Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
Criticisms of
Aristotle’s Ethics:
1. Aristotle looks for
the function of human beings, but why
assume there is a function, and why assume there is a
unique one?
“What is the function of paper
[writing, wrapping, lining, etc.]?”
2. In his Inventing
Right and Wrong, J.L. Mackie contends that:
as guidance about what is the good
life, what precisely one ought to do, or even by what standard one should try to
decide what one ought to do, this is too circular to be very helpful.
And though Aristotle’s account is filled out with detailed descriptions
of many of the virtues, moral as well as intellectual, the air of indeterminacy
persists. We learn the names of the
pairs of contrary vices that contrast with each of the virtues, but very little
about where or how to draw the dividing lines, where or how to fix the mean.
As Sidgwick says, he “only indicates the whereabouts of virtue.”[1]
This critique is echoed by many.
Robert Louden, in his “Some Vices of Virtue Ethics,” for example,
contends that while Aristotle tells us that right acts are those which are means
between extremes, it is almost impossible to determine how to apply this
conception in actual situations:
...virtues are not simply
dispositions to behave in specified ways, for which rules and principles can
always be cited. In addition, they
involve skills of perception and articulation, situation-specific “know-how,”
all of which are developed only through recognizing and acting on what is
relevant in concrete moral contexts as they arise.
These skills of moral perception and practical reason are not completely
routinizable, and so cannot be transferred from agent to agent as any sort of
decision procedure....Due to the very nature of the moral virtues, there is thus
a very limited amount of advice on moral quandaries that one can reasonably
expect from the virtue-oriented approach.[2]
He concludes that virtue-based ethics can not be of any use
in applied ethics or in casuistry.
3. Robert Louden also offers the following criticisms of
Aristotle’s sort of virtue-based ethical theory:
another reason for making sure that
our ethical theory allows us to talk about features of acts and their results in
abstraction from the agent is his conception of what he is doing is that
sometimes even the best person can make the wrong choices.
There are cases in which a man’s choice is grounded in the best possible
information, his motives honorable, and his action not at all out of character.
And yet his best laid plans may go sour.
Aristotle, in his Poetics, suggests that here lies the source of
tragedy....Virtue ethics, however, since its conceptual scheme is rooted in the
notion of a good person, is unable to assess correctly the occasional
(inevitable) tragic outcomes of human action.[3]
A third reason for insisting that our moral theory enable us
to assess acts in abstraction from agents is that we need to be able to identify
certain types of action which produce harms of such magnitude that they destroy
the bonds of community and render (at least temporarily) the achievement of
moral goods impossible.[4]
A fourth reason for insisting that a moral theory be able to
assess acts in abstraction from agents and their conception of what they’re
doing is that people’s moral characters may sometimes change.[5]
...the focus on good and bad agents rather than on right and
wrong actions may lead to a peculiar sort of moral backsliding.
Because the emphasis in agent ethics is on long-term, characteristic
patterns of behavior, its advocates run the risk of overlooking occasional lies
or acts of selfishness on the ground that such performances are mere temporary
aberrations—acts out of character.[6]
...we do not seem to be able to know
with any degree of certainty who really is virtuous and who vicious.”[7]
This means that moral skepticism is a serious problem for a virtue-based ethical
system.
4. In her The Therapy
of Desire, Martha Nussbaum offers the following criticisms of Aristotle’s
ethical theory:
Aristotelian dialectic...makes
several controversial assumptions about the nature of the ordinary person’s
ethical beliefs. It assumes that
these beliefs are essentially healthy: truth is in there, along with whatever is
false, and in such a way that, in the process of scrutiny, the true beliefs will
turn out to be the “greatest number and the most basic.”
Since the beliefs in question are for the most part socially taught, the
procedure also assumes the relative health of the surrounding society.
Moreover, the method assumes that the most important beliefs lie close to
the surface of the interlocutor’s reason in such a way that they can be elicited
by calm dialectical questioning. And
finally, the method appears to assume that everyone who
ought to be helped by the dialectical process
can be so helped: it points to no troublesome gap between the
availability of rational “therapy” and the needs of its intended recipients.
Such assumptions seem to Epicurus at best naive, at worst obtuse and
callous. He invites us to look at
ourselves, at our friends, at the society in which we live.
