the most
part true and with premisses of the same kind to reach conclusions that are no
better. In the same spirit,
therefore, should each type of statement be received; for it is the mark of an
educated man to look for precision in each class of things just so far as the
nature of the subject admits; it is evidently equally foolish to accept probable
reasoning from a mathematician and to demand from a rhetorician scientific
proofs.” [1094b]
C. What Is The Good
For Man?
Chapter 4. Common
Beliefs about Happiness:
The good for man is generally agreed to be happiness, but
there are various views as to what happiness is:
“...both
the general run of men and people of superior refinement say that it is
happiness, and identify living
well and doing well with being happy; but with regard to what happiness is they
differ, and many do not give the same account as the wise.
For the former think it is some plain and obvious thing, like
pleasure,
wealth, or honor; they differ, however, from one
another—and often even the same man identifies it with different things, with
health when he is ill....”
[1095a]
He notes that arguing
from and arguing
to first principles are different
sorts of activities, and “...while we must begin with what is known, things are
objects of knowledge in two senses—some to us, some without qualification.
Presumably, then, we must begin with things known to us.
Hence any one who is to listen intelligently to lectures about what is
noble and just and, generally, about the subjects of political science must have
been brought up in good habits.” [1095b]
Chapter 5. Four
Views of the Highest Good (Four Lives):
Discussion of the popular views that the good is
pleasure, honour, wealth, and
contrast with the view that it is
contemplation:
405 “...most men, and men of the
most vulgar type, seem (not without some ground) to identify the good, or
happiness, with pleasure; which is
the reason why they love the life of enjoyment.
For there are, we may say, three prominent types of life—that just
mentioned, the political, and
thirdly the contemplative life.
Now the mass of mankind are evidently quite slavish in their tastes,
preferring a life suitable to beasts....”
[1095b]
-“...people of superior
refinement and of active disposition identify happiness with
honor....But it seems too superficial
to be what we are looking for, since it is thought to depend on those who bestow
honour rather than on him who receives it, but the good we divine to be
something proper to a man and not easily taken from him.
Further, men seem to pursue honour in order that they may be assured of
their goodness....”
Perhaps, he notes, we would say
that the life of virtue is to be preferred to those of pleasure or honor, but,
he notes, “...possession of virtue seems actually compatible with being asleep,
or with lifelong inactivity, and, further, with the greatest sufferings and
misfortunes; but a man who was living so no one would call happy....”
It is thus the activity of the
virtuous person living the virtuous life that he wants to emphasize—an
unactualized disposition is not of interest to him!
[1095b]
-In what follows, Aristotle will
consider different accounts of virtue or excellence.
He identifies wisdom as our excellence, but distinguishes productive,
practical, and theoretical or intellectual wisdom, so his account will be
complex.
Chapter 6. Critique
of Plato’s “Forms:”
In this Chapter, Aristotle discusses Plato’s view of the
forms. First he notes that
Plato uses `good’ in talking of such widely divergent “categories”[3]
[as substance, quality, quantity, and relation—but since these are distinct and
very different categories, they can not share a common property, characteristic,
etc.:
“...but things are
called good both in the category of substance and in that of quality and in that
of relation, and that which is per se,
i.e. substance, is prior in nature to the relative (for the latter is like an
offshoot and accident of what is); so that there could not be a common Idea set
over all these goods. Further,
since things are said to be good in as many ways as they are said to be (for
things are called good both in the category of substance , as God and reason,
and in quality, e.g. the virtues, and in quantity, e.g. that which is moderate,
and in relation, e.g. the useful, and in time, e.g. the right opportunity, and
in place, e.g. the right locality, and the like), clearly the good cannot be
something universally present in all cases and single; for then it would not
have been predicated in all the categories but in one only.
Further, since of the things answering to one Idea there is one science,
there would have been one science of all the goods; but as it is there are many
sciences even of the things that fall under one category, e.g. of opportunity,
for opportunity in war is studied by strategics and in disease by medicine, and
the moderate in food is studied by medicine and in exercise by the science of
gymnastics.” [1096a]
406 Secondly,
he claims that there are a variety of things deemed to be “goods in themselves,”
and if they can be pursued independently and in isolation, then there is not a
common element:
“…of honour, wisdom, and pleasure, just
in respect of their goodness, the accounts are distinct and diverse.
The good, therefore, is not something common answering to one Idea.”
[1096b]
Finally, Aristotle
claims that Plato is “looking” for “the good” in the “wrong place:”
“…even if there is some one good
which is universally predicable of goods or is capable of separate and
independent existence, clearly it could not be achieved or attained by man; but
we are now seeking [in our study of practical reason] something attainable.”
