Hauptli’s Lecture
Supplement on Berkeley’s Principles
[1710, second edition: 1734][1]
Copyright © 2015 Bruce W. Hauptli
The full title is A
Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge.
It is usually referred to as the
Principles—thus easily distinguishing it from Locke’s
Essay [1690] and David Hume’s
Treatise [1739-1740].[2]
We will be reading the Introduction and the first thirty-three sections
of Part I (as well as sections 139-149 of Part I).
Berkeley characterized Part I as that “wherein the chief Causes of Error
and Difficulty in the Sciences, and
the Grounds of Skepticism,
Atheism and
Irreligion, are inquir’d into.”
There was a Part II which Berkeley told the American Philosopher Samuel
Johnson he lost on a trip to Italy[3]—it
dealt with ethics, freedom of the will, and the nature of the deity he believes
to be so important. He intended
still more parts, but the work was not well-received, and he dropped the longer
project.
The reading assignment from Berkeley’s
Principles will be:
Introduction (all)
Part I sections 1-33, 89, and
139-149.
The version we have has an excellent introduction by Kenneth Winkler,[4]
and an excellent Glossary (beginning
on p. 89) which is of great help given some of the now archaic words (and some
of the now archaic senses of words he uses).
In addition, the text includes an
Analytical Table of Contents (which I have revised in places for my lectures
on the Principles):
Introduction
(1-25):
1-5 Philosophers are disturbed by doubts caused by false
principles.
6-12 One such principle is the doctrine of
abstract ideas—they are impossible,
and are not necessary for communication.
13-17 They are contradictory, and are not required for
communication or for the enlargement of knowledge.
18-20 The source of the doctrine of abstract ideas is a
mistaken view of language.
21-25 Advantages of considering ideas instead of words.
Part I.
1-2 Ideas and spirits compared.
Ideas cannot exist outside the mind.
3 First argument, from the meaning of the word
exist.
4 Second argument: sensible things are those things we
perceive, but we perceive only our own ideas.
5-6 The belief in unperceived objects depends on
abstraction.
7 Spirit is the only substance.
8 An objection: ideas represent external objects.
But an idea can represent nothing but another idea.
9-15 The distinction between primary and secondary
qualities:
i) 9 The distinction
explained. It has already been
shown that no quality can exist outside the mind
ii) 10 Primary qualities cannot
be conceived apart from secondary qualities, and cannot exist apart from them.
iii) 11 Great and small, swift
and slow.
iv) 12 Number.
v) 13 Unity
vi) 14 Arguments from perceptual
relativity work as well for extension and figure as they do for color and taste.
vii) 15 That is, they do not work
at all. And my earlier arguments
apply to the distinction between primary and secondary qualities as a special
case.
16-17 Third argument: the notion of
matter is either empty or
incomprehensible.
18-20 Fourth Argument: If matter existed, we could neither
know it nor have reason to believe it.
21-24: Fifth argument: The notion of physical substance is
contradictory [a direct attack upon the belief in such objects—we cannot even
conceive of an object existing “outside the mind]:”
23-33 How are ideas caused?
i) 25 They cannot be caused by
extension, figure, and motion.
These qualities are ideas, and all ideas are inactive.
ii) 26 Ideas must therefore be
caused by a substance or spirit.
iii) 27 We can have no idea of
spirit.
iv) 28 We are the cause of some
of our ideas.
v) 29-32 But God is the cause of
the ideas of sense. He produces
them according to set rules or laws of nature, enabling us to regulate our
actions for the benefit of life.
Supplement to Section 30:
Sections 145-149.
vi) 33 Ideas of sense are
real things. They are more regular,
vivid, and constant than ideas of imagination.
The Text:
I. Introduction (1-25):
1-5: Philosophers are
disturbed by doubts caused by false principles:
1. When we leave common sense
behind for abstruse reason, skepticism results.
3. Our errors are due to our
misuse of our faculties rather than to the fact that our faculties are
inadequate.
6-12: One such abuse of our faculties is the doctrine of
abstract ideas—they are impossible,
and are not necessary for communication:
In his “Notes:
The Principles,” Jonathan Dancy
maintains that in sections 7-9 “...Berkeley lays out the account of abstraction
that he wants to reject. First, we are
supposed to be able to consider separately each of the properties of an object:
its extension apart from its colour or its motion, for instance ([section] 7).
Then we can consider the extensions of different objects, and make a
‘most abstract idea of extension’ as that which is common to all particular
extensions ([section] 8). Finally,
we can consider abstract ideas of ‘compounded beings’, i.e. of
man and of
horse, by considering together the
qualities common to all men, and leaving out any respects in which one man
differs from another ([section] 9).
In [section] 10 Berkeley gives his reasons for rejecting these claims about
abstraction. We can do none of
these things, because we cannot separate in the mind (i.e. abstract from each
other) qualities that cannot exist separately.
In [section] 11 Berkeley considers the main reason offered by Locke for
supposing us able to abstract in these ways, which is that we cannot otherwise
explain the existence of general words or concepts.
In [section] 12 Berkeley offers an alternative explanation of general
words, one which involves no appeal to or use of abstraction.[5]
-10:
Abstract ideas are impossible because
what they represent is impossible.
