Lecture Supplement on Bernard Williams’ “Against
Utilitarianism”[1]
[1973]
Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
Bernard Williams contends that utilitarianism (and
consequentialism generally), rests upon an extreme notion of impartiality which
focuses exclusively upon the consequences of our actions.
Williams uses two examples to try and show that there is a serious
problem with utilitarianism here: the
doctrine deprives agents of their
integrity. He contends that
this happens because utilitarianism
separates an agent’s actions from his “projects.”
The Text:
245 “Consequentialism is
basically indifferent to whether a state of affairs
consists in what I do, or is
produced by what I do, where that
notion is itself wide enough to include, for instance situations in which other
people do things which I have made them do, or allowed them to do, or encouraged
them to do, or given them a chance to do.
All that consequentialism is interested in is the idea of these doings
being consequences of what I do, and
that is a relation broad enough to include the relations just mentioned, and
many others.”
-Note that this sentence is
understandable only after one has read the whole article!
246 Utilitarianism is [overly]
committed to a strong doctrine of
negative responsibility which flows from the fact that it assigns ultimate
value to states of affairs. [See p.
225 below!]
-...from the moral point
of view [for the utilitarian and consequentialist], there is no comprehensible
difference which consists just in my
bringing about a certain outcome rather than
someone else’s producing it.
That the doctrine of negative responsibility represents in this way the
extreme of impartiality, and abstracts from the identity of the agent, leaving
just the locus of causal intervention in the world—that fact is not merely a
surface paradox.
247 Williams notes that while the
use of particular examples in moral theory (as one attempts to disprove by
counter-example) is subject to problems (e.g., the examples may be
arbitrarily cut-off from alternative courses of action, or they may be
arbitrarily cut off from the rest of the agents’ lives), the examples to be
presented are to be sufficiently detailed that they should, at least, point to
serious problems.
-Indeed, he contends, in moral
thought “...discussion about how one would think and feel about situations
somewhat different from the actual...plays an important role in discussion of
the actual.”
First example:
George (an unemployed new Ph.D. in
chemistry): should he take a job working on biological and chemical warfare?
Someone else will if George doesn’t; George has a family; jobs are
scarce; George’s wife isn’t against this sort of research.
Second example:
Jim in the jungle: either Pedro
kills twenty Indians or Jim kills one.
-“To these dilemmas, it
seems to me that utilitarianism replies, in the first case, that George should
accept the job, and in the second that Jim should kill the Indian.
Not only does utilitarianism give us these answers, but, if the
situations are essentially as described and there are no further special
features, it regards them, it seems to me, as
obviously right answers.”
248 “A feature of utilitarianism
is that it cuts out a kind of consideration which for some others makes a
difference to what they feel about such cases: a consideration involving the
idea, as we might first and very simply put it, that each of us is specially
responsible for what he does, rather
than for what other people do. This
is an idea closely connected with the value of
integrity.”
-We should, perhaps, ask
ourselves: “What is integrity?”
We then should ask whether Williams correctly captures it, and whether he
is right in his claim that, utilitarianism can not account for, or allow for,
it.
-While utilitarians might
suggest that we should forget about integrity, we can not do that and this
points to a weakness in utilitarianism: “...the reason why utilitarianism cannot
understand integrity is that it cannot
coherently describe the relation between a man’s projects and his actions.”
-248-250 Utilitarians often
consider the psychological effect of a course of action upon the agent.
But the bad feelings George or Jim might have are, from a strictly
utilitarian point of view, irrational!
Indeed, a utilitarian should suggest that any squeamishness felt, for
example, by Jim, is actually
self-indulgent and should be ignored rather than valued or followed!
--249-250 “The reason why the
squeamishness appeal can be very unsettling, and one can be unnerved by the
suggestion of self-indulgence in going against utilitarian considerations, is
not that we are utilitarians who are uncertain what utilitarian value to attach
to our moral feelings, but that we are partially at least not utilitarians, and
cannot regard our moral feelings as objects of utilitarian value.
