Supplement to Lectures on Gettier’s “Is JTB Knowledge?”
[1] [1963]
Copyright © 2013
Bruce W. Hauptli
1.
Introduction—Analysis and Propositional Knowledge:
Having briefly examined the skeptical challenge to
knowledge, we naturally come to wonder
what knowledge is (what separates
it from “mere” belief). The
traditional analysis[2]
is that knowledge is justified true belief [JTB].
Plato offered this claim first,[3]
and it was a staple of the Western philosophical tradition until 1963 when
Edmund Gettier published his “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”
It is important for us to note in passing that the analysis of knowledge
to be discussed here, the problems with this analysis, and almost all of the
ensuing articles and discussions are all discussions of “propositional
knowledge”—that is, knowledge that p.[4]
As I have noted, there are other
senses of knowledge which are not covered by such analyses.
Moreover, one might well question (as A.J Ayer does in his “Knowing As
Having The Right to be sure[5])
whether anyone can provide a single correct “analysis” of “knowledge”—one might
claim that there is no single unified concept of knowledge.
In his “Plato’s Euthyphro,
Peter Geach maintains that a particular “style of mistaken philosophical
thinking:”
...may well be called the
Socratic fallacy, for its
locus classicus is the Socratic
dialogues. Its influence has, I
think, been greater than that of the theory of Forms; certainly people can fall
into it independently of any theory of Forms.
I have myself heard a philosopher refuse to allow that a proper name is a
word in a sentence unless a “rigorous definition” of ‘word’ could be produced;
again, if someone remarks that machines are certainly not even alive, still less
able to think and reason, he may be challenged to define ‘alive’.
Both these controversial moves are clear examples of the Socratic
fallacy; and neither originates from any belief in Forms.
Let us be clear that this is a
fallacy, and nothing better. It has
stimulated philosophical enquiry, but still it is a fallacy.
We know heaps of things without being able to define the terms in which
we express our knowledge.
Formal definitions are only one way of
elucidating terms; a set of examples may in a given case be more useful than a
formal definition.[6]
While there may be senses of ‘knowledge’ which are not
covered by the sorts of analyses we will be discussing, and while we must keep
an open mind to the possibility that the search for a single analysis may be the
result of an overly simplistic assumption, the pursuit of such an analysis has
engendered much epistemological understanding, and we now turn to this topic.
2. The Traditional
Analysis of Knowledge:
12 JTB thesis: S knows that P
iff:[7]
(i)
P is true,
(ii)
S believes that P, and,
(iii) S is justified in believing
that P.
3. Gettier’s First Case for the
Rejection of the Traditional Analysis:
According to Gettier, traditional analyses are incorrect
because they do not actually state
sufficient conditions for
knowledge.[8]
To show this he will rely upon two points:
“...it is possible for a person
to be justified in believing a proposition that is in fact false”
and
what is called “the
transmissibility
principle:[9]”
“...if S is justified in believing P, and P entails Q, and S deduces Q from P
and accepts Q as a result of this deduction, then S is justified in believing Q”
-The principle works
like this: P = “Socrates is an Athenian,” Q = “Socrates is a Greek,” S is
justified in believing P, P entails Q, S deduces Q from P and accepts Q as a
result of P, and, thus (on the transmissibility principle), S is justified in
believing Q.
Gettier puts these two points together to engender
counter-examples to the traditional JTB analysis.
Here we should note that an analysis of a concept is said to be
too strong when it excludes
cases which clearly fall under the concept—for example, an analysis of
“triangularity” which held that “triangles are closed three-sided figures all of
whose sides are of equal length” would be too strong as it excludes isosceles
and scalene triangles! An
analysis is said to be
too weak when it
includes cases which clearly do
not fall under the concept—for example, an analysis of “triangularity” which
held that “triangles are figures” would be too weak as it includes squares under
the concept.
In his Problems of Knowledge: A
Critical Introduction to Epistemology, Michael Williams maintains that the
first presupposition is worthy of comment.
While the traditional analysis of knowledge is ancient, so is a model of
justification which has fallen into disfavor in modern and contemporary
epistemology—the demonstrative model of
justification. Throughout much
of Western philosophy the demonstrative model (of knowledge and justification)
held that [Euclidean] geometry was the very model of knowledge.
It was the clearest exemplar, and individuals wished to model their
inquiries upon its methodology, practice, certainty, and results.
This meant that knowledge and justification were held to consist in
reasoning which began with self-evident axioms and postulates and proceeded by
deduction upon these beginning points.
With the rise of scientific knowledge in the Early Modern period, an
a posteriori conception arose which
both challenged and then replaced this model.