All our ideas are particular:
“but then whatever hand or eye I imagine, it must have some particular shape and
color. Likewise the idea of man
that I frame to myself, must be either of a white, or a black, or a tawny, a
straight, or a crooked, a tall, or a low, or a middle-sized man.
I cannot by any effort of thought conceive the abstract idea above
described. And it is equally
impossible for me to form the abstract idea of motion distinct from the body
moving....I own myself able to abstract in one sense, as when I consider some
particular parts or qualities separated from others, with which though they are
united in some object, yet, it is possible they may really exist without them.
But I deny that I can abstract one from another, or conceive separately,
those qualities which it is impossible should exist so separated....”
-11. Berkeley discusses Locke’s
view on general terms and language and maintains that “...a
word becomes general by being made the sign, not of an abstract idea but, of
several particular ideas, any one of which it indifferently suggests to the
mind.”
-12. That is, he maintains that
there are general ideas, but denies
that there are abstract ones: “...an
idea, which considered in itself is particular, becomes general, by being made
to represent or stand for all other particular ideas of the same sort.”
Berkeley offers the example of a geometrician who is demonstrating the
technique for dividing a line into two equal parts.
The line used in such a demonstration is
used as a sign for all lines.
It is, nonetheless, a particular line.
According to him, the geometrician “...draws, for instance, a black line
of an inch in length, this which in itself is a particular line is nevertheless
with regard to its signification general, since as it is there used, it
represents all particular lines whatsoever; so that what is demonstrated of it,
is demonstrated of all lines, or, in other words, of a line in general....[it]
owes its generality, not to its being the sign of a abstract or general line,
but of all particular...lines that may possibly exist....”
--Locke holds that there
are particular,
general, and
abstract ideas.
Berkeley, really, holds that there are only the former.
General and abstract terms are differing
uses of our particular ideas, but, he
contends, they are not, really, ideas themselves.
--Hume calls Berkeley’s account
of general terms here “...one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that
has been made of late years in the republic of letters.”[6]
As Jonathan Dancy notes, however, “we should note that this remark does
not endorse Berkeley’s attack on our supposed powers of abstraction.
Hume is agreeing with Berkeley that general terms do not need to be
abstract. Berkeley could be right
about that, and wrong about the impossibility of abstraction.”[7]
13-17: Abstract ideas are contradictory, and are not
required for communication or for the enlargement of knowledge:
13. He discusses the
general (or abstract) idea of a triangle, and points out that the “abstract
idea” here involves contradictions.
Berkeley appeals to our experience to show that no one has such an
abstract idea: “if any man has the faculty of framing in his mind such an idea
of a triangle as is here described, it is in vain to pretend to dispute him out
of it, nor would I go about it. All
I desire is, that the reader would fully and certainly inform himself whether he
has such an idea or no. And this,
methinks, can be no hard task for anyone to perform.
What [could be] more easy than for anyone to look a little into his own thoughts,
and there try whether he has, or can attain to have, an idea that shall
correspond with the description that is here given of the general idea of a
triangle, which is neither oblique, nor
rectangle, equilateral, equicural, nor scalenon, but all and none of these at
once?”
15. Berkeley maintains
that “abstract ideas” are no more necessary for the “enlargement of knowledge”
than they are necessary for communication.
-16. Berkeley responds
to the contention that abstract ideas are necessary if there is to be universal
knowledge (knowledge of universal truths) by contending that it arises as we pay
attention to certain features of particular things.
18-20: The source of the doctrine of abstract ideas is a
mistaken view of language:
18. He contends that mistaken
views about language (especially views about naming) lead many to the doctrine
of abstract ideas.
20. Berkeley points out that
language is not used exclusively for the communication of ideas of ideas by
words: “there are other ends, as the raising of some passion, the exciting to,
or deterring from an action, the putting the mind in some particular
disposition; to which the former is in many cases subservient, and sometimes
entirely omitted, as I think does not infrequently happen in the familiar use of
language.”
-Of course, claiming that there
are other uses of language than the
one Locke asserted to be primary (the
communication of ideas), does not establish either that this is not a use, or
that it is not the primary use.
Berkeley’s remarks here, however, are taken by many to be a precursor of
twentieth century views of language—both J.L. Austin and Ludwig Wittgenstein
contend that it is the practical use of language which is primary.[8]
21-25: Advantages of considering ideas instead of words:
22. He would avoid “verbal
controversies” and restrict himself to ideas.
He holds that abstract ideas are impossible, not useful, and arise from
mistaken views about language.
25. Berkeley asks us not to be
misled by language but, instead, encourages us to pay attention to our
experience (ideas).
II. Criticism of Berkeley’s Rejection of
Abstract Ideas:
While there is much virtue in Berkeley’s critique (and, as
noted above, while Hume richly praises it and partially agrees with it), the
overall nominalism which is supposed to be supported by the critique (that is
the claim that there are only particular ideas) may not be warranted.[9]
In his “After Empiricism,” Hilary Putnam maintains that:
according to Berkeley and
Hume, I do not have such a thing as an “abstract idea” or a “general idea” of
green. When a particular token—be
it a green color-patch or a token of the word “green”—occurs in my mind, and is
used as a symbol for the whole class of green sense-data, all that happens is
that the token is associated with a certain class of other tokens to which it is
similar or which are similar to one another.