[1097a]
-“For a doctor seems not even to
study health in this way, but the health of man, or perhaps rather the health of
a particular man; it is individuals that he is healing.”
Chapter 7. An
Account of the Human Good—It must be
Self-Sufficient and Final:
The good must be something
final and self-sufficient.
His definition of happiness is reached by considering the characteristic
function of man:
407 “...clearly not all
ends are final ends; but the chief good is evidently something final.
Therefore, if there is only one final end, this will be what we are
seeking, and if there are more than one, the most final of these will be what we
are seeking. Now we call that which
is in itself worthy of pursuit more final than that which is worthy of pursuit
for the sake of something else, and that which is never desirable for the sake
of something else more final than the things that are desirable both in
themselves and for the sake of that other thing, and therefore we call final
without qualification that which is always desirable in itself and never for the
sake of something else.
Now such a thing happiness, above all else is held to be; for this we
choose always for itself and never for the sake of something else, but honor,
pleasure, reason, and every virtue we choose indeed for themselves (for if
nothing resulted from them we should still choose each of them), but we choose
them also for the sake of happiness, judging that by means of them we shall be
happy. Happiness, on the other
hand, no one chooses for the sake of these, nor, in general, for anything other
than itself.
From the point of view of
self-sufficiency the same result seems to follow....”
[1097a]
“...to say that happiness is the chief
good seems a platitude, and a clearer account of what it is is still desired.
This might perhaps be given, if we could first ascertain the function of
man.” -[1097b]
--Aristotle points out
that life [that is nutrition and
growth] is a “function” which we share with
plants.
We are, however, seeking out the particular function of man.
--Similarly,
perception is a function we share
with animals.
[1098a]
-407-408“There remains,
then, an active life of the element that
has a rational principle; of this, one part has such a principle in the
sense of being obedient to one, the other in the sense of possessing one and
exercising thought. And as ‘life of
the rational element’ also has two meanings, we must state that life in the
sense of activity is what we mean; for this seems to be the more proper sense of
the term. Now if the function of
man is an activity of the soul which follows or implies a rational principle,
and if we say ‘a so-and-so’ and a good so-and-so’ have a function which is the
same in kind, e.g. a lyre-player and a good lyre-player, and so without
qualification in all cases, eminence in respect to goodness being added to the
name of the function...human good turns out to be activity of the soul in
accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in accordance
with the best and most complete.
But we must add ‘in a complete
life’. For one swallow does not
make a summer, nor does one day; and so too one day, or a short time, does not
make a man blessed and happy.”
[1098a]
--Aristotle points out
again that we must remember that each inquiry has its appropriate degree of
precision, and we must not expect more precision that in appropriate for a given
discipline.
Chapter 8. A
Defense of the Account in Terms of Popular Views:
408 This definition is confirmed by then current beliefs
about happiness:
Aristotle notes that
“goods” have been divided into those things good externally, those good for the
body, and those good for the soul, and his view accords with this orientation.
[1098b]
Similarly, others distinguish
virtue and happiness with practical wisdom, others with theoretical wisdom, and
others with pleasure and these.
Again, his view accords with such theories.
Similarly, finally, those who
distinguish “noble” pleasures from others, find that his view accords with
theirs.
Chapter 9.
Happiness Is Achieved by Habituation:
409 “…happiness seems,
however, even if it is not god-sent but comes as a result of excellence and some
process of learning or training, to be among the most godlike things; for that
which is the prize and end of excellence seems to be the best thing and
something godlike and blessed.
[1099b]
Chapter 10. Can One
Be Happy During One’s Lifetime?
Should no man be called happy while he lives?
409
“...he is happy who is active in
accordance with complete virtue and is sufficiently equipped with external
goods, not for some chance period but throughout a complete life....”
[1101a]
[Skip: Chapters 11 and 12]
D. Kinds of Virtue:
Chapter 13.
Introduction—The Psychological Foundation of the Virtues:
He discusses the division of the soul (or, better, types of
souls), and resultant division of virtue into intellectual and moral:
410-411 “Virtue too is
distinguished into two kinds in accordance with this difference; for we say that
some of the virtues are intellectual and others moral, philosophic wisdom and
understanding and practical wisdom being intellectual, liberality and temperance
moral. For in speaking about a
man’s character we do not say that he is wise or has understanding but that he
is good-tempered or temperate; yet we praise the wise man also with respect to
his state of mind; and of states of mind we all those which merit praise
virtues.” [1103a]
Book II. Virtue
and. Character:
A. Moral Virtue,
How It Is Produced and Exhibited.