No longer did knowledge seem to call for self-evident and certain
beginning points, and no longer did justification need to mirror and emulate
deduction. As Williams says,
Gettier’s problem is new, much
newer than the standard analysis….On the demonstrative model, justification (at
least the sort of justification relevant to knowledge) depends on deductive
(truth-preserving) reasoning from self-evidently true premises.
This precludes the crucial presupposition of Gettier’s argument: that a
belief can be justified but false.
It is a fairly recent innovation to extend ‘knowledge’ to beliefs that are well
supported but not strictly entailed by the evidence we have for them.
Within the abstract framework of the standard analysis, a conceptual
revolution has taken place. This
revolution is presupposed by Gettier’s problem, which can emerge only after the
classical conception of knowledge has been abandoned.
[10]
Gettier’s Case I:
14 Smith and Jones are candidates
for a job, and Smith has strong evidence for:
(d) Jones is the man who will get
the job, and Jones has ten coins in his pocket.
His evidence might be that the
president of the company assured him that Jones would get the job, and he
himself has counted the coins in Jones’ pocket.
Now, (d) implies (e):
(e) The man who will get the job
has ten coins in his pocket.
Suppose that Smith recognizes the
entailment, and that he believes (e) on the basis of this.
It seems clear (by the above principle) that
Smith is clearly justified in believing
that (e) is true!
Imagine, however, that Smith does
not realize it, but he is
getting the job; moreover, while he is unaware of the fact, he [also] has
ten coins in his pocket!
Gettier maintains that this
example is one where proposition (e) is
true, Smith believes it, and
Smith’s belief is justified (even
though (d)—through which he inferred (e)—is false).
But, Gettier contends, Smith
does not know (e).
Thus, he is saying, the
traditional JTB analysis is inadequate (it is too weak, and does not state
sufficient conditions for propositional knowledge).
4. Modified Gettier
Counter-Examples:
Both of Gettier’s examples involve
reasoning through false beliefs.[11]
As John Pollock points out, however (building on an example from Alvin
Goldman), this is not a central requirement for what came to be called “Gettier
cases:”
suppose you are driving
through the countryside and see what you take to be a barn.
You see it in good light and from not too great a distance, it looks the
way barns look, and so on.
Furthermore, it is a barn. You then
have justified true belief that it is a barn.
But in an attempt to appear more opulent than they are, the people around
here have taken to constructing very realistic barn facades that cannot readily
be distinguished from the real thing when viewed from the highway.
Under these circumstances we would not agree that you know that what you
see is a barn, even though you have justified true belief.
Furthermore, your belief that you see a barn is not in any way inferred
from a belief about the absence of barn facades.
Most likely the possibility of barn facades is something that will not
even have occurred to you, much less have played a role in your reasoning.
We can construct an even simpler perceptual example.
Suppose S sees a ball that looks red to him, and on that basis he
correctly judges that it is red.
But unbeknownst to S, the ball is illuminated by red lights and would look red
to him even if it were not red.
Then S does not know that the ball is red despite his having a justified true
belief to that effect....These examples...indicate that justified true belief
can fail to be knowledge because of the truth values of propositions that do not
play a direct role in the reasoning underlying the belief.[12]
This version of the problem doesn’t “reason through false
beliefs,” and there are many other versions which raise the problem—indeed, in
his, The Analysis of Knowledge Robert
Shope cataloged 98 distinct examples
of “the Gettier problem” as of 1983.[13]
The closest I have come to a real-world version of
Goldman's barn facade case is the front cover of the 2004 edition of Fromer's
Vermont, New Hampshire, and Maine which is a photo of
"a heard of cow sculptures on
a Vermont farm (location and photographer unattributed).
5. Lucky Guesses, and Lucky (or Accidental) Truths:
Philosophers disagree over how to describe the “problem”
which Gettier uncovers. In his
An Introduction to Contemporary
Epistemology, Matthias Steup distinguishes between a
lucky guess (my
naming the winning team of the super bowl [given the woeful state of my
ignorance in the area of professional football]—cases where given
S’s evidence, the truth of
p is not a likely outcome), and a
lucky truth (my
getting a job at FIU in 1976 [when there were hundreds of candidates, many more
qualified]—cases where in relation to the relevant facts,
p’s truth was not a likely outcome).
As Steup notes
justification is what prevents a true
belief from being a lucky guess, but not from being a lucky truth.
...What the Gettier problem shows us is that in order for a true belief
to qualify as knowledge, it must satisfy two conditions; it must not be a lucky
guess (that is, it must be justified),
and it must not be a lucky truth.
