Lecture Supplement
Introducing Aristotle’s Nicomachean
Ethics
Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
I. Aristotle’s
Life:
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.) was the son of the court
physician of Amyntas II, King of Macedon—who was the father of Philip the Great.
He was born in
In 343 when Philip of Macedon invited him come to
Aristotle resumed his own studies, and returned to
In his “Introduction” to his edition of
The Basic Works of Aristotle, Richard
McKeon maintains that:
the period of Aristotle’s most
characteristic and productive scientific activity coincided almost exactly with
the reign and campaigns of Alexander the Great.
Moreover, the greater part of his career as a student and as teacher was
spent in
II. A Brief
Introduction to The Ancient Worldview:
In her “Excellence and Obligation: A
Very Concise History of Western
Metaphysics 387 BC to 1887 AD,” Christine Korsgaard maintains that:
Plato and Aristotle came
to believe that value was more real than
experienced fact, indeed that the real world is, in a way, value itself.
They came to see the world we experience as being, in its very essence, a
world of things that are trying to be much better than they are, and that really
are much better than they seem....Plato believed that the essence of a thing is
the form in which it participates.
A thing’s true nature and its perfect nature are one and the same.
Form, which is value, is more real than the things that appear to us to
participate in but fall short of it.
Aristotle believed that the
actuality of a thing is its form, which makes it possible for the thing to
do what it does and therefore to be what it is....For Plato and Aristotle, being
guided by value is a matter of being guided by the way things ultimately
are.
In ethics, this way of viewing the
world leads to what we might call the idea of
arête [excellence or
virtue].
Being guided by the way things really are is, in this case, being guided
by the way you really are.
The form of a thing is its perfection, but it is also what enables the
thing to be what it is. So the
endeavor to realize perfection is just the endeavor to be what you are—to be
good at being what you are.
And so the ancients thought of human virtue as a kind of excelling, of
excellence.[5]
According to Korsgaard,
we are no longer at all
puzzled about why the world, being good, is yet not good.
Because for us, the world is no longer first and foremost form.
It is matter.
This is what I mean when I say that there has been a revolution, and that
the world has been turned inside out.
The real is no longer the good.
For us, reality is something hard,
something that resists reason and value, something that is recalcitrant to form.
If the real and the good are no
longer one, value must find its way into the world somehow.
Form must be imposed on the world of matter.
This is the work of art, the work of obligation, and it brings us back to
Kant.[6]
Korsgaard, in short, alerts us to “the fact” that our
“fact/value” question (or distinction) wasn’t found in its current form in Plato
and Aristotle.
A.R Caponigri draws our attention to the difference between the Ancient
and the Modern views of motion and change.
He notes that the Ancient and Medieval worldviews relied upon
...the distinction between
elementary substances: Earth, water, air and fire, and celestial substances.
This distinction, in turn, rests on a further and more basic distinction
between the kinds of motion and their distribution in the cosmos.
Motion is distinguished into rectilinear and circular.
The circular is thought to be “perfect”....because its beginning and its
end coincide; the rectilinear is imperfect....These types of motion are then
distributed and assigned: rectilinear motion to the elementary substances,
circular motion to the celestial.
Likewise proceeding by this logical process of conceptualization and
analysis of concepts, this view holds that the circular movement of the
celestial elements is eternal; but that of the elementary substances is
predicated upon rest, from which they must be moved by a principle external to
them. This rest is identified as
the “natural place” of the elementary substance in the universe: lower for the
heavier, higher for the lighter and more volatile.
“Upper” and “lower” are absolute determinations in space.
The rectilinear movement of the elementary substances is due to the fact
of their initial displacement from their natural locations, to which they seek
to return.”[7]
As Michael Matthews notes,
central to Aristotle’s thought is
his concept of nature. This was
essentialistic and
teleological.
Nature was not just matter moving around as a result of random pushes and
pulls (materialism), nor was it an unintelligible and imperfect shadow of some
other perfect realm (Platonism).
Nature was differentiated into various species and objects, all of them had
their own internal and essential dynamic
for change (including local motion).
Their alteration was the progressive, teleological actualization of a
preexisting potential. The universe
was finite, closed, hierarchically ordered, and all its constituents were fixed.
Everything had its own preordained purpose.
In appropriate circumstances, the acorn would develop through an
internally generated process of natural change. Likewise, when not interfered
with, heavy objects would naturally move to their natural place at the centre of
the earth. Science was largely
concerned with the understanding of these natural changes in the world.
The contrasting violent or chance changes were of little interest to
philosophers, as they did not reveal anything of the object’s nature.[8]
Think of the difference between having the
growth of an acorn and the
falling of a ball-bearing as your
scientific model and you can come to a better understanding of the contrast
between the Aristotelian and Medieval world-views, on the one hand, and the
early Modern world-view, on the other.