Because our moral relation to the world is partly given by such feelings,
and by a sense of what we can or cannot “live with,” to come to regard those
feelings from a purely utilitarian point of view, that is to say, as happenings
outside one’s moral self is to lose a sense of one’s moral identity: to lose, in
the most literal way, one’s integrity.
At this point utilitarianism
alienates one from one’s moral feelings; we shall see a little later how, more
basically, it alienates one from one’s actions as well.”
--250 Utilitarianism and the
punishment of an innocent minority by the majority.
Moral feelings of revulsion are irrational here!
Omitted from our text is
Williams’ discussion of the precedent
effect—the effect that such a precedent might establish for other people.
But neither of the cases in question are such that there should be such
an effect: Jim’s case is relatively unique and George’s situation is relatively
private. For the precedent effect
to be relevant, others must be in the same sort of situation and the likelihood
of this occurring must be significant.
251 Consequentialism offers a
strong doctrine of negative
responsibility:
-Negative
responsibility: “...if I know that if I do X, O1 will eventuate,
and if I refrain from doing X, O2 will [eventuate], and that O2
is worse than O1, then I am responsible for O2 if I
refrain voluntarily from doing X.
`You could have prevented it’ can be said truly to Jim, if he refuses, by the
relatives of the other Indians.”
-“That may be enough for us to
speak, in some sense, of Jim’s responsibility for that outcome, if it occurs;
but it is certainly not enough...for us to speak of Jim’s
making those things happen.”
Pedro is the person who makes the effects (kills the Indians).
The problem Williams is
pointing to here is, perhaps, indicated by the following question: “What
projects [of life] does (or, could) a utilitarian agent have?”
-“...among the things that make
people happy is not only making other people happy, but being taken up or
involved in any of a vast range of projects, or...commitments.
One can be committed to such things as a person, a cause, an institution,
a career, one’s own genius, or the pursuit of danger.”
-“Happiness...requires
being involved in, or at least content with, something else.”
-252 But utilitarianism
requires, in effect, that we stand back from our projects and value them only if
the promote the general utility: “...what the outcome will actually consist of
will depend entirely on the facts, on what persons with what projects and what
potential satisfactions there are within calculable reach of the causal levers
near which he finds himself. His
own substantial projects and commitments come into it, but only as one lot among
others—they potentially provide one set of satisfactions among those which he
may be able to assist from where he happens to be.
He is the agent of the satisfaction system who happens to be at a
particular point at a particular time: in Jim’s case, our man in
-253 “It is absurd to
demand of such a man when the sums come in from the utility network which the
projects of others have in part determined, that he should just step aside from
his own project and decision and acknowledge the decision which utilitarian
calculation requires. It is to
alienate him in a real sense from his actions and the source of his action in
his own convictions. It is to make
him into a channel between the input of everyone’s projects, including his own,
and an output of optimific decision; but this is to neglect the extent to which
his actions and his decisions have to be seen as the actions and decisions which
flow from the projects and attitudes with which he is most closely identified.
It is thus, in the most literal sense, an attack on his integrity.”
253-254 “The significance of the
immediate should not be underestimated.
Philosophers, not only utilitarian ones, repeatedly urge one to view the
world sub specie aeternitatis,[2]
but for most human purposes that is not a good species to view it under.”
(end)
For an excellent critique of William’s essay, examine Peter
Railton’s “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality.”[3]
[1] Notes to
selection in
Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings
(sixth edition), eds. Louis Pojman and James
Fieser (Belmont: Wadsworth, 2007), pp. 245-254.
The selection originally appeared in
Utilitarianism: For and Against, Bernard
Williams and J.J.C. Smart (Cambridge: Cambridge
U.P., 1973), pp. 97-99, 101-103, 108-109, and
112-116.
[2] That is,
“under the aspect of eternity.”
[3] Peter
Railton, “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the
Demands of Morality,” in
Philosophy and Public Affairs v. 13 (1984),
pp. 134-171.
File revised on: 09/28/2013.