Ayer and Russell depart from Berkeley and Hume on this point—and with
good reason. For they see that
if I can think of a
particular relation of “similarity,”
then I am able to recognize at least one universal.
Thus universals cannot really be avoided in the way Berkeley and Hume
wanted to do.[10]
Thus Putnam, and others, contend that some universal(s) are
required—at least that of “similarity.”
Some contemporary theorists endeavor to “get by” with the fewest number
of such universals as they try and account for the richness of human language
and conceptualization.[11]
III. Part I. Wherein the
chief causes of error and difficulty in the sciences, with the grounds of
skepticism, atheism, and irreligion, are inquired into:
1-2: Ideas and spirits compared.
Ideas cannot exist outside the mind:
1. The objects of human knowledge
are ideas. Where ideas originate:
senses, passions, memory and imagination [reflection].
2. Minds/Spirit: where
ideas exist: “...the existence of an idea consists in its being perceived.”
-Cf.,
sections 27, 89, 145, and 139-140.
3: First argument against the “notion” of physical
substance—from the meaning of the word ‘exist’:
Esse est percipi “...attend to what is meant by the term ‘exist’ when
applied to sensible things.” Here
he begins his phenomenalistic analysis
of “material thing.”
This section raises an
interpretive question or problem, however.
It suggests that Berkeley is a
phenomenalist rather than an
idealist (this suggestion is seconded
by what he says in section 58, which I recommend that you read in this regard).
In his “Editor’s Introduction” [to another edition of Berkeley's
Principles], Jonathan Dancy maintains
that: “this looser view would have it that for a physical thing to exist is for
it to be able to be present to some
mind, not for it actually to be doing so.
Both conceptions of physical existence require a relation to a mind; so
both involve a rejection of realism, which conceives the existence of a physical
thing in terms of its taking its place in the mind-independent spatio-temporal
matrix which constitutes the natural world.
The looser view is called
phenomenalism, the tighter one idealism.”[12]
I will follow the main tradition of Berkeley interpretation, and read him
as an idealist.
4: Second argument: sensible things are those things we
perceive, but we perceive only our own ideas: “it is indeed an opinion
strangely prevailing amongst men, that houses, mountains, rivers, and in a word
all sensible objects have an existence natural or real, distinct from their
being perceived by the understanding.
But with how great an assurance and acquiescence soever this principle
may be entertained in the world, yet whoever shall find in his heart to call it
in question may, if I mistake not, perceive it involve a manifest contradiction.
For what are the forementioned objects but the things we perceive by
sense, and what do we perceive besides
our own ideas or sensations; and is it not plainly repugnant that any one of
these, or any combination of them, should exist unperceived?”
Here we get
Berkeley’s elaboration of his “phenomenalistic
analysis of “things.”
In his “Idealism: A Victorian
Horror Story (Part One),” David Stove maintains that: “philosophical idealism
demands...the identity of reality
with thought or with something thought-like.
It is not enough for idealism that a billiard ball, and everything else,
‘be thought’, in a predicative sense:
I mean that the billiard ball, while being (for example) round and hard and
shiny, be thought as well—supposing we could understand even that.
Still less is it enough for idealism that a billiard ball, and everything
else, ‘be thought’ in a relational
sense: I mean, that it be thought of,
by someone or something. What
idealism requires is that billiard balls, and everything else,
be thoughts (or experiences, or
ideas, etc.), in the sense of ‘be identical with.’
Idealism is an identity-claim, or it is nothing: nothing but some variety
or other of dualism.”[13]
Stove offers an extended critique of this identity claim.
5-6: The belief in unperceived objects depends on
abstraction:
5. “...can there be a nicer
strain of abstraction[14]
than to distinguish the existence of sensible objects from their being
perceived, so as to conceive them existing unperceived?”
-“But my conceiving power does
not extend beyond the possibility of real existence or perception.
Hence, as it is impossible for me to see or feel anything without an
actual sensation of that thing, so it is impossible for me to conceive in my
thoughts any sensible thing or object distinct from the sensation or perception
of it.”
-According to W.T.
Jones, “Locke wrote as if he believed that what is before the mind when it
thinks “triangle” is a generalized image—a triangle that is neither scalene nor
equilateral. According to Berkeley,
no such general image exists. What
is before the mind is always some particular triangle, which stands for, or
represents, every other particular triangle.
Thus, when Berkeley denied that men have the “faculty of abstracting
their ideas,” he was actually making two distinct assertions, though he did not
distinguish them. He was asserting
both a psychological thesis—that
there are no generalized images, only specific ones—and an
epistemological [metaphysical?]
thesis—that there are no universals,
only particulars. As regards the
former, he and Locke differed. As
regards the latter...they were in agreement....
Since all ideas are concrete
particulars, and since there are no real universals, it follows that a general
name simply refers to (is the sign of) several particular ideas, all of which it
indifferently represents, and some one of which is always actually present to
the mind when it thinks about the meaning of this name.
But if what is before the mind is always a particular, how can we ever
know any general truths at all....Berkeley’s answer was that we can be sure that
what is true of one is true of the other because the particular properties that
differ in the two triangles...do not enter into the proof.”[15]
6. Ideas need to be in a mind.
“...all the choir of heaven and furniture of earth have not any
subsistence without the mind...their being is to be perceived or known.”
7: Spirit is the only substance.
Of course, if there are no bodies, then “spirits” are the only things
“left” to “have” the ideas.