The Aristotelian notion of causation involves a compilation of four
distinct notions:
-the material cause—what a thing
is made of,
-the formal cause—how a thing is
structured,
-the efficient cause—what brings
a thing about, and
-the final cause—the goal/purpose
of a thing.
Together talk about matter and form are to answer the
questions we can ask about what causes a thing to be what it is.
The full story here requires talk about the four Aristotelian causes—they
provide a complete explanation both of what a thing came from and where it is
going:
|
Matter |
Form |
Where it is going |
material cause |
final cause |
Where it came from |
efficient cause |
formal cause |
While a full understanding of anything requires that we
understand all four causes, the final cause is the most important one—Aristotle
offers a teleological view![9]
Not everything lives up to its final cause however—consider two acorns
which have the same internal character but are grown in very different
environments. Thus the talk of the
other causes becomes quite important for him.
Talk of these other causes requires that we recognize that a thing may be
judged against either an absolute standard (in terms of consideration only of
the final cause) or against a more relativistic standard (which considers all
the causes).
III. Introduction
to Aristotle’s Philosophy By Way of Contrast With Plato:
Like Socrates and Plato, Aristotle was concerned to deny
the conventionalism of the sophists
and to establish the objective validity
of our knowledge and values. There
is a central similarity in the pictures that these three philosophers offer:
each recommends the life of philosophic reflection as the best life.
Moreover each maintains that the state plays a fundamentally moral role,
and the good life is, essentially, a social one.
There are significant differences between Aristotle’s philosophical
orientation and Plato’s, however, and an examination of some epistemological and
metaphysical points will help clarify the differences in their thought:
Plato explains the objectivity of
our knowledge and values by an appeal to
a changeless world of “the forms.”
This world was to explain (and ground) the changing world which we
inhabit. However, one of the main
problems Plato’s theory faces is the problem of change—he must explain the
obvious fact of change in this world,
and it is not clear how appeal to unchanging forms can facilitate this.
Similarly, and secondly, Plato confronts the
problem of participation—to the
extent that his forms do not change, and are so very different from the things
in this world, it is questionable how well they could do the explanatory job for
which they were created—it is not clear how the forms “participate” in the
particular things which are to be explained.
Plato also sought exact and
certain knowledge. His model of
knowledge was mathematics, and he wanted to appeal to timeless, external,
universal, and unchanging standards.
For him knowledge was to be achieved by the exercise of pure reason that
produced certainty, and its object was the otherworldly forms.
He held that belief was the appropriate attitude in regard to the
changing world, and here we dealt with fallible opinion rather than knowledge.
Aristotle wanted to avoid the
otherworldliness of Plato. Yet
he also wanted to avoid the
conventionalism (or relativism)
of the sophists. To achieve this
complex objective he opted for the following metaphysical position:
the forms are
not separate, other-worldly, and
logically prior to the particular things in this world—rather the forms are
immanent in the changing things in
this world. That is, according to
Aristotle each particular thing is composed of
both form and matter (“thisness”
and “suchness“):
-suchness: the universal
characteristic (necessary for knowledge), the properties which various
particular things can share in common—it is the form which provides an answer to
the question “What is it?” which is asked of a particular thing; and
-thisness: that which makes a
particular thing (e.g., this course, this person, etc.) itself—it is this which
provides for the identity of the individual through change.
Aristotle also felt Plato placed too much emphasis upon theoretical (or
pure) knowledge. According to
Aristotle, there are three different sorts of knowledge: the
theoretical, the
productive, and the
practical:
theoretical knowledge (which is
concerned with knowledge for knowledge’s sake) is the “pure” exercise of reason
in the areas of metaphysics, physics, and mathematics;
productive knowledge (which is
concerned with putting reason to use in the service of our immediate needs) is
oriented toward concrete action in the changeable world producing results which
satisfy our needs; and
practical knowledge (which deals
with the use of reason for the organization of our lives) in the areas of
politics and ethics. As Martin
Ostwald notes, the practical sciences resemble the productive “...in that the
initiating motive...is in man himself and not external to him, as it is in the
theoretical sciences. But in the
practical sciences [politics and ethics] man is a moral agent rather than a
producer. His end is not the
creation of a product which will exist independent of him once it is completed,
but rather the living of a certain kind
of life. In other words, in the
practical sciences the end is neither the study or knowledge of something
external to man as it is in the theoretical sciences, nor is it the creation of
a product that will exist apart from him as soon as it is completed.
It is the very activity of living a good life that is in itself the end.”[10]
Aristotle also felt that each subject matter admits of its
own appropriate degree of precision.
While Plato held that knowledge was the same wherever it was found,
Aristotle held that each area or discipline had its own standards of accuracy
and precision. Here Aristotle’s
scientific orientation differs significantly from Plato’s rationalistic one.