Chapter 1. Moral
Virtue Acquired As the Result of Habits:
Virtue, like the arts, is acquired by repetition of the
corresponding acts:
413 Virtue, then, being
of two kinds, intellectual and
moral, intellectual virtue in the
main owes both its birth and its growth to teaching (for which reason it
requires experience and time), while moral virtue comes about as a result of
habit, whence also its name
ethike is one that is formed by a
slight variation from the word ethos
(habit). From this it is also plain
that none of the moral virtues arises in us by nature for nothing that exists by
nature can form a habit contrary to its nature.
For instance the stone which by nature moves downward cannot be
habituated to move upwards, not even if one tries to train it by throwing it up
ten thousand times; nor can fire be habituated to move downwards, nor can
anything else that by nature behaves in one way be trained to behave in another.
Neither by nature, then, nor contrary to nature do the virtues arise in
us; rather we are adapted by nature to receive them, and made perfect by habit.”
[1103a]
-“...of all the things
that come to us by nature we first acquire the potentiality and later exhibit
the activity...but the virtues we get by first exercising them....”
Chapter 2. There
Can Be No Exact Prescription—One Must Avoid Excess and Defect:
These acts cannot be prescribed exactly, but must
avoid
excess and
defect:
413 “Since, then, the
present inquiry does not aim at theoretical knowledge like the others (for we
are inquiring not in order to know
what virtue is, but in order to become
good, since otherwise our inquiry would have been of no use), we must
examine the nature of actions, namely how we ought to do them; for these
determine also the nature of the states of character that are produced, as we
have said. Now, that we must act
according to the right rule is a common principle and must be assumed....But
this must be agreed upon beforehand, that the whole account of matters of
conduct must be given in outline and not precisely....”
[1103b]
413-414 “...it
is the nature of such things to be destroyed by defect and excess, as we see
in the case of strength and of health...both excessive and defective exercise
destroys the strength, and similarly drink or food which is above or below a
certain amount destroys the health, while that which is proportionate both
produces and increases and preserves it.
So too is it, then, in the case of temperance and courage and the other
virtues....temperance and courage, then, are destroyed by excess and defect, and
preserved by the mean.”
[1104a]
Chapter 3. The
Importance of Pleasure and Pain—they are tests of virtue:
414 Pleasure in doing virtuous acts is a sign that the
virtuous disposition has been acquired: a variety of considerations show the
essential connexion of moral virtue with pleasure and pain.
Chapter 4. Virtuous
Actions vs. Virtuous Character:
415 The actions that produce moral virtue are not good in
the same sense as those that flow from it: the latter must fulfill certain
conditions not necessary in the case of the arts:
“It is possible to do something
that is in accordance with the laws of grammar, either by chance or at the
suggestion of another. A man will
be a grammarian, then, only when he has both
done something grammatical and
done it grammatically; and this means
doing it in accordance with the grammatical knowledge in himself.
Again, the case of the arts and that of the virtues are not similar; for
the products of the arts have their goodness in themselves, so that it is enough
that they should have a certain character, but if the acts that are in
accordance with the virtues have themselves a certain character it does not
follow that they are done justly or temperately.
The agent must be in a certain
condition when he does them; in the first place he must have knowledge, secondly
he must choose the acts, and choose them for their own sakes, and thirdly his
action must proceed from a firm and unchangeable character.”
[1105a]
415 “Actions,
then, are called just and temperate when they are such as the just or the
temperate man would do, but it is not the man who does these that is
just and temperate, but the man who does them
as just and temperate men do them, that it is by doing just acts that
the just man is produced, and by doing temperate acts the temperate man; without
doing these no one would have even the prospect of becoming good.”
-[1105b]
B. The Definition
of Moral Virtue:
Chapter 5. The
Genus of Virtue
is Character:
The genus of moral virtue: it is a
state of character, not a passion
nor a faculty:
415 Aristotle maintains that the
“things” of the soul are either passions, faculties, or states of character.
He contends that the virtues are neither passions nor faculties, and,
therefore, they are states of character.
Chapter 6. The
Differentia of
Virtue of Character—A Disposition to Choose the Mean:
The differentia
of moral virtue: it is a disposition to choose the mean:
416 “In everything that
is continuous and divisible it is possible to take a more, less, or an equal
amount, and that either in terms of the thing itself or relatively to us; and
the equal is an intermediate between excess and defect.