8: An objection: ideas represent external objects:
“But, say you, though the ideas themselves do not exist without the mind, yet
there may be things like them,
whereof they are copies or resemblances which things exist without the mind in
an unthinking substance. I answer,
an idea can be like nothing but an idea....”
Some secondary sources refer to this as
Berkeley’s “likeness principle.”
Look at your thoughts and you will see
this. Suppose the idea is to be
like something (an original), if that thing is perceivable we can make sense of
this; if not, we can not make sense of it (to assert that a color is like
something that is invisible and intangible is to cease to talk sense).
In his “Notes:
The
Principles,” Jonathan Dancy maintains
that Berkeley’s principle “...is the main weapon in his attack on the view that
ideas can represent material things.
Those who maintained, with Locke, that the mind is primarily acquainted
with its own ideas had to say how it is was possible for it
also to be acquainted...with
things....The normal account was that the ideas
represented the material things to
the mind....But if one says this one has to give some story about what it is for
an idea to represent....The story that was normally given appealed to two
concepts: resemblance and
causation....Berkeley’s...principle,
if sound. undermines all this talk of ideas representing material objects by
resembling them.”[16]
Of course, since there is no adequate understanding of how things cause
ideas, the “normal story” is flawed on this aspect also!
-Here we need to consider whether
it is important to distinguish between “knowledge by acquaintance” and
“knowledge by description.” More
generally, in discussing “knowledge”, we should distinguish:
propositional knowledge from:
knowledge by acquaintance (e.g.,
knowing your uncle Fred, or French, your migraine headaches, your best friend,
etc.); know-how (sometimes called
“competence” or “procedural” knowledge—e.g.,
knowing-how to ride a bike); knowing what
(e.g., knowing what a
piano sounds like), knowing-why
(having an explanation as to why some thing, event, etc., came about—e.g.,
knowing why you must go to bed without supper), and knowledge by description
(wherein one places the described item in the space of reasons,
justifications, narrations, or depictions).
Propositional knowledge, the stable for many philosophers, is a
sub-class of the latter type—one where the emphasis is placed upon descriptions
which are to elucidate and lumen the essential nature of things.
In her “Relocating Aesthetics: Goodman’s Epistemic Turn,” Catherine Elgin
maintains that:
contemporary realists are prone
to think that literal language at its best partitions its domain into natural
kinds, or divides nature at the joints, or discloses the true and ultimate
structure of reality. Somehow, the
world is supposed to dictate its proper description.
[Nelson] Goodman denies this.
He believes that any order we find is an order we impose.
Systems of categories are contrived to impose order.
They divide a domain into individuals and group these individuals into
kinds. They thereby equip us to
describe, predict, explain, and complain about the entities thus recognized.
But the success of one category scheme does not preclude the success of
others. There is no unique way the
world is, hence no privileged way the world is to be described.
A single domain may be organized in multiple ways; and for different
purposes, different classifications may be best.[17]
I find a lot to agree to in this viewpoint, and I believe one shouldn’t
assume that knowledge is a “natural kind” but, rather, note that it may be a
“nominal” one. If this is the case,
of course, a “unitary analysis” may not be the right way to go.
Moreover, in his “The Pragmatic Dimension of Knowledge,” Fred Dretske
develops a contextualistic analysis of knowledge suggesting that we:
...think of knowledge as an
evidential state in which all relevant
alternatives (to what are known) are
eliminated. This makes
knowledge an absolute concept but the restriction
to relevant alternatives makes it,
like empty and
flat, applicable to this
epistemically bumpy world we live in.[18]
The social or pragmatic
dimension to knowledge, if it exists at all, had to do with what
counts as a relevant alternative, a
possibility that must be evidentially excluded, in order to have knowledge.
It does not change the fact that to know
one must be in a position to exclude all
such possibilities. It does not
alter the fact that one must have, in this sense, an optimal justification—one
that eliminates every relevant) possibility of being mistaken.[19]
9-15: The distinction between primary and secondary
qualities does not support the “notion” of a physical substance:
i) 9: The distinction explained:
it has already been shown that no quality can exist outside the mind.
What Locke means by matter
involves a contradiction: “...extension, figure, and motion are only ideas
existing in the mind, and that an idea can be like nothing but another idea, and
that consequently neither they nor their archetypes can exist in an unperceiving
substance. Hence it is plain, that
the very notion of what is called matter
or corporeal substance involves a
contradiction in it.”
ii) 10: Primary qualities
cannot be conceived apart from secondary qualities, and cannot exist apart from
them: “but I desire anyone to reflect and try whether he can, by any abstraction
of thought, conceive the extension and motion of a body without all other
sensible qualities. For my own
part, I see evidently that it is not in my power to frame an idea of a body
extended and moving, but I must withal give it some color or other sensible
quality which is acknowledged to exist only in the mind.
In short, extension, figure, and motion abstracted from all other
qualities are inconceivable.”