The differences between Plato and Aristotle regarding both the object of
knowledge (another world, this world) and regarding our cognitive states when
knowing (certainty, different levels of precision for different sciences), are
reflected in their overall world-views.
Plato was most concerned with reaching theoretical knowledge of the
other-worldly forms dialectically, while Aristotle wanted to arrive at
scientific knowledge of the changing world.
While Plato was a “rationalist” and Aristotle was an “empiricist,”
however, as we have seen, we must not attribute
our science to him.
He is certainly not an empiricist in the sense that such a thinker
develops testable hypotheses, theories, laws, or explanations and then tests
predictions in our experience of the world.
This is a view that will not come on the scene for almost two thousand
years.
To get a quick idea of the sense in which Aristotle was an empiricist, we
should look to his work in biology.
Aristotle developed a careful classification of animals based upon observations
(both his own and those of others) of more than 500 distinct kinds of animals.
Some of his observations were so detailed that they support the following
claim by W.T. Jones:
it is difficult…to draw a firm
line between experiment and observation.
Did Empedocles, for instance, merely happen to observe what occurs when
the end of a tube is submerged in water and seize on this as support for his
theory about the plenum? Or was the
tube a device to test the theory? Probably
the former. On the other hand, the
Pythagoreans must have experimented to discover the ratios of their tuned lyre.
Was Aristotle experimenting when he observed the embryo chicken?
This question cannot be answered by a simple “yes” or “no,” for this is a
borderline case in which we cannot be sure what Aristotle’s intent was.
Yet there is a difference in
principle between (1) recognizing the interest and importance of some fact when
one chances to see it and (2) deliberately planning a situation that will test
some hypothesis.
The Greek neglect of experiment is one of the chief points that
distinguishes their method from that of modern science.
Perhaps “neglect” is too strong a word, for it may suggest that they left
something undone that they might easily have done.
Experiment is connected with an appreciation of the complexity of nature,
with a recognition of the necessity of deciding between alternatives.
And the Greeks had no reason at the outset of the development of science
to believe nature to be as complex as we know it to be.
Though their conviction that nature is a simply organized cosmos may have
made them too facile, it had its fortunate aspect.
Had they been aware of how complex the order really is they might have
been too discouraged even to begin investigating it.[11]
The description of the chick embryo that Jones refers to is
in Aristotle’s Historia Animalium (The
History of the Animals) and goes on for several pages.
Here is a portion of the discussion:
generation of the egg
proceeds in an identical manner with all birds, but the full periods from
conception to birth differ….With the common hen after three days and three
nights there is the first indication of the embryo; with larger birds the
interval is longer, with smaller birds shorter.
Meanwhile the yolk comes into being, raising towards the sharp end, where
the primal element of the egg is situated, and where the egg gets hatched; the
heart appears, like a speck of blood, in the white of the egg.
This point beats and moves as though endowed with life, and from it two
vein-ducts with blood in them then in a convoluted course….and a membrane
carrying bloody fibres now envelops the yolk, leading off from the vein-ducts.
A little afterwards the body is differentiated, at first very small and
white. The head is clearly
distinguished, and in it the eyes, swollen out to a great extent….It is only by
degrees that they diminish in size and collapse.
At the outset the under portion of the body appears insignificant in
comparison with the upper portion….The life-element of the chick is in the white
of the egg, and the nutriment comes through the navel-string out of the yolk.[12]
As W.D. Ross notes, Aristotle rejects Plato’s “method of
division by dichotomy” (which seems to arbitrarily classify animals without
sufficient attention to the many similarities amongst species), and offers a
much more complex classification scheme:
no cut-and-dried
classification is to be found in his writings.
He is well aware of the difficulties; well aware of the existence of
isolated species which fall under no recognized `greatest genus,’ and of species
intermediate between two such genera.
But his classification is clear enough in its main lines, and is one that
has on the whole stood well the test of time; it was a great advance on anything
that preceded it, and no further advance was made before Linnaeus [1707-1778].[13]
As Ross notes,
the sciences of Aristotle are
based on a multiple system of classification, not on a simple scheme of mutually
exclusive and independently existent genera and species, and one of the
important contributions of metaphysical analysis to the sciences is the
elaboration of causes which permits the differentiation of the subject matters
of the natural sciences.[14]
In regard to ethics, as Ross notes, Aristotle notes that
ethics reasons not from but to
first principles: it starts out not with what is intelligible in itself but
which what is familiar to us, i.e., with the bare facts, and works back from
them to the underlying reasons; and to give the necessary knowledge of the facts
a good upbringing is necessary….The first principles of ethics are too deeply
immersed in the detail of conduct to be...easily picked out, and the substance
of ethics consists in picking them out.