A true belief that isn’t a lucky guess—like Smith’s belief...may still be
a lucky truth, and thus fall short of being knowledge.
Hence in order to solve the Gettier problem, epistemologists have to
figure out what kind of condition can prevent a true belief from being a lucky
truth.[14]
-Note:
in his “Epistemic Luck and the Purely Epistemic,” however, Richard Foley
maintains that: lucky truths may not be
all bad in epistemology: “we can criticize the person’s intellectual
character, or his cognitive equipment, without criticizing everything which is a
product of that character or equipment.
A belief can be rational even though what prompts the believer to choose
his belief or what cognitive equipment causes him to have the belief regularly
produces epistemic howlers. In such
cases, we should admit...that the believer has been epistemically lucky.”[15]
Other epistemologists seek to characterize the Gettier problem by
speaking of “accidental truths.”
For example, Ralph Baergen says what goes wrong in the Gettier cases is:
the target belief is true, but
the way in which it is true isn’t
what the subject has in mind. One
has the feeling that these beliefs are only accidentally true, and this seems to
be what prevents us from regarding these beliefs as knowledge.
The weakness of the JTB theory, then, seems to be that it doesn’t rule
out the possibility that the target belief could be true only accidentally.[16]
The following table may be helpful here regarding “Gettier examples:”
Diagnosis: |
Difficulty explained: |
Potential remedy to restore
knowledge: |
|
Reasoning through false
beliefs: |
some of the beliefs in the
justification are false and this prevents
S
from knowing
p.
|
disallow false beliefs in
justifications, or, more sanely, disallow false
beliefs from playing any central role in
justifications.
|
Not sufficient, there are
Gettier examples which don’t reason through
false beliefs!
[See below.]
|
Lucky guesses: |
given
S’s
evidence, the truth of
p is
not likely, and this prevents
S
from knowing
p.
|
require a justification
with “sufficient evidence” so that p’s
truth is “likely” on S’s evidence and
s/he is not guessing!
|
|
Lucky truths: |
in relation to the facts of
the case,
p’s truth is not likely.
|
add something to the
justification condition to overcome the “luck”
and allow the claim to be knowledge.
|
Multiple attempts!
|
Accidental truths: |
the truth of
p is
only accidental here.
|
add something to the
justification condition to overcome the “luck”
and allow the claim to be knowledge. |
Multiple attempts!
|
Whether we think the problem is inference through false
beliefs, lucky truths, and/or accidental truths, clearly something is amiss with
the traditional analysis. To cinch
his case, Gettier provides a second case:
Gettier’s Case II:
14 Smith has strong evidence for
believing that:
(f) Jones owns a ford.
His evidence might be that Jones
has for all of Smith’s past acquaintance owned Fords, he has ridden in Jones’
Fords, he has just been offered a ride in Jones’ Ford, etc.
Now (f) clearly implies each of the following:[17]
(g) Either Jones owns a Ford, or
Brown (another of Smith’s many friends) is in Boston.
(h) Either Jones owns a Ford, or
Brown is in Barcelona.
(i) Either Jones owns a Ford, or
Brown is in Brest-Litovsk.
Suppose Smith recognizes the
implications, and he believes (g), (h), and (i) on the basis of this
recognition. His beliefs are, by
the above principle justified (even though he doesn’t know where in the world
Brown is).
Suppose, further, that Jones
doesn’t now own a Ford, but that Brown is in Barcelona.
14-15 Does Smith
know that (h)? He believes it,
his belief is justified, and it is true!
Again, Gettier says, we have a case of JTB which isn’t a case of
knowledge. This means that the
fulfillment of the JTB condition is not
sufficient for knowledge.
Again, epistemologists contend, we have a case of an “accidental truth”
(or “lucky truth/guess”).
(end of Gettier essay)
6. An Overview of
Some of the Responses to Gettier’s Counter-Examples:
There are a number of contemporary attempts to devise an
“adequate” analysis of knowledge so
as to avoid the “Gettier problem.”
Each of these endeavors to avoid the possibility of accidental truths (or
lucky truths/guesses) counting as knowledge.[18]
One approach adds a causal
condition maintaining that there must be “an appropriate causal connection”
between our belief and that which justifies it.[19]
Of course, the specification of the “appropriate sort of causal
connection” becomes the main job of such an approach.
Goldman maintains that in addition to the obtaining of the “appropriate
sort of causal connection,” the individual in question must be able to
“correctly reconstruct” (mentally), the causal chain.
The idea here is that accidental truths will be ruled out because of this
condition. If a causal connection
obtains but the individual has a radically altered conception of it, then the
true belief will be deemed an “accidental” one!