-In his “Notes:
The
Principles,” Jonathan Dancy notes
that “commentators have often supposed that Berkeley’s position here depends on
taking ideas to be mental images, pictures in the mind, so that all conception
is imagination. It would be
comparatively easy to show that one cannot
form a mental image of an object
existing without colour; colour seems essential to an image, even if it be only
black and white. It is much harder
to show that one cannot conceive of
something extended but uncoloured, if conceiving is different from imagining.”[20]
iii) 11: Great and
small, swift and slow exist in the mind: “...thus we see how much the tenet of
extended movable substances depends on the strange doctrine of
abstract ideas.”
iv) 12: Number is relative and
depends on the mind (one yard, three feet, 36 inches).
v) 13: Similarly for “unity.”
vi) 14: Arguments from perceptual
relativity work as well for extension and figure as they do for color and taste.
Berkeley provides additional examples of the mind dependence of ideas.
vii) 15: He contends that
his earlier arguments apply to the distinction between primary and secondary
qualities as a special case: “but the arguments foregoing plainly show it to be
impossible that any color or extension at all, or other sensible quality
whatsoever, should exist in an unthinking subject without the mind, or in truth,
that there should be any such thing as an outward object.”
16-17: Third argument: the notion of matter is either
empty or incomprehensible:
16. The notion of
“matter’s supporting extension,” etc., are without meaning.
Those who propose such notions have nothing positive in mind.
17. They mean by this simply
“...the idea of substance being in general, together with the relative notion of
its supporting accidents.” But this
is the most abstract of ideas, and the most incomprehensible.
18-20: Fourth Argument [Epistemic]: If matter existed,
we could neither know it nor have reason to believe it:
Up to this point, Berkeley as argued “linguistically”
against materialism: he has claimed that the meaning of ‘exists’, the
phenomenalistic analysis of ‘things’, and the meaning of ‘physical substance,”
all show that the materialists are engaged in meaningless (and abstract)
discourse. These arguments aim to
show that the materialists have no real
meaning attached to their words.
Berkeley now switches to a new sort of argument—he argues that we can
have no evidence
for the “notion” of a physical
substance. Since we can have no
evidence for it, and could not know it if it existed, he contends, we should not
be committed (certainly not “fundamentally committed”) to such things!
-Discuss Occam’s razor and
Plato’s beard.
18. Even if it made any sense to
say that “physical substance supports the accidents,”
there would be no way to know substance: “but though it were possible that
solid, figured, movable substances may exist without the mind, corresponding to
the ideas we have of bodies, yet how is
it possible for us to know this?
Either we must know it by sense or by reason.
As for our senses, by them we have the knowledge only of our sensations,
ideas, or those things that are immediately perceived by sense; but they do not
inform us that things exist without the mind....it must be by reason, inferring
their existence from what is immediately perceived by sense.
But what reason can induce us to believe the existence of bodies without
the mind, from what we perceive, since the very patrons of matter themselves do
not pretend there is any necessary connection betwixt them and our ideas?”
19. [Additional argument:]
Moreover, even if we suppose the notion of substance,
it does not do its job! Those
who propose such a “notion” “...by their own confession are never the nearer
knowing how our ideas are produced, since they own themselves unable to
comprehend in what manner body can act upon spirit, or how it is possible it
should imprint any idea in the mind.
Hence it is evident the production of ideas or sensations in our minds
can be no reason why we should suppose mater or corporeal substances, since it
is acknowledged to remain equally inexplicable with or without this supposition.
If therefore it were possible for bodies to exist without the mind, yet
to hold they do so must needs be a very precarious opinion: since it is to
suppose without any reason at all, that God has created innumerable beings that
are entirely useless, and serve to no manner of purpose.”
-20. Material objects do not
serve as an explanatory tool: “in short, if there were external bodies, it is
impossible we should ever come to know it; and
if there were not [such bodies], we might
have the very same reasons to think there were that we have now.”
--Suppose a mind with
our same ideas, but with no physical causes.
It would have the very evidence that we have for physical substances
(and, of course, its evidence would be misleading)!
21-24: Fifth argument: The notion of physical substance
is contradictory [a direct attack upon the belief in such objects—we cannot even
conceive of an object existing “outside the mind]:”
Whereas we have had “linguistic,” and “epistemic”
arguments, we now come to a stronger sort of argument—at least so Berkeley
suggests. He wants to argue against
the “metaphysical possibility” of material substance!
He will contend that the concept involves a
contradiction, and, thus,
there can be no such things.
22. Try to imagine something
existing unperceived—if you succeed, it exists perceived!
23. A tree falling in the woods
with no one around—no woods! In
short, be careful as you engage in the recommended experiment.
24. There is a
contradiction involved in “matter:”
1. Phenomenalistic
analysis of “things”—they are “nothing but” collections of ideas.
2. Ideas are “in” minds—they can
not “be” “outside” of minds.
3. Materialists contend that
“things” “exist” “outside” of minds.
Therefore, materialists
contradict themselves, and (since contradictory things can not exist), there are
no such things.
--This argument can be
“attacked” by rejecting (i) the phenomenalistic analysis of “things”,
criticizing the claim that ideas are “in” minds (and the substance metaphysics
which is in the background), or, perhaps, by criticizing the connection between
“contradiction” and “nonexistence.”
25-33: How are
ideas caused?
i) 25: They cannot be
caused by extension, figure, and motion.
These qualities are ideas, and
all ideas are inactive—there is nothing of power or agency in them.
Look at your ideas and you will see this!
ii) 26: Ideas must
therefore be caused by a substance or spirit.
There is substance: “we perceive a continual succession of ideas, some
are anew excited, others are changed or totally disappear.