For this two conditions are needed.
Firstly, the student must be so brought up that he accepts the general
opinions on moral questions that represent the collective wisdom of the race.
These opinions are not very clear nor very consistent, but such as they
are, they are the only data we have from which to reach the first principles.
The second condition is an enquiry in which these beliefs are examined,
compared with one another, purged of their inaccuracies and inconsistencies, and
found to yield truths `more intelligible in themselves,’ by no means obvious at
first sight but self-evident when once you have reached them.
If ethics is not demonstrative, is it then…dialectical?
In a sense it is; one of the uses of dialectic is just this, to lead us
to first principles. Hence
Aristotle often reasons dialectically, not from the principles known to be true
but from the opinions whether of `the many’ or of `the wise,’ and particularly
from those of the Platonic school.
But it does not follow that the Ethics
is a prolonged argumentium ad hominem
from opinions that he does not himself accept; he would certainly not have
thought that worth his while. For
the most part he accepts the opinions of the Academy as his own, and when he
does not he has no hesitation is saying so.[15]
IV. An Introduction
to Aristotle’s Ethical Theory:
Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics (like all the writings we have of his) is actually based
on notes from a course of lectures given by Aristotle, which incorporate his
mature thoughts on ethical theory.
According to Martin Ostwald, the work gets its name from “...Aristotle’s son
Nicomachus [who] is said to have edited the work after his father’s death....”[16]
Aristotle’s ethics is an
aretaic one—the central question of
such theories is: “What sort of person
should I become?”—rather than “What
should I do?” Here we have what
may be called an ethics of
being rather than an ethics of
doing.
Aristotle maintains that:
413[17]
...the present inquiry does not aim at theoretical knowledge like the others
(for we are inquiring not in order to
know what excellence is, but in order to
become good, since otherwise our
inquiry would have been of no use), we must examine the nature of actions,
namely how we ought to do them; for these determine also the nature of the
states that are produced....
For Aristotle, virtues are characteristics which enable
human beings to live well in communities.
He conceives of humans as naturally social animals, and the good life as
a social one:
he believes people are not
self-sufficient materially speaking,
he believes the reproductive
instinct shows a need for others,
he believes self-preservation is
secured better in a community, and
[most importantly] he believes
that the good life is possible only
socially.
As he sees it, we are led to form social units naturally.
As W.D Ross notes, Aristotle maintains
…that the state does not exist
merely by convention but is rooted in human nature; that the natural is to be
found, in its truest sense, not in the origins of human life but in the goal
towards which it moves; that civilized life is not a declension from the life of
a hypothetical noble savage; that the state is not an artificial restriction of
liberty but a means of gaining it.
He is here implicitly attacking two views which had found favour in Greece:— (1)
the view of some of the sophists…that law and the state are mere products of
convention, interferences with the liberty of the individual which are either
forced on him by his masters or adopted by him merely as a safeguard against
injury; and (2) the view of the Cynics that the wise man is sufficient to
himself and should be a citizen of no country but only of the world—a view which
was encouraged by the disillusionment that fell upon Greece with the defeat of
Chaeronea.[18]
For Aristotle, then, to look at what we “naturally are,” we
must look not to how we begin, but to our “end.”
For him family, village and city state form a “progression” which does
not simply reflect some sort of “cultural” or “anthropological” progress, but,
rather, reflects a progression toward conditions which allow for the development
of persons in accord with their end.
Family
® |
Village
® |
|
meets everyday wants |
serves more than every
day wants |
comes into being to
provide the
good life.
|
In effect, Aristotle holds that our “highest good” is
achieved only within the social context of the [city] state.
This conception of the importance
of the community is especially poignant
since Aristotle was a resident alien in Athens for a significant
portion of his adult life—his own life lacked something which he believed to be
essential for proper human
functioning (he was not a citizen).[19]
To elaborate here and “ground” his view a bit more carefully, we should
note that Aristotle believes we find out what a good thing is by asking what the
function or purpose of that sort of
thing is. Thus, “What is a good
knife” requires determining what the purpose of knives is, and then determining
what would make for an excellent (or
virtuous) one. Thus he begins his
ethical theorizing by asking “What is the final cause (end) for persons?”
Clearly, then, his ethics is
teleological.
Note the implicit presumptions that
(1) there is a function here, and (2)
that there is a unique function here!
In the case of human beings, this may appear especially doubtful.
For Aristotle, of course, the “question” of functionality is an
objective one!
To find out what
our function is, we have to have a better idea of what kind of “thing” we
are, and here we must look to Aristotle’s “psychology” and to his discussion of
our “souls” (or “psyches”).[20]
As W.D. Ross notes,
the first step is to determine to
which of the main divisions of being—the categories—soul belongs, and again
whether it is a potentiality or an actuality.