A second sort of account argues that knowledge is
undefeated JTB.[20]
As Ralph Baergen notes,
in looking back at the Gettier
cases, one sees that in each one there is some relevant fact (or facts) about
the situation of which the subject is unaware, and the existence of these facts
(along with the subject’s failure to be aware of them) prevents the target
belief from counting as knowledge....Such facts (when they are still
undiscovered) are called
defeaters; when they are in fact
added to one’s stock of information they become
overriders.
Suppose S is
prima facie justified in believing
that P.
An overrider is some fact that, when added to
S’s justification, eliminates that
justification; that is, the new, expanded body of information no longer supports
the target belief. A defeater is a
potential overrider; that is, a defeater is a fact such that, if
S knew about it, it would act as an
overrider. Now, here’s how
defeaters and overriders fit into this account of knowledge: A defeater will
prevent a JTB...from counting as knowledge (but won’t prevent it from being a
JTB), but an overrider prevents a belief from being a JTB (because it prevents
it from being justified).[21]
We will look at an early version of this approach as we
discuss Keith Lehrer and Thomas Paxson’s “Knowledge: Undefeated Justified True
Belief.”
A third approach focuses on the evidence the subject has for the belief
by adding a “conclusive reasons
condition” to the traditional JTB account of knowledge.[22]
It maintains
that we know only if
...the reasons the subject has
for holding the target belief guarantee the truth of the belief.
This rules out the possibility that the theory will label a belief as
knowledge if one’s reasons for holding the belief don’t preclude errors.[23]
Conclusive reasons, then, are intended to eliminate the
possibility of an accidental truth.
There is a complex interrelationship between these accounts but each is
aiming at offering an analysis of knowledge which improves upon the traditional
account and allows us to better understand what knowledge is by identifying
necessary and sufficient conditions
for knowing. John Pollock offers
the following rationale for the seeming intractability of the Gettier problem:
to a certain extent, I think that
the claim that knowledge requires objective epistemic justification provides a
solution to the Gettier problem.
But it might be disqualified as a solution to the Gettier problem on the grounds
that the definition of objective justification is vague in one crucial respect.
It talks about being justified for
some reason, in believing P.
I think that that notion makes pre-theoretic good sense, but to spell out
what it involves requires us to construct a complete epistemological theory.
That, I think, is why the Gettier problem has proven so intractable.
The complexities in the analysis of knowing all have to do with filling
out this clause. The important
thing to realize, however, is that these complexities have nothing special to do
with knowledge per se. What they
pertain to is the structure of epistemic justification and the way in which
beliefs come to be justified on the basis of other beliefs and nondoxastic
states. Thus even if it is deemed
that we have not yet solved the Gettier problem, we have at least put the blame
where it belongs—not on knowledge but on the structure of epistemic
justification and the complexity of our epistemic norms.[24]
In his Pyrrhonian Reflections On
Knowledge and Justification, Robert Fogelin maintains that:
...the justification clause in
the traditional doctrine that knowledge equals justified true belief is now seen
to have two components. The first
concerns the manner in which S came
to adopt a belief. This is the (iiip)[25]
clause, which demands that he do this in an epistemically responsible manner.
The second concerns a relationship between the proposition believed and
the grounds on which it is believed.
This is the (iiig) clause, which demands that these grounds
establish the truth of the proposition believed on their basis.[26]
I claim that in every version of
the Gettier problems we will find this same situation:
S will be justified in his belief,
having come to it in a responsible manner; that is, his performance will satisfy
the (iiip) clause of the amended biconditional.
At the same time, his grounds will not establish the truth of what he
believes, so the (iiig) clause will not be satisfied.[27]
According to Michael Williams, for Fogelin the key to Gettier’s problem
is that we
…have access to information that
Smith lacks. Because of this
‘informational mismatch’, we can see that Smith is
personally but not
evidentially justified in his belief
that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket.
This explains why Gettier’s case
seems to be an example of justified true belief without knowledge.
In one way (epistemic responsibility), Smith’s belief
is justified.
But in another (adequacy of grounds), it is not.
Smith’s grounds are strong only relative to his restricted informational
state. Given our extra information,
they are not strong at all, which is why we are reluctant to count his belief as
an instance of knowledge.[28]
Fogelin contends that knowledge is “...justified true
belief, justifiably arrived at.”[29]
Finally, in her Evidence and
Inquiry, Susan Haack maintains that:
Gettier-type ‘paradoxes’ arise
because of a mismatch between the concept of knowledge, which, though vague and
shifting, is surely categorical, and the concept of justification, which
is essentially gradational.