By the intermediate in the object I mean that which is equidistant from
each of the extremes, which is one and the same for all men; by the intermediate
relatively to us that which is neither too much nor too little—and this is not
one, nor the same for all. For
instance, if ten is many and two is few, six is the intermediate taken in terms
of the object; for it exceeds and is exceeded by an equal amount; this is
intermediate according to arithmetical proportion.
But the intermediate relatively to us is not to be taken so; if ten
pounds are too much for a particular person to eat and two too little, it does
not follow that the trainer will order six pounds; for this also is perhaps too
much for the person who is to take it, or too little—too little for Milo, too
much for the beginner in athletic contests.
The same is true of running and wrestling.
Thus a master of any art avoids excess and defect, but seeks the
intermediate and chooses this—the intermediate not in the object but relatively
to us.” [1106a]
416-417 Virtue, then, is a state
of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean, i.e. the mean relative to
us, this being determined by a rational principle, and by that principle by
which the man of practical wisdom would determine it.
Now it is a mean between two vices, that which depends on excess and that
which depends on defect; and again it is a mean because the vices respectively
fall short of or exceed what is right in both passions and action, while virtue
both finds and chooses that which is intermediate.
Hence in respect of its substance and the definition which states its
essence virtue is a mean, with regard to what is best and right an extreme.
[1107a]
-Exception: “but
not every action nor every passion admits of a mean; for some have names that
already imply badness, e.g. spite, shamelessness, envy, and in the case of
actions adultery, theft, murder; for all of these and suchlike things imply by
their names that they are themselves bad, and not the excesses or deficiencies
of them. It is not possible, then,
ever to be right with regard to them; one must always be wrong.
[11071a]
Chapter 7. Examples
of the Mean In Particular Virtues:
[not in text]
417-418 This proposition is illustrated by reference to the
particular virtues:
Activity |
the excess |
the mean |
the defect |
giving and taking money |
prodigality |
liberality |
meanness |
honor and dishonor |
empty vanity |
proper pride |
humility |
truth-telling |
boastfulness |
truthfulness |
mock modesty |
|
envy |
righteous indignation |
spite |
C. Characteristics
of the Extreme and Mean States:
Chapter 8. The
Relation Between the Mean and the Extremes:
The extremes are opposed to each other and to the mean:
418 “There are three
kinds of disposition, then, two of them vices, involving excess and deficiency
respectively, and one a virtue, viz. the mean, and all are in a sense opposed to
all; for the extreme states are contrary both to the intermediate state and to
each other, and the intermediate to the extremes....”
[1108b]
Chapter 9.
Attaining the Mean:
419 The mean is hard to attain, and is grasped by
perception, not by reasoning:
“For in everything it is no easy
task to find the middle, e.g., to find the middle of a circle is not for
everyone but for him who knows; so, too, anyone can get angry—that is easy—or
give or spend money; but to do this to the right person, to the right extent, at
the right time, with the right motive, and in the right way, that is not for
every one, nor is it easy; wherefore goodness is both rare and laudable and
noble.” [1109a]
-“...since to hit the mean is
hard in the extreme, we must as a second best...take the least of the evils....”
[1109a]
-“...the intermediate state is in
all things to be praised, but that we must incline sometimes towards the excess,
sometimes towards the deficiency; for so shall we most easily hit the mean and
what is right.” [1109b]
BOOK III.
A. The Conditions
Needed for Responsible Action:
Chapter 1. Actions
Voluntary and Involuntary:
Moral action requires
absence of compulsion and
knowledge of the circumstances of the
action.
420 When one throws goods overboard during a storm, is this
a voluntary act or an involuntary one?
“Such actions, then, are mixed, but are more like voluntary actions; for
they are worthy of choice at the time when they are done, and the end of an
action is relative to the occasion. Both
the terms, then. “voluntary,” and “involuntary,” must be used with reference to
the moment of the action.” [1110a]
“Everything that is done by
reason of ignorance is not voluntary;
it is only what produces pain and repentance that is
involuntary.
For the man who has done something owing to ignorance and feels not the
least vexation at his action, has not acted voluntarily, since he did not know
what he was doing, nor yet involuntarily, since he is not pained.”
[1110b]
421 “Now every wicked man is
ignorant of what he ought to do…and it is by reason of error of this kind that
men become unjust and in general bade; but if a man
is ignorant of what is to his
advantage—for it is not mistaken purpose that causes involuntary action (it
leads rather to wickedness), nor ignorance of the universal (for that men are
blamed), but ignorance of
particulars, i.e., of the circumstances of the action and objects with which it
is concerned. For it is on these
that both pity and pardon depend, since the person who is ignorant of any of
these acts involuntarily.” 1110b]
Here a footnote from Martin
Ostwald’s translation is helpful: “reasoning on matters of conduct involves two
premises, one major and one minor.