But at this point a difficulty arises.
Suppose that there are different parts of soul, and various species or
perhaps even genera arising from the presence of these parts in various
combinations; it may then be that there is no one definition of soul.
It may be that the primary facts are the different kinds of soul, and
that there is no one thing answering to the name `soul’ in general or only a
slight nucleus of common nature in the various souls.
Aristotle’s answer is in effect that the kinds of soul are neither so
much alike that any single definition of soul will give a sufficient idea of its
varieties, ranging from its humble manifestations in plants and zoophytes to the
heights it reaches in man or in God, nor yet so different that we cannot
recognize a common nature in all its varieties.[21]
For Aristotle our souls have a
nutritive part (one which is in all
living things), a sensitive part
(one which is in all animals), and a
rational part (one which is in human beings only).
The rational part of the soul includes both
theoretical reason and
practical reason.
It is practical reason we are primarily concerned with here, of course.
In practical reasoning we can settle for much less than we can in
theoretical reasoning—instead of absolute knowledge of the universals, here we
need the ability to apprehend particular facts.
Indeed, Aristotle holds that while the happiest person would have both
theoretical and practical knowledge, a person might settle for less and still be
quite happy!
According to Aristotle: most people aim at
pleasure, some people aim at
honor, but
virtue is what people
should aim for.
In his “Introduction” to his selection from Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics in his
Social and Political Philosophy:
Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives, James
Sterba maintains that:
...Aristotle tries to provide
ethics with a firm foundation. He
begins by noting that all human activity aims at some good.
He then argues that for humans happiness is the ultimate good.
Happiness, he claims, is wrongly thought to consist simply in pleasure,
wealth, and honor. Rightly
understood, Aristotle argues, happiness is the activity of the soul exhibiting
the best and most complete excellence or virtue.[22]
As W.D. Ross notes, we need to be careful with Aristotle’s
terminology here:
the conventional translation
‘happiness’ is unsuitable in the Ethics;
for whereas ‘happiness’ means a state of feeling, differing from ‘pleasure’;
only by its suggestion of permanence, depth, and serenity, Aristotle insists
that eudemonia is a kind of
activity; that it is not any kind of
pleasure, though pleasure naturally accompanies it.
The more non-committal translation ‘well-being’ is therefore better.
If the question be asked whether Aristotle was a hedonist, it is better
to go by his repeated and deliberate statement that the end of life is activity
rather than by his use, for want of a better word, of one which suggests not
action but feeling.[23]
In her The Therapy
of Desire, Martha Nussbaum maintains that:
eudaimonia is often rendered
“happiness”: but this is ·misleading, since it misses the emphasis on
activity, and on completeness of
life, that is (as Aristotle cogently argues) present in the ordinary use of the
Greek term, and wrongly suggests that what is at issue must be a state or
feeling of satisfaction.[24]
In her In her
Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions, Martha Nussbaum
maintains that:
…I want to refer directly to the
Greek concept of eudaimonia, which is
compatible with as many distinct conceptions of what that good is as one cares
to propose….[25]
In addition, John Sellars notes that we must, here, talk
about “…a substantive well-being in one’s life, rather than a merely subjective
feeling of contentment….sometimes translated as “well-being” or “flourishing”….”[26]
Talking about Aristotle and moral virtue means talking about his
doctrine of the [golden] mean—what
is good is not the same for every individual (a metaphor about athletics and
trainers is useful here). Aristotle
believes that we must actually look to the world to see what morality requires:
416 in everything that is
continuous and divisible it is possible to take a more, less, or an equal
amount, and that either in terms of the thing itself or relatively to us; and
the equal is an intermediate between excess and defect.
By the intermediate in the object I mean that which is equidistant from
each of the extremes, which is one and the same for all men; by the intermediate
relatively to us that which is neither too much nor too little—and this is not
one, nor the same for all. For
instance, if ten is many and two is few, six is the intermediate taken in terms
of the object; for it exceeds and is exceeded by an equal amount; this is
intermediate according to arithmetical proportion.
But the intermediate relatively to us is not to be taken so; if ten
pounds are too much for a particular person to eat and two too little, it does
not follow that the trainer will order six pounds; for this also is perhaps too
much for the person who is to take it, or too little—too little for Milo, too
much for the beginner in athletic contests.
The same is true of running and wrestling.
Thus a master of any art avoids excess and defect, but seeks the
intermediate and chooses this—the intermediate not in the object but relatively
to us.
416-417 Excellence
[virtue], then, is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean,
i.e. the mean relative to us, this [1107a] being determined by a rational
principle, and by that principle by which the man of practical wisdom would
determine it. Now it is a mean
between two vices, that which depends on excess and that which depends on
defect; and again it is a mean because the vices respectively fall short of or
exceed what is right in both passions and action, while virtue both finds and
chooses that which is intermediate.
