Lecture Supplement to John Dewey’s “The Influence of Darwinism On Philosophy" [1909][1]

 

     Copyright © 2014 Bruce W. Hauptli

 

Click here for a newer version of this file

Charles Darwin’s On the Origin of the Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life was published in 1859, and the title was shortened to On The Origin of Species for the 1872 sixth edition.  The essay had a transformative effect upon science, culture, and philosophy—one which is still working itself out a century and a half later! 

 

In his “Dewey, Democracy: The Task Ahead of Us,” Richard Bernstein maintains that:

 

it is the [Darwinistic] understanding of life and experience as process, as change, as organic interaction that Dewey emphasized.  We are neither beings with a fixed human nature which unfolds in the course of time nor are we infinitely plastic and perfectible.  Human beings are continuous with the rest of nature but have the capacity to develop those beliefs, dispositions, sensitivities and virtues that Dewey called “reflective intelligence.”  Experience itself involves undergoing, suffering, activity, and consummations.[2] 

 

In short, and as we shall see, an important characteristic of the American Pragmatists’ orientation will be a general adherence to naturalism—in the sense in which this term is contrasted with “supernaturalism!”  Thus H.S. Thayer notes that

 

...Darwinism...challenged the idea of a universe created for or directed to some overall final purpose....The particular conditions and form of change, rather than universal “laws” of growth become the significant item.  And particular changes, variations among and within species, were seen as functions of particular adaptive circumstances and purposes or “struggles.”  The variability of life in nature, the contingencies of successful and unsuccessful adaptations, appeared to render any philosophic attempt to formulate a complete system of natural phenomena or to legislate the goals of nature vain and pretentious.  Chance and design were both features of the world but in neither case deducible from metaphysical principles.  Finally, man’s life was seen as set within nature and like all other living forms subject to uncertainty, unprivileged although advantageously equipped for survival.[3] 

 

In his “The Development of American Pragmatism,” John Dewey maintains that a central differentiation between instrumentalism or pragmatism, on the one hand, and traditional empiricism, on the other, is that the former is forward-looking (looking at “consequent” phenomena) rather than backward-looking (looking at “antecedent” phenomena).[4]  He goes on to maintain that this shows that pragmatism or instrumentalism has metaphysical implications:

 

the doctrine of the value of consequences leads us to take the future into consideration.  And this taking into consideration of the future takes us to the conception of a universe whose evolution is not finished, of a universe which is still, in James’ term, “in the making,” “in the process of becoming,” of a universe up to a certain point still plastic.[5] 

 

These introductory points serve to situate Dewey’s essay, which I am using to provide an overall introduction to the American Pragmatists.  Late in the course we will turn back to the work of Dewey in detail. 

 

The Text:

 

336 Dewey notes that “the conceptions that had reigned” for 2,000 years in Western Philosophy emphasized (or assumed) a view which treated the categories of “the fixed and the final” as superior to those of “change and beginning (Dewey uses ‘origins’).  As he notes,

 

-in laying hands upon the sacred ark of absolute permanency, in treating the forms that had been regarded as types of fixity and perfection as originating and passing away, the “Origin of Species” introduced a mode of thinking that in the end was bound to transform the logic of knowledge, and hence the treatment of morals, politics, and religion. 

 

336-337 Dewey notes that the half century since Darwin’s work had been published has been one of intellectual crisis—while the theological consequences had been (and continue to be a century later) significant, Dewey wants to emphasize the changes which arose in science and philosophy.  To clarify this he discusses in detail the pre-Darwinistic intellectual climate which:

 

337-338 –emphasized teleology wherein each sort of thing is to be characterized by its own edios (or species)—which Dewey characterizes [338] as applying to “everything in the universe that observes order in flux and maintains constancy through change.” 

 

338 Dewey sees two alternatives for such views: either the telos of each kind of thing is to be found within that thing, or it is to be found within some transcendent or supernatural region.  As he tells the story human minds turned to the latter alternative to avoid “the pathless wastes of generation and transformation. 