The major premise is always universal, e.g., “to remove by stealth another
person’s property is stealing,” and the minor premise particular, e.g., “this
horse is another person’s property,” so that the conclusion would be: “To remove
this horse by stealth is stealing.”
What Aristotle says her is that ignorance of the major premise produces an
immoral act, while ignorance of the minor premise produces an involuntary act
which may be pitied or pardoned.
Thus it is a moral defect for a man not to know that to remove by stealth
another person’s property is stealing.
In an involuntary act on the other hand, the agent does know the
universal premise, but is ignorant of the particular, i.e., that this horse is
the property of another.”[4]
“Since that which is done under
compulsion or by reason of ignorance is involuntary, the voluntary would seem to
be that of which the moving principle is in the agent himself, he being aware of
the particular circumstances of the action.”
[1111a]
Chapter 2. Choice:
In addition, moral action requires that the action is
done by choice and that
the choice arises from prior
deliberation.
421 “Choice, then, seems to be voluntary, but not the same
thing as the voluntary, the latter extends more widely.
For both children and the lower animals share in voluntary action, but
not in choice, and actions done on the spur of the moment we describe as
voluntary, but not as chosen.”
[1111b]
Chapter 3.
Deliberation—It Regards Means:
423 “We deliberate not about ends but about means.
For a doctor does not deliberate whether he shall heal, nor an orator
whether he shall persuade, nor a statesman whether he shall produce law and
order….They assume the end and consider how and by what means it is to be
attained…. [1112a]
Chapter 4. Rational
Wish—It Regards Ends:
423 “Now those who say that the good is the object of wish
must admit in consequence that that which the man who does not choose aright
wishes for is not an object of wish (for if it is to be so, it must also be
good; but it was, if it is so happened, bad); while those who say the apparent
good is the object of wish must admit that there is no natural object of wish,
but only what seems good to each man.
Now different things appear good to different people, and, if it so
happens, even contrary things.
If these
consequences are unpleasing, are we to say that absolutely and in truth the good
is the object of wish, but for each person the apparent good; that that which is
in truth an object of wish is an object of wish to the good man, while any
chance thing may be so [for] the bad man, as in the case of bodies also the
things that are in truth wholesome are wholesome for bodies which are in good
condition, while for those that are diseased other things are wholesome—or
bitter or sweet or hot or heavy, and so on; since the good man judges each class
of things rightly, and in each the truth appears to him?”[5]
[1113a-b]
Chapter 5. Man As A
Responsible Agent—Both for Good and For Bad:
424 “The end, then, being what we wish for, the means what
we deliberate about and choose, actions concerning means must be according to
choice and voluntary. Now the
exercise of the virtues is concerned with means.
Therefore virtue also is in our own power, and so too vice.
For where it is in our power to act it is also in our power not to act,
and vice versa….Now if it is in our
power to do noble or base acts, and likewise in our power not to do then, and
this was what being good or bad meant, then it is in our power to be virtuous or
vicious.” [1113b]
425 “With regard to the virtues
in general we have stated their genus in outline, viz. that they are means and
that they are stares of character, and that they tend, and by their own nature,
to the doing of the acts by which they are produced, and that they are in our
power and voluntary, and act as the right rule prescribes.
But actions and states of character are not voluntary in the same way,
for we are masters of our actions from the beginning right to the end, if we
know the particular facts, but though we control the beginning of our states of
character the gradual progress is not obvious any more than it is in an illness;
because it was in our power, however, to act in this way or not in this way,
therefore the states are voluntary.
Let us take up several virtues, however, and say which they are and how
they are concerned with them….first let us speak of courage.”
[1114b-1115a]
B. The Virtues and
Vices [Book III 6-Book V 11]:
Chapter 6. Courage
and Its Sphere of Operation:
It is concerned with feelings of fear and confidence; and
is clearly in evidence when life is threatened in battle.
[1115a]
425 “Now we fear all evils, e.g.,
disgrace, poverty, disease, friendlessness, death, the brave man is not thought
to be concerned with all….Now death is the most terrible of all things; for it
is the end, and nothing is thought to be any longer either good or bad for the
dead.” [1115a]
Here, once more we get the point that the virtues he wants
to talk about have a “duality” that comes from our nature and the “four causes:”
the final cause (telos or end) and
the particular nature of the individual intermix and just as in the case of Milo
and the ordinary citizen, the “mean” will have both a common and an individual
specification. Talking about
courage in battle helps focus on the common element (remember, here, the
“traditional” [Homeric] conception of
arête and its influence on his view and his culture.