Hence in respect of its substance and the definition that states its essence
virtue is a mean, with regard to what is best and right an extreme.
-417
Exception: “but not every action nor
every passion admits of a mean; for some have names that already imply badness,
e.g. spite, shamelessness, envy, and in the case of actions adultery, theft,
murder; for all of these and suchlike things imply by their names that they are
themselves bad, and not the excesses or deficiencies of them.
It is not possible, then, ever to be right with regard to them; one must
always be wrong.”
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics
consists of an extended discussion of various “excess, virtue, deficiency”
“triads:”
foolhardiness, courage, and
cowardliness;
self-indulgence, self-control, a
rare condition for man;
self-indulgence, temperance, and
insensibility;
extravagance, generosity, and
stinginess;
vulgarity, magnificence, and
niggardliness;
pride [pettiness], humility [high
mindedness], vanity;
ambition, a nameless mean, and
lack of ambition;
short temper, gentleness, and
apathy;
obsequiousness, friendliness, and
grouchiness;
boastfulness, truthfulness, and
self-deception;
buffoonery, ready-wit
[wittiness], and boorishness; and
bashfulness, shame, and
shamelessness.
For Aristotle, the moral virtues are different from the intellectual
ones. They can not be taught
directly, but must be lived in order
to be learned. For Aristotle,
however, these “moral” virtues are not enough.
Here, unfortunately, we encounter a major “vice” in the selection in our
text—the editor does not include Aristotle’s discussion of the intellectual
virtues, and, I contend, this is central
to understanding his overall theory:
1177a if happiness is
activity in accordance with virtue, it is reasonable that it should be in
accordance with the highest virtue; and this will be that of the best thing in
us. Whether it be reason or
something else that is this element which is thought to be our natural ruler and
guide and to take thought of things noble and divine, whether it be itself also
divine or only the most divine element in us, the activity of this in accordance
with its proper virtue will be perfect happiness.
That this activity is contemplative we have already said.
Now this would seem to be in agreement both with what we said before and
with the truth. For, firstly, this
activity is the best (since not only is reason the best thing in us, but the
objects of reason are the best of knowable objects); and secondly, it is the
most continuous, since we can contemplate truth more continuously than we can
do anything.
And we think happiness has pleasure mingled with it, but the activity of
philosophic wisdom is admittedly the pleasantest of virtuous activities; at all
events the pursuit of it is thought to offer pleasures marvelous for their
purity and their enduringness, and it is to be expected that those who know will
pass their time more pleasantly than those who inquire.[27]
-As David Ross says,
“Aristotle...[here] passes from moral to intellectual virtue.
Two reasons make it necessary to study the latter.
(1) The virtuous man has been defined as acting in accordance with the
`right’ rule. The forming of this
rule is an intellectual operation and we must consider its nature.
(2) Well-being has been defined as `activity of the soul in accordance
with virtue, or if there be more than one virtue, in accordance with the best
and most perfect. If we are to know
what happiness is, we must consider the nature of the intellectual as well as
the moral virtues.”[28]
-Ultimately, then, for Aristotle
contemplation is the essential
component of the good life. Thus,
Ross says: “...both theoretical and practical wisdom are good in themselves
apart from any good they produce, since they are virtues of distinct parts of
the soul; we have been told definitely that theoretical wisdom, and less
definitely that practical wisdom, is not, or not only a
means to well-being, but in its
exercise constitutes well-being.
But we have also learnt that theoretical wisdom is superior to practical
and that at any rate part of the latter is that it helps to produce the former.
It is clear that contemplation is for Aristotle the main ingredient in
well-being; whether moral action is another ingredient in it or only a means to
its production is not so evident.
The doubt is not entirely removed by Book X.
Well-being, we are told, must be activity in accordance with the virtue
of the best part of us, which is reason.
The activity of which we are capable, since it is the exercise of the
best in us on the best of all objects, those which are eternal and unchanging;
is what we can do most continuously; it brings pleasure of wonderful purity and
stability; it is least dependent on other men, while moral virtue requires
others as the objects of its activity; it alone seems to be loved for itself,
while practical activities—notably the greatest of them, the deeds of the
statesman and the soldier—aim at goods beyond themselves;
it is the life we must ascribe to the
gods, since the ascription of moral life to them would be absurd.
But the life of contemplation is too high for us; we cannot live it
qua men, beings compounded of body,
irrational soul, and reason, but only in virtue of the divine element in us.