What do we see when we look, and look honestly?”[8]
Nussbaum continues this discussion by questioning each of
these assumptions in turn: people with unhealthy beliefs (“victims of false
social advertising”), a sick society (“whose sick teachings about love and sex
turn half of its members into possessions”), “people who are profoundly ignorant
of what they believe and what motivates them,” and a process which helps only
those who are already well off and have a “liberal education.”
She concludes the passage by maintaining:
Epicurus challenges us, then, to
recognize that Aristotelian dialectic may be powerless to help where help is
most urgently needed, powerless to criticize where the need for philosophical
critique is greatest. A philosophy
that stops here is not only impotent but also callous: a tool of exploitation,
an accomplice of misery. The
powerful challenge compels us: can we recognize both the depth of social ills
and the delicate complexity of the human psyche and still remain believers in
the calm give-and-take of “Aristotelian” ethical argument?[9]
Nussbaum also maintains that:
Aristotle cares too much about
self-sufficiency and rational control to admit love in all its terribleness.
He permits many risks, but he despises slavery too much to admit to
intrinsic value a kind of relation in which we are so completely within the
power of another, inhabited, intertwined, with no hard core to our natures.
The Stoic remedy is a contraction of boundaries.
But if we refuse this remedy, we must, it seems, learn to imagine
ourselves with new images: not as safe house-dwellers in the solid edifice of
our own virtue, but as beings soft and sinuous, weaving in and out of the world,
in and out of one another.[10]
5. In his “Natural Affection and Responsibility for
Character,” Gregory Trianosky maintains that:
...although one’s attitudes,
emotions, reactive capacities, and skills are or can to some extent be developed
by will, no effort of will, however sustained, is
sufficient for their development.
Character is the product not only of voluntary action but also of the
activity of temperament, along with upbringing, childhood experiences, social
environment, peer expectations, and pure happenstance.
And not only temperament but all of these things are not themselves the
product of some exercise of agency, whether voluntary or nonvoluntary.
Hence, no Aristotelian account of responsibility for character can
succeed.[11]
6. In her “Aristotle and the Politicization of the Soul,”
Elizabeth Spelman maintains that:
...Aristotle does
not try to justify his view about the
natural rule of men over women by reference to a general principle about ruling
and subject elements, for he quite explicitly refers us in particular to the
constitution of the soul. There we
find ruling and subject elements, but they are highly personalized entities
whose relationships are described in terms of political relationships among
human beings. In light of this, we
must conclude that Aristotle’s argument for the natural rule of men over women
is circular. He argues for the
position that men by nature rule women.
How do we know that they do?
We know this because the rational element of the soul by nature rules the
irrational element. And how do we
know this? This is where we come
full circle: Because men rule women (and also because masters rule slaves,
because tutors rule children). In
fact the rule of men over women provides us with a means of understanding the
kind of relationship among parts of the soul; and, coupled with the assumption
that men represent the rational element and women represent the irrational
element, it provides us with a means of establishing that in the soul the
rational element rules the irrational.[12]
[1]
J.L. Mackie,
Ethics:
Inventing Right and Wrong (N.Y.: Penguin,
1977), p. 186.
[2]
Robert Louden, “Some Vices of Virtue Ethics,” in
Ethical Theory Classic and Contemporary Readings (first edition),
ed. Louis Pojman (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1989), pp.
311-320, pp. 313-314.
This article originally appeared in
The
American Philosophical Quarterly v. 21
(1984), pp. 227-236.
[3]
Ibid.,
p. 314.
[4]
Ibid.,
pp. 314-315.
[5]
Ibid.,
p. 315
[6]
Ibid.
[7]
Ibid.,
p. 316.
[8]
Martha Nussbaum,
The
Therapy of Desire (Princeton: Princeton
U.P., 1994), pp. 102-103.
[9]
Ibid.,
p. 104.
[10]
Ibid.,
p. 481
[11]
Gregory Trianosky, “Natural Affection and
Responsibility for Character,” in
Identity,
Character, and Morality, eds. Owen Flanagan
and Amelie Rorty (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990),
pp. 93-109, p. 104.
[12]
Elizabeth Spelman, “Aristotle and the
Politicization of the Soul,”
in Social
and Political Philosophy: Classical Western
Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives,
ed. James Sterba (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1995), pp.
63-72, p. 69.
Last revised on: 12/01/2013.