There is therefore some cause of these ideas, whereon they depend, and
which produces and changes them.
That this cause cannot be any quality or idea or combination of ideas, is clear
from the preceding section. It must
therefore be a substance; but it has been shown that there is no corporeal or
material substance; it remains therefore that the cause of ideas is an
incorporeal active substance or Spirit.”
-Note the
presuppositions here!
iii) 27:A spirit “...is
one simple, undivided, active being: as it perceives ideas it is called the
understanding, and as it produces or
otherwise operates about them, it is called the
will.”
Berkeley contends that we can
have no idea of spirit. “A spirit
is one simple, undivided, active being....”
We can have no idea of substance or spirit (logically): “though it must
be owned at the same time that we have some
notion of soul, spirit, and the
operations of the mind such as willing, loving, hating....”
-Cf.,
section 89 where Berkeley clarifies his conception of substance and his way of
“knowing” the self: “we comprehend our own existence by inward feeling or
reflection, and that of other spirits by reason.
We may be said to have some knowledge or notion of our own minds, of
spirits and active beings, whereof in a strict sense we have not ideas.
In like manner we know and have a notion of relations between things or
ideas, which relations may be perceived by us without our perceiving the
former.”
-Cf.,
section 145: “from what has been said, it is plain that we cannot know the
existence of other spirits, otherwise than by their operations, or the ideas by
them excited in us. I perceive several
motions, changes, and combinations of ideas, that inform me there are certain
particular agents like myself, which accompany them, and concur in their
production. Hence the knowledge I
have of other spirits is not immediate, as is the knowledge of my ideas: but
depending on the intervention of ideas, by me referred to agents or spirits
distinct from myself, as effects or concomitant signs.”[21]
-Cf.,
sections 139-140, and p. xxxiii of Kenneth Winkler’s “Editor’s Introduction.”[22]
In these sections Berkeley elaborates upon why we can not have an idea of
soul, spirit, or mental substance.
-Berkeley expands upon
his discussion of our “notion” of the self, soul, or spirit in
his Three Dialogues Between Hylas and
Philonous [1713] where he explicitly replies to an objection which holds
that his reasons for rejecting corporeal substance seem to apply to incorporeal
substance as well. In this
discussion he maintains that: “...I do not deny the existence of material
substance merely because I have no notion of it, but because the notion of it is
inconsistent, or, in other words, because it is repugnant that there should be a
notion of it.
Many things, for aught I know, may exist
whereof neither I nor any other man has or can have any idea or notion
whatsoever. But then those
things must be possible, that is, nothing inconsistent must be included in their
definition. I say, secondly, that
although we believe things to exist which we do not perceive, yet we may not
believe that any particular thing exists without some reason for such belief;
but I have no reason for believing the existence of matter. I have no immediate
intuition thereof, neither can I immediately from my sensations, ideas, notions,
actions, or passions infer an unthinking, unperceiving, inactive substance,
either by probable deduction or necessary consequence.
Whereas, the being of my self, that is, my own soul, mind, or thinking
principle, I evidently know by reflection....In the very notion or definition of
“material substance” there is included a manifest repugnance and inconsistency.
But this cannot be said of the notion of spirit.
That ideas should exist in what does not perceive, or be produced by what
does not act, is repugnant. But it
is no repugnancy to say that a perceiving thing should be the subject of ideas,
or an active thing the cause of them....I
have a notion of spirit, though I have not, strictly speaking, an idea of it.
I do not perceive it as an idea, or by means of an idea, but know it by
reflection.”[23]
-“...I know or am
conscious of my own being, and that I
myself am not my ideas, but something else, a thinking, active principle
that perceives, knows, wills, and operates about ideas.
I know that I, one and the same self, perceive both colors and sounds,
that a color cannot perceive a sound, nor a sound a color, that I am therefore
one individual principle distinct from color and sound, and, for the same reason
from all other sensible things and inert ideas.
But I am not in like manner conscious either of the existence or essence
of matter. On the contrary, I know
what nothing inconsistent can exist, and that the existence of matter implies an
inconsistency. Further, I know what
I mean when I affirm that there is a spiritual substance or support of ideas,
that is, that a spirit knows and perceives ideas.
But I do not know what is meant when it is said that an unperceiving
substance has inherent in it and supports either ideas or the archetypes of
ideas. There is, therefore, upon
the whole no parity of case between spirit and matter.”[24]
-In his “Editor’s
Introduction,” Jonathan Dancy contends that Berkeley doesn’t succeed in putting
the issue to rest, however—he contends that the conclusion which it seems
appropriate to draw from Berkeley’s argument is that his “positive” notion of a
mental substance must go the way of Locke’s (and others’) notion of a material
one.[25]
iv) 28: We are the cause
of some of our ideas.
v) 29-32: But God is the
cause of the ideas of sense. He
produces them according to set rules or laws of nature, enabling us to regulate
our actions for the benefit of life.
-29. “...whatever power I may
have over my own thoughts, I find the
ideas actually perceived by sense have not a like dependence on my will....There
is therefore some other will or spirit that produces them.”
--It is worth noting
that Berkeley’s proof of the deity here is (i)
a posteriori; and (ii) in many ways,
really not a proof of existence but,
rather of the nature of the deity
(existence is established by our inability to cause these ideas).