We must, as far as may be, `lay hold of eternal life’ by living the life
of that which, however small a part of us it be, is the best thing in us, and
the most truly ourselves.”[29]
V. Criticisms of
Aristotle’s virtue-ethics:
In his Inventing
Right and Wrong, J.L. Mackie contends that:
as guidance about what is the
good life, what precisely one ought to do, or even by what standard one should
try to decide what one ought to do, this is too circular to be very helpful.
And though Aristotle’s account is filled out with detailed descriptions
of many of the virtues, moral as well as intellectual, the air of indeterminacy
persists. We learn the names of the
pairs of contrary vices that contrast with each of the virtues, but very little
about where or how to draw the dividing lines, where or how to fix the mean.
As Sidgwick says, he “only indicates the whereabouts of virtue.”[30]
In his Varieties of Moral
Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism, Owen Flanagan maintains that:
there are two main models
of moral excellence in philosophy.
One is the model of the principled reasoner who applies some supreme
general-purpose algorithm to all moral problems.
The other is the model of the morally excellent person as the fully
virtuous person. The first model
fails to capture the actual psychology of many persons we think of as excellent.
The second picture is, on the interpretation according to which the
virtuous person possesses the full complement of the virtues, either an idea we
do not understand or one that is incoherent.
The weaker and more credible model that distinguishes among the mandatory
and nonmandatory virtues still has three problems.
First, we cannot agree about what to include on which list.
Second, even when there is something approaching agreement, exceptions
are normally granted; otherwise saints and exemplars would be few and far
between. Finally, we do not know
from a psychological point of view, what a virtue is; how the virtues are
individuated; how they interact; how situation sensitive they are; how they are
subserved by and interact with cognition, the emotions, and temperament; and how
they connect to action.[31]
Flanagan goes on to offer a theory which is to overcome
these problems.
In his “The Moral First Aid Manual,” Daniel Dennett maintains that much
ethical theory is far to “theoretical.” Dennett contends that while there are
serious problems with the first sort of theory, the “retreat to an “ethics of
virtue” is not an answer:
it is all very well to say, more
or less with Aristotle, that if we concentrate our theoretical attentions on
Virtue, the process of decision-making will take care of itself (since the
Virtuous Person will know how to make morally wise decisions without any need to
consult a Manual). This just passes
the buck; how, exactly, is the paragon of Virtue supposed to do this?
This “design” question remains archingly open—it is both theoretically
and practically interesting since few of us take ourselves to be beyond
improvement in this regard—even if we agree (as we should not, in fact) that the
ideally virtuous agent needs no help from our designers.[32]
(end)
[1] As David
Ross notes, “we need not suppose that it was any
attraction to the life of philosophy that drew
him to the Academy; he was simply getting the
best education that
[2] Martin
Ostwald, “Introduction,” in his edited
translation of
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics
(Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1962), pp.
xi-xxiv, p. xii.
[3] David
Ross notes that “...Aristotle rented some
buildings—as an alien he could not buy them—and
founded his school.
Here, every morning, he walked up and
down with his pupils [hence the name
Peripatetics] in the
loggie
[open covered galleries] or among the trees, and
discussed the more abstruse questions of
philosophy; and in the afternoon or evening
expounded less difficult matters to a larger
audience....The more abstract subjects—logic,
physics, and metaphysics—required a more
intensive study, while subjects such as
rhetoric, sophistic, or politics answered a
wider demand and could be expounded in a more
popular way” (David Ross,
Aristotle, op. cit., p. 5).
[4] Richard
McKeon, “Introduction,” in
The Basic
Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon
(N.Y.: Random House, 1941), pp. xi-xxxiv, pp.
xiv-xv.
[5] Christine
Korsgaard, “Excellence and Obligation: A
Very
Concise History of Western Metaphysics 387 BC to
1887 AD,” in
The
Sources of Normativity, ed. Onora O’Neill
(Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1996), pp. 1-5, pp.
2-3.
Emphasis added to passage at three
points.
[6]
Ibid.,
pp. 4-5.
[7] A.R.
Caponigri,
A History
of Western Philosophy: Philosophy From The
Renaissance to the Romantic Age (Notre Dame:
Univ. of Notre Dame, 1963), p. 152.
[8] Michael
Matthews,
The Scientific Background to Modern Philosophy
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989), p. 6—the emphasis
is mine.
[9]
Teleological explanations occur when past and
present events are explained in terms of
future
events (they are “goal-oriented” explanations).
They are often contrasted with mechanical
explanations which hold that present and future
events are to be explained in terms of
past
mechanical events and their consequences. The
contrast is well-stated by Wilber Long in his
entry under “teleology” in
Dictionary of Philosophy, ed. Dagobert Runes
(N.Y.: Philosophical Library, 1960), p. 315.
[10] Martin
Ostwald, “Introduction,”
op. cit.,
p. xvii.
[11] W.T.
Jones, A
History of Western Philosophy: The Classical
Mind (second edition) (N.Y.: Harcourt,
1970), pp. 234-235.