 

On p. 340 he provides an excellent summary of the earlier overall view:

 

-purposefulness accounted for the intelligibility of nature and the possibility of science, while the absolute or cosmic character of their purposefulness gave sanction and worth to the moral and religious endeavors of man.  Science was underpinned and morals authorized by one and the same principle and their mutual agreement was eternally guaranteed. 

 

338-339 Dewey points out that while it is now easy to demean the Scholastic treatment of “real essences,” we need to see how great the transformation was as human thought turned to the alternative approach. 

 

339 He discusses Galileo’s “transfer of interest from the permanent to the changing.”  He says, however, that

 

…prior to Darwin the impact of the new scientific method upon life, mind, and politics, had been arrested, because between these ideal or moral interests and the inorganic world intervened the kingdom of plants and animals.  The gates of the garden of life were barred to the new ideas; and only through this garden was there access to mind and politics.  The influence of Darwin upon philosophy resides in his having conquered the phenomena of life for the principle of transition, and thereby freed the new logic for application to mind and moral and life.  When he said of the species what Galileo had said of the earth, e pur se muove [and yet it moves], he emancipated, once for all, genetic and experimental ideas as an organon [a set of principles for scientific investigation] of asking questions and looking for explanations.” 

 

--Now while there clearly is a lot of rhetorical language in such passages (esp. the use of ‘conquered,’ ‘freed’. and ‘emancipated’), the underlying contrast should be clear.  We will have to turn later to Dewey’s “evaluations” here (and to the question of the superiority which he alleges applies to the Darwinian perspective), but for now at this introductory stage, it is the contrast which we need to understand and remark upon. 

 

339-343 Dewey indicates that while the full consequences of the change he is calling our attention to [in 1910] are not fully clear, several implications seem fairly clear:

 

340-341 –if all organic adaptations are due simply to constant variation and the elimination of those variations which are harmful in the struggle for existence that is brought about by excessive reproduction, there is not call for a prior intelligent causal force to plan and preordain them. 

 

341 –philosophy forswears inquiry after absolute origins and absolute finalities in order to explore specific values and specific conditions that generate them. 

 

343 –To improve our education, to ameliorate our manners, to advance our politics, we must have recourse to specific conditions of generation. 

 

-…a philosophy that humbles its pretensions to the work of projecting hypotheses for the education and conduct of mind, individual and social, is thereby subjected to test by the way in which the ideas it propounds work out in practice. In having modesty forced upon it, philosophy also acquires responsibility. 

 

344 In ending the essay, Dewey points out that the “old habits of thought” will not be easily displaced. 

 

(end)

 

 Notes: (click on note number to return to text for the note--emphasis has been added to several of the citations)


[1] John Dewey, “The Influence of Darwinism on Philosophy,” the essay was originally a lecture in a course of public lectures given by Dewey on Charles Darwin and His Influence on Science,” at Columbia University in 1909.  It was then published in Popular Science Monthly [1909], and reprinted Dewey’s The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy (N.Y.: Henry Holt, 1910).  This supplement is to the reprint in Classic American Philosophers (second edition), ed. Max Fisch ((N.Y.: Fordham U.P., 1996), pp. 336-344.  Emphasis has been added to several citations.  The essay may be found online at: http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/aboutcsp/dewey/darwin.htm .  Emphasis has been added to several of the passages. 

[2] Richard Bernstein, “Dewey, Democracy: The Task Ahead of Us” in Post-Analytic Philosophy, eds. John Rajchman and Cornel West (New York: Cornell U.P., 1985), pp. 48-59, p. 53.  Emphasis added to the citation at several points. 

[3] H.S. Thayer, “Introduction,” in his Pragmatism: The Classical Writings, op. cit., p. 19. 

[4] Cf., John Dewey, “The Development of American Pragmatism,” originally published in Studies in the History of Ideas v. 2, ed. Department of Philosophy of Columbia Univ. (N.Y.: Columbia U.P., 1925), pp. 353-377.  It is reprinted in The Later Works of John Dewey v.2, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: SIU Press, 1984), pp. 3-21.  The citation is to a reprint in Pragmatism: The Classic Writings, ed. H.S. Thayer (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1982), 23-47, pp. 32-33. 

[5] Ibid., p. 33.

Return to PHH 3700 Home page

File revised on