--Jonahan Dancy notes in
his “Editor’s Introduction: “there is one weakness in Berkeley’s proof, which it
shares with the others [other a
posteriori proofs]....even if we agree that ideas of sense need a
[different] cause [than ourselves] and that only minds can be causes, we surely
want to know what it is that tells us that
one and the same mind is the cause of
all the ideas of sense.
Might there not be several very powerful minds, all at work at once?”[26]
--30. “The
ideas of sense are more strong, lively,
distinct, than those of imagination:
they have likewise a steadiness, order, coherence, and are not excited at
random, as those which are the effects of human wills often are, but in a
regular train or series, the admirable connection whereof sufficiently testifies
the wisdom and benevolence of its Author.”
--“...the set rules or
established methods wherein the mind we depend on [his deity] excites in us the
ideas of sense, are called the laws of
nature; and these we learn by experience, which teaches us that such and
such ideas are attended with such and such other ideas, in the ordinary course
of things.”
-31. We learn the laws of
nature through experience, not a priori
by studying relations amongst ideas!
-32. Our most frequent
mistake in regard to these laws is to “...attribute power and agency to the
ideas themselves....”
-Cf.,
sections 56-57.
vi) 33. Ideas of
sense are real things.
They are more regular, vivid, and constant than ideas of imagination.
“The ideas imprinted on the senses by the Author of nature are called
real things; and those excited in the imagination, being less regular, vivid,
and constant, are more properly termed
ideas, or images of things, which they copy and represent.”
-“The ideas of sense are
allowed to have more reality in them, that is, to
be more strong, orderly, and coherent
than the creatures of the mind; but this is no argument that they exist without
the mind. They are also less
dependent on the spirit, or thinking substance which perceives them, in that
they are excited by the will of another...spirit....”
Nonetheless, they are ideas.
Sections 34 through 84 provide
Berkeley’s “responses” to a number of “objections” he anticipated, and in
Sections 86-156 he provides an account of the “advantages” he claims for his
immaterialism over materialism. We
will largely skip over these sections in this class.
I have already discussed section 89, however, and we need to look at
sections 139-149 as here he elaborates upon his account of minds (spirits) and
of a deity. As Jonathan Dancy notes in his “Editor’s Introduction:”
in the remainder of the Principles Berkeley considers three main threats [to the acceptability of his theory]. His views may be in breach of common sense; they may be in opposition to established scientific opinions and results; and they may be in opposition to religion. In each of these cases he argues that his philosophy leaves things either no worse, or else notably better, than they were before [on the supposition of materialism]. In the second part [sections 34-84], where he is considering objections, he is still fairly defensive. In the third part [sections 86-156], where he is listing advantages, things are rather more positive.[27] I will only discuss the final seven of the sections in this "third part."
139-140 While we don’t have an
idea of spirit, we do have a notion here.
142 Spirits are not known in the
same way as ideas, but nonetheless they are known and exist.
Here he argues from effects to their causes.
The spirits are what relate the ideas to one another.
145 “...we cannot know the
existence of other spirits otherwise than by their operations, or the ideas by
them excited in us.”
146. “...if we attentively
consider the constant regularity, order,
and concatenation of natural things, the surprising magnificence, beauty,
and perfection of the larger, and the more exquisite contrivance of the smaller
parts of the creation, together with the
exact harmony and correspondence of the whole, but above all the
never-enough-admired laws of pain and
pleasure, and the instincts or natural inclinations, appetites, and passions
of animals; I say if we consider all these things, and at the same time attend
to the meaning and import of the attributes: one, eternal, infinitely wise,
good, and perfect, we shall clearly perceive that they belong to the aforesaid
spirit, “who works all in all,” and “by whom all things consist.””
147. Therefore it is evident, he
says, that a deity exists.
148. Human beings are not
perceived by sense. Similarly with
the deity.
149. Those who don’t see this
truth are “blinded by the light.”
(end of reading assignment)
Appendix: Summary of Berkeley’s
Arguments Against Substance:
1. Phenomenalistic analysis of sensible objects and
assertion that ideas can not exist unperceived (section 4).
2. Critique of abstract ideas and assertion that “physical
substance is such an idea” (sections 5, 10-15).
3. Assertion that ideas are signs and not copies—way around
problem of representationalism (section 8).
4. Primary/secondary qualities argument (sections 9-15).
5. What do they (Locke, et. al.) mean by “supporting?”
(sections 16, 17).
6. There is no way to know substance (section 18).
Here is the core of idealism—the
view that if “something” is not in mind, it does not exist!
THIS POINT IS WORTHY OF ELABORATION!
7. Even if we suppose such a notion, it doesn’t do its job
(section 19).
8. A spirit which had ideas only “internally” and was never
exposed to physical substance might have the same evidence as one which was,
thus we have no evidence for such substance (section 20).
9. Try to imagine something existing unperceived—but be
careful (sections 22-24).
(end)
[1] These
notes are to George Berkeley,
Treatise
Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge
[1710, 1734], ed. Kenneth Winkler (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1982).
Throughout these notes refer to the
section numbers of the Introduction, or of Part
I, rather than to pages in the text.
[2] David
Hume, A
Treatise of Human Nature [1739], L.A. Selby-Bigge
(Oxford: Oxford U.P., 1888, second edition:
1978).