[12]
Aristotle,
Historia
Animalium (The
History of Animals), 561a, ff, trans. J.A.
Smith, in
The Works of Aristotle, eds. J.A. Smith and
W.D. Ross (Clarendon: Oxford, 1910-1952), v. 2
(1930).
[13] W.D.
Ross,
Aristotle, op. cit., p. 115.
[14] W.D.
Ross, “Introduction,”
op. cit.,
p. xxiii.
Ross notes that “the subtle changes which
gradually made natural functions into grades of
perfection of being, scientific classifications
into metaphysical forms, and finally made
observation seem otiose in science, and
dialectic seem over-subtle play with fictions in
metaphysics, were initiated in the Greek
commentators on his works.
They were later developed and elaborated
by medieval philosophers, and the consequences
of those changes have more frequently than what
Aristotle himself said, furnished objects for
the rhetorical refutations constructed to lay
the ghost of Aristotelian science during the
Renaissance and often repeated in subsequent
centuries.
Whatever the virtues or defects of
Aristotle’s physical treatises, they depend on
the separation of metaphysics from physics, not
on the merging of the two sciences, and although
the conception of a continuous scale of nature
from inorganic substances to biological and
psychological phenomena is of basic importance
in all his science, explanation does not consist
in running uniformly up the hierarchy of beings
to God or in reducing, for all problems,
functions to organs and organs to their material
elements” (ibid.,
p. xxii).
[15] W.D.
Ross,
Aristotle, op. cit., pp. 189-190.
[16] Martin
Ostwald, “Introduction,”
op. cit,
p. xii.
David Ross notes that when he left
[17] The page
references here are to the selection from
Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics, translated by W.D. Ross
[1908],
Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics, ii.2.1103b, trans. W.D.
Ross [1930], revised by J.L. Acknill and J.O.
Urmson, in
Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings
(sixth edition), eds. Louis Pojman and James
Fieser (Boston: Wadsworth, 2011), p. 413.
As Richard McKeon notes (in his
“Introduction,” in his
The Basic
Works of Aristotle, op. cit., pp. xi-xxxiv,
p. viii), “the pagination of the Bekker edition
of the Greek text of Aristotle [1831-1870],
which is published in…the five volumes of the
Berlin edition, has become the customary means
to locate a passage in Aristotle....”
Thus the above reference is to Chapter 2
of Book II of the
Nicomachean Ethics, the second column (b) of
page 1103.
The editors of our text do not use the
standard references.
[18] W.D.
Ross,
Aristotle, op. cit., p. 239.
The reference to Phillip II’s defeat of
[19]
Cf.,
Martha Nussbaum, “Aristotelian Social
Democracy,” in
Liberalism and the Good, eds. G. Mara and H.
Richardson (London: Routledge, 1990), pp.
201-252, p. 233.
[20] To
understand what he has to say about virtue, we
must first make certain we do not misunderstand
his use of ‘soul’—we see this word through a two
thousand year filter of the
Judeo-Christian-Islamic tradition.
He does not use it in this fashion (or,
better perhaps, this two thousand year use is an
adaptation of his [and Plato’s] use of the
term).
[21] W.D.
Ross,
Aristotle, op. cit.,
p. 129.
[22] James
Sterba, “Introduction” to his selection from
Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics in
Sterba’s
Social and Political Philosophy: Classical
Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural
Perspectives (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1995), pp.
39-41, pp. 39-40.
[23] W.D.
Ross,
Aristotle, op. cit., p. 190.
Emphasis added to passage.
[24] Martha
Nussbaum
The Therapy of Desire (Princeton: Princeton
U.P., 1994), p. 15.
[25] Martha
Nussbaum,
Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of
Emotions (
[26] John
Sellars,
Stoicism (Chesham: Acumen, 2006), p. 123.
[27]
Aristotle’s
Ethica
Nicomachea, trans. W.D. Ross, in
The Basic
Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon,
op. cit.,
x.7.1177a, p.1104.
[28] David
Ross,
Aristotle, op. cit., p. 215.
[29]
Ibid.,
pp. 232-233.
[30] J.L.
Mackie,
Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (N.Y.:
Penguin, 1977), p. 186.
Cited by Pojman in his “Virtue-Based
Ethical Systems,”
op. cit., p. 374.
[31] Owen
Flanagan,
Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and
Psychological Realism (Cambridge: Harvard
U.P., 1991), pp. 11-12.
.
[32] Daniel
Dennett, “The Moral First Aid Manual,” in
The
Tanner Lectures on Human Values v. 8, ed.
Sterling M. McMurrin (Salt Lake City: Univ. of
Utah, 1988), pp. 121-147, p. 131, footnote.
Last revised on: 11/07/2013.