Chapter 7. Courage:
Its Nature and Its Opposites:
Courage is motivated by a sense of
honor, and its opposites are
rashness (excess)
and cowardice (deficiency).
427 “What is terrible I not the same for all men….”
[1115b]
Attend, again, to the above
comment about “duality.”
Chapter 8.
Qualities Similar to Courage:
426-427 He discusses the courage of: the citizen, of
Socrates, of the wounded, of the experienced soldier, and of those ignorant of
the danger. [1116a-1117a]
Chapter 9. The
Relation of Pleasure and Pain to Courage:
428 Just as boxers
aim at a pleasant end, but experience many blows to achieve it, “…courage is
similar, death and wounds will be painful to the brave man and against his will,
but he will face them because it is noble
to do so or because it is base not to
do so.” [1117b]
The “Middle” Core
of the Work:
In the ensuing discussion Aristotle discusses the virtues
of: temperance (self-indulgence and ‘insensibility’), liberality with money
(prodigality and meanness), magnificence with money (meanness and
niggardliness), pride (vanity and humility), honor (ambition and its opposite),
good temper (irascibility and its opposite), friendliness (obsequiousness, and
churlishness), truthfulness (boastfulness and mock-modesty), wit (buffoonery and
boorishness), shame (bashfulness and shamelessness), and justice (extended
discussion). He then turns to
discussions of intellectual virtue [Book VI], continence and pleasure [Book
VII], friendship [Book IX], and pleasure’s relation to happiness [Book X,
Chapters 1-6]. We pick up with his
general discussion of happiness [Book X, Chapters 6-9].
Supplemental
Reading Regarding the Intellectual Virtues:[6]
Book X. Chapters
6-9: Happiness:
Chapter 6.
Happiness, Activity and Amusement:
1176b-1177a] Summary—attend to it carefully!
Chapter 7.
Happiness, Intelligence, and the Contemplative Life:
[1177a] “If happiness is activity
in accord with virtue, it is reasonable for it to accord with the supreme
virtue, which will be the virtue of the best thing.
The best is understanding, or whatever else seems to be the natural ruler
and leader, and to understand what is fine and divine, by being itself either
divine or the most divine element in us.
Hence complete happiness will be its activity in accord with its proper
virtue; and we have said that this activity is the activity of study.
This seems to agree with what has been said before, and also with the
truth. For this activity is
supreme, since understanding is the supreme element in us, and the objects of
understanding are the supreme objects of knowledge.
Further, it is the most continuous
activity, since we are more capable of continuous study than any continuous
activity.”
Note: it should be clear that
Aristotle is not working with the common conception of the gods in his culture.
His talk of the divine as being wholly non-human (and associated with the
life of rational cognition) is not simply the then common view of the lives of
the gods. Jump, here, to 1178b for
a related passage which helps us clarify what he is contending when he both
“privileges” the intellectual virtues, but doesn’t contend that they are the
only important virtue.
[1177b] “Such a life would be superior to the human level.
For someone will live in it not insofar as he is a human being, but
insofar as he has some divine element in him.”
Here, again, we need to pay
attention to the “duality” which comes from speaking of the “common end) for
men, and the “golden mean” in this sense of virtue, and the end for each
particular individual.
Chapter 8.
Theoretical Study and the Other Virtues: The Advantages of the Contemplative
Life:
[1178a] “The life in
accord with the other kind of virtue [i.e., the kind concerned with action] is
[happiest] in a secondary way, because the activities in accord with this virtue
are human. For we do just and brave
actions, and the other actions in accord with the virtues, in relation to other
people, by abiding by what fits each person in contracts, services, all types of
actions, and also in feelings; and all these appear to be human conditions.
Indeed, some feelings actually seem to arise from the body; and in many
ways virtue of character seems to be proper to feelings.”
Here, I believe,
we confront a fundamental interpretative issue in reading the
Nicomachean Ethics.
Throughout our primary selection (Books I and II), and, indeed, in the
remainder of the work (Books III-Book V and Books VII-X Chapter 5), with the
exception of Book VI, Aristotle discusses the “moral virtues.”