Further references to this work will
refer to it as the “Treatise” and, following the
standard model, will refer to the Book, Part,
and Section—thus “Treatise I I 7” refers to Book
I, Part I, Section 7 of this work.
[3]
Cf.,
Berkeley’s November 25, 1729 letter to Johnson,
in George
Berkeley: Principles, Dialogues, and
Philosophical Correspondence, ed. Colin M.
Turbayne (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965), p.
228.
[4] Kenneth
Winkler, “Introduction” [1982], in
George
Berkeley,
Treatise
Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge
[1710], ed. Kenneth Winkler,
op. cit.,
pp. xi-xxxiv.
[5] Jonathan
Dancy, “Notes:
The
Principles,” in
George
Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles
of Human Knowledge [1710, 1734], ed.
Jonathan Dancy (Oxford: Oxford U.P., 1998), p.
194.
[6] David
Hume,
Treatise I I 7,
op. cit.
[7] Jonathan
Dancy, “Notes:
The
Principles,”
op. cit.,
pp. 195-196.
[8]
Cf.,
J.L. Austin,
How To Do
Things With Words (Oxford: Oxford U.P.,
1962).
He contends that human beings use
language primarily to do things—they engage in
“speech acts” where they call out warnings, make
promises, offer excuses, and name things.
In the case of warning, obviously, the
goal is not to communicate an idea (a
la Locke), but, rather, to, for example, to
get someone to duck.
Cf.,
Ludwig Wittgenstein,
Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M.
Anscome (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1953).
He contends that our simplest uses of
language are entirely practical—rather than
communicating images or ideas, we want to get
people to “do something.”
[9] It is to
be noted that since Berkeley holds that there
are two sorts of “things” (ideas and minds), the
discussion of the introduction would, at best,
only give us a nominalism about the former—it
leaves open the question of whether there are
“general minds.”
Berkeley, of course, rejects any such
talk, and thus wants to maintain that whatever
is, is particular.
[10] Hilary
Putnam, “After Empiricism,” in his
Realism
With A Human Face (Cambridge: Harvard U.P.,
1990), pp. 43-53, p. 46.
Emphasis added to passage.
[11]
Cf.,
W.V. Quine,
Word and
Object (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1960).
[12] Jonathan
Dancy, “Editor's Introduction,” in
George
Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles
of Human Knowledge [1710, 1734], ed.
Jonathan Dancy
op. cit.,
pp. 5-69, p. 42.
Cf.
pp. 42-44 for Dancy's extended argument about
the rival interpretations of Berkeley here.
[13] David
Stove, “Idealism: A Victorian Horror Story,” in
his The
Plato Cult (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991),
pp.
83-133, p. 123.
[14] Of
course, he does not mean this in a complementary
fashion.
This “nice strain of abstraction” is, for
him, the most serious sort of linguistic
confusion.
[15] W.T.
Jones, Hobbes to Hume (second edition) (New
York: Harcourt, 1969), p. 285.
[16] Jonathan
Dancy, “Notes:
The
Principles,”
op. cit.,
pp. 199-200.
[17]
Catherine Elgin, “Relocating Aesthetics:
Goodman’s Epistemic Turn” [1993], in her
Between
the Absolute and the Arbitrary (Ithaca:
Cornell U.P., 1997), pp. 63-80, pp. 67-68.
The essay originally appeared in
Revue
Internatiolale de Philosophie v. 46 (1993),
pp. 171-186.
[18] Fred
Dretske, “The Pragmatic Dimension of Knowledge,
Philosophical Studies
v. 40
(1981), pp. 363-378, p. 367.
[19]
Ibid.,
pp. 367-368.
[20] Jonathan
Dancy, “Notes:
The
Principles,”
op. cit.,
pp. 200-210.
[21] Here, it
should be noted, we have a window to a problem
which many who follow our empiricists inherit.
Since they begin with
an
individual's ideas, they find it difficult
to prove that there are
other
individuals (the “problem” is often called “the
problem of other minds”).
There is, of course, a direct parallel
here to the problem of representationalism (also
called the problem of the external world) which
we discussed in Locke.
[22] Kenneth
Winkler, “Editor's Introduction,” in his edition
of
Berkeley's Principles,
op. cit.,
pp. xi-xxxvi, p. xxxiii.
[23] George
Berkeley,
Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous
[1713, 1734],
in
Berkeley: Principles, Dialogues, and
Correspondence, ed. Colin Turbayne,
op. cit.,
pp. 177-178.
The passage is on pp. 115-116 of the
Dancy edition [Three
Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous [1713,
1734], ed. Jonathan Dancy (N.Y.: Oxford U.P.,
1998)].
[24]
Ibid.,
pp. 178-179 (p. 117 of the Dancy edition).
[25]
Cf.,
Jonathan Dancy, “Editor's Introduction,”
op. cit.,
pp. 56-58.
[26] Jonathan
Dancy, “Editor's Introduction,”
op. cit.,
p. 39—emphasis added to passage twice.
Indeed, Berkeley has a problem with
personal identity which is similar here--cf.
Dancy's footnote 19 on p. 117 of his edition
of
Berkeley's Three Dialogues, op. cit., p.
173.
[27] Jonathan
Dancy, “Editor's Introduction,”
op. cit.,
pp. 17-18.
Go to Selected Criticisms of Berkeley
File last revised on 03/23/15.