In Book VI he distinguishes “theoretical” and “practical” wisdom, and
initially states what he reiterates in our supplemental selection (Book X,
Chapters 7-8 [I will discuss the final Chapter in a moment])—that
the intellectual virtues are higher than the moral ones and that
practical wisdom can not be higher than
theoretical wisdom:
[Book VI, Chapter 13,
1145a] “But again it [practical wisdom] is not
supreme over philosophic wisdom, i.e.
over the superior part of us, any more than the art of medicine is over health;
for it does not use it but provides for its coming into being; it issues orders,
then, for its sake, but not to it.
Further, to maintain its supremacy would be like saying that the art of politics
rules the gods because it issues orders about the affairs of the state.”
These passages lead to a
picture of Aristotle’s view of the highest good as largely akin to that of
Plato—the highest good for human beings is the life of philosophic
contemplation, of the pursuit of “theoretical wisdom” (and “philosophical or
theoretical” activity, which is the most continuous) over “practical wisdom”
(and activity). On this
interpretation, the “[highest] end for human beings” is the life of the
philosopher. There is much to
recommend this interpretation, and the textual evidence in Book VI and X
(Chapters 7-8) certainly support it unequivocally.
I want to
advance a different interpretation however.
Looking back at his critique of Plato’s doctrine of the forms (Book I,
Chapter 6), and paying attention both to his view that forms are immanent rather
than transcendent, and to his view that human beings are fundamentally social
beings (that the state is the “end” for us), I interpret his mention of the
“godlike” character of the philosophic life as “qualifying” his praise in Book
VI and Book X Chapters 7-8. His
view of actual human beings is that
we are complex—we have a soul with
nutritive, perceptual, emotional, and
intellectual elements; and talk of our “end” (“final cause”) must pay close
attention to all these “elements” (as well as to our “material, efficient, and
formal” “causes”). Contemplation
for Plato can have a significant “otherworldly” element, but this can not be the
case for Aristotle. While the
“intellectual” element of the soul may be “higher” (while the “intellectual”
virtues may be superior to the “moral” ones),
character (and, thus
virtue) is the state of an
individual, not simply of a
component thereof.
That is, the
contemplative life is a life after
all, which means (for Aristotle) that it takes place in a
body, in a
state, and
in collaboration with other individuals.
Thus, I believe, the praise of the intellectual virtues and the
contemplative (or philosophical) life must be seen in context, and, I think,
Aristotle so qualifies the praise in the final Chapter of his
Nicomachean Ethics (Book X Chapter
9).
Chapter 9. Moral
Education and Politics:
Aristotle has just praised the intellectual virtues as the
“highest” and the life of philosophical contemplation as “the best.”
Indeed he has deemed it “godlike,” and talked of the “moral virtues”
(those associated with action in the world with other individuals) as good in a
“secondary way” (as being “merely human”).
While the study of politics will be important as facilitating a
means to achieving theoretical wisdom
and the contemplative life, Aristotle here seems to “qualify” his praise for
that life:
[1179b] “…the aim of
studies about action…is surely not to study and know about a given thing, but
rather to act on our knowledge.
Hence knowing about virtue is not enough, but we must also try to possess and
exercise virtue….
Now if arguments were sufficient by themselves to make people decent, the
rewards they command would justifiably have been many and large….In fact,
however, arguments seem to have enough influence to stimulate and encourage the
civilized ones among the young people, and perhaps to make virtue take
possession of a well-born character that truly loves what is fine; but they seem
unable to turn the many toward being fine and good.”
“Now some think it is
nature that makes people good; some
think it is habit; some that it is
teaching.
The [contribution] of nature is clearly not up to us, but results from
some divine cause in those who have it, who are the truly fortunate ones.
Arguments and teaching surely do not prevail on everyone, but the soul of
the student needs to have been prepared by habits for enjoying and hating
finely, like ground that is to nourish seed.”
“It is difficult, however, for
someone to be trained correctly for virtue from his youth if he has not been
brought up under correct laws….”
[1180a-b] “That is why
legislators must, in some people’s view, urge people toward virtue and exhort
them to aim at the fine—on the assumption that anyone whose good habits have
prepared him decently will listen to them—but must impose corrective treatments
and penalties on anyone who disobeys or lacks the right nature, and must
completely expel the incurable.”
“It is best, then, if the
community attends to upbringing, and attends correctly.
But if the community neglects it, it seems fitting for each individual to
promote the virtue of his children and friends….”
[1180b] “Further, education
adapted to an individual is actually better than a common education for
everyone, just as individualized medical treatment is better.
For though generally a feverish patient benefits from rest and
starvation, presumably some patient does not; nor does the boxing instructor
impose the same way of fighting on everyone.
Hence it seems that treatment in particular cases is more exactly right
when each person gets special attention, since he then more often gets the
suitable treatment.”
“Then perhaps also someone who
wishes to make people better by his attention, many people or few, should try to
acquire legislative science, if laws are a means to make us good.
For not just anyone can improve the condition of jut anyone, or the
person presented to him; but if someone can, it is the person with knowledge,
just as in medical science and the others that require attention and prudence.”
In ending the
Nicomachean Ethics, then, Aristotle says we must study
politics, and must attend to the
science of using laws, education, and habituation to prepare the ground for
individuals to develop virtuous characters.
Now if the highest end is the pursuit of philosophical wisdom and
intellectual virtue, if the contemplative life was the true highest end for
human beings, then the detailed discussion of the need to go on and pursue the
empirical study of constitutions and states to yield the practical science of
politics would seem out of place here.
Of course the “praise” of political science here could be no more than
the praise of a means to the ultimate end of theoretical wisdom; but I can’t buy
that interpretation. I think it
works only for those individuals who are “lucky” enough to have the “divine
gift” [1179b] of a nature already habituated to virtue (and, indeed, to the
highest of the virtues). But these
people are “godlike,” and Aristotle, I contend, is concerned with
real individuals, and with
virtuous character instantiated in the
mundane (rather than some “divine”)
world. Thus, I interpret him as
ultimately coming down on the side of the “moral” (or “practical”) virtues—of
advocating “practical” wisdom over the “theoretical” for man, and of praising
politics over philosophy. There
are, of course, many who reject this view (and they are, I should add, far
better schooled in Aristotle than I).
[1] Our text
reproduces selections from W.D. Ross’ 1930
translation of Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics as it is revised by J.L.
Acknill and J.O. Urmson in 1980 (Oxford: Oxford
U.P.).
These notes are sometimes based upon
Ross’s unrevised translation, so there may be
minor differences between my citations and those
in the text.
The titles for Books and Chapters are
borrowed (in part) from Ross, from Martin
Ostwald’s translation of the
Nicomachean Ethics (Indianapolis:
Bobbs-Merrill, 1962), and from Terence Irwin’s
translation of the
Nicomachean Ethics (second edition)
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1999).
[2] As
Richard McKeon notes (in his “Introduction,” in
The Basic
Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon
(N.Y.: Random House, 1941), pp. xi-xxxiv, p.
viii), “the pagination of the Bekker edition of
the Greek text of Aristotle [1831-1870], which
is published in the first two of the five
volumes of the Berlin edition, has become the
customary means to locate a passage in
Aristotle....”
This passage is in Chapter 1 of Book I of
the
Nicomachean Ethics, the first column (a) of
page 1094.
The editors of our text,
Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings,
eds. Louis Pojman and James Fieser (Boston:
Wadsworth, 2011), do not use the standard
reference system, and so I will use their
pagination in referring to passages, and I will
follow each citation with the standard
reference.
For the selections from Book X which I am
having your read, I will use the standard
reference method.
[3] The
categories are general types of predicates
assignable to subjects.
The most basic category is
substance
(or being) and these predicates answer to
the question “What is it?”
Ensuing categories are
quantity
(answering “How large is it?”),
quality
(answering “What sort is it?”),
relation,
etc.
[4] Martin
Ostwald’s translation of Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics,
op. cit.,
p. 55 (footnote).
[5] In his
footnote to his translation of this sentence
Martin Ostwald maintains: “this seemingly
trivial sentence is, in fact, one of the most
important in the
Ethics.
It seems trivial in that it hinges on the
double meaning inherent in the Greek verbal
adjective
boulēton here translated as ‘object of
wish’), which means (1) an actual object of
wish, something wished as a matter of fact; and
(2) something intrinsically wishable, the true
object of wish as an ethical norm.
But behind this linguistic ambiguity lies
the whole question of the factual and normative
in ethical choices.
Aristotle’s solution is to recognize
“Whatever seems good to a particular individual”
as the factual object of all wishes and choice,
but at the same time to insist upon the
existence of a normative object of wish, which
is “by nature the object of wish” and which he
defines as the end actually wished and chosen by
the good man. This shows in what sense the man
of high moral standards is for Aristotle the
“standard and measure,” who makes the actual and
the normative coincide.”
Nichomachean Ethics, trans. Martin Ostwald
(Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1962), pp. 63-64
(footnote).
[6] The
supplement is taken from the web version of W.D.
Ross’s translation available at:
http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.10.x.html
.
File revised on: 11/25/2013.