If so, there may be no intuitively satisfactory analysis of knowledge to be had,
no sharp line to be drawn between cases where a subject does, and cases where he
doesn’t, know, no ideal point of equilibrium which precludes our having
knowledge by luck without precluding our having knowledge altogether.
And to me, at any rate, the question: what counts as better or worse
evidence for believing something? seems both deeper and more important than the
question: supposing that what one believes is true, how good does one’s evidence
have to be before one can count as knowing?[30]
In the remainder of this section of the course, we will examine two
responses to what has come to be called “the Gettier Problem” (Goldman’s causal
theory and a version of the defeasibility analysis—Lehrer and Paxson’s
“fallibilistic” theory). Before we
turn to that discussion, however, I want to discuss the use of examples in the
above discussion (and in what will ensue).
7. Conceptual
Analysis, Intuitions, and “Reflective Equilibrium:”
How is it that Gettier is so certain that
we will agree with
him—what makes him so sure that
we will accept
his examples as cases of JTB without
knowledge? Our other authors
(Lehrer, Goldman, BonJour, etc.) will make similar appeals to
epistemological examples.
Indeed, when we look back at Plato’s dialogues we see something very
similar.
How is it that Plato’s Socrates’ and Gettier’s opponents are supposed to
recognize the “error” of their views?
As Stanley Cavell points out that:
Socrates gets his antagonists to
withdraw their definitions not because they do not know what their words mean,
but because they do know what they (their words) mean, and therefore know that
Socrates has led them into paradox.[31]
I believe Socrates and Gettier are seeking a “reflective
equilibrium” between their theories and judgments, on the one hand, and our
ordinary (or pre-reflective) judgments (or “intuitions”),[32]
on the other. Before we continue,
then, we should critically consider the appropriateness of employing this
technique of seeking such a “reflective equilibrium.”
In his Naturalizing the Mind,
Fred Dretske maintains that it
...is typical of philosophical
thought experiments...[that] one is asked to make judgments about situations
that differ profoundly from the familiar regularities of daily life.
Intuitions are generated by, they bubble out of, customary patterns of
thought, exactly the patterns of thought that are not applicable in the bizarre
circumstances of philosophical thought experiments.
The time to suspend intuitions, the time to not trust snap judgments, is
in the midst of a philosophical thought experiment.
That is where they are least likely to be reliable.[33]
In the case of Lehrer, Gettier, and Goldman (and of others
who we will be reading), we must be on our guard as we encounter the
philosophical use of examples (and counter-examples) intended to produce
reflective equilibrium. One must
guard against adhering too rigidly to one’s “pretheoretic intuitions,” but one
must also guard against adhering too rigidly to one’s “theoretical positions.”
For a more thorough discussion of “reflective equilibrium,” see Stephen
Stich’s “Reflective Equilibrium, Analytic Epistemology, and the Problem of
Cognitive Diversity.”[34]
A discussion of Roderick Chisholm’s “particularism” helps explain why
epistemologists are drawn to seek a “reflective equilibrium.”[35]
As Ralph Baergen notes, Chisholm contends that one can think of
epistemologists as faced with this pair of questions:
(1) Which of our beliefs are
justified? and (2) What conditions must a belief meet in order to qualify as
justified? If we can work out an
answer to one of the questions, the answer to the other should fall into place.
If we knew which of our beliefs where justified, we could examine them
for common features and draw out the conditions that justified beliefs must
meet; and if we knew the conditions on justified belief, we could apply them to
our beliefs to see which are justified.
The methodological question is this: Which of these [questions] should
epistemologists address first?
Those who say we should address (1) have been called [by Chisholm]
“particularists,” and those who give priority to (2) are “methodists.”
Which of these questions we take on first will influence what sort of
results we end up with.[36]
Descartes can be seen as an adherent of what Chisholm calls
“methodism”—he contends that some of our beliefs are justified, some not, and we
must find (and that he has found) a general
method which we can employ to
distinguish them. Chisholm opts for
the alternative of contending that a general method must be “grounded in our
prior beliefs (he calls this “particularism”), and Baergen maintains that:
my preference is to begin with
our ordinary judgments about both
questions, find the points at which these seem to conflict, and resolve these
conflicts by having each side trade away some of its claims.
This approach allows us to avoid having to identify one of the above
questions as having precedence over the other.
Also, we needn’t begin with the assumption that we know the answer to
either question; we need only assume that we have
some idea of the answers to
both questions, and work from there.
As was pointed out earlier, we do have a concept of justification and we
do manage to employ it in a regular manner, so this is not an unreasonable
assumption. Of course, there is a
shortcoming involved in this business of trading away parts of our answers to
each question to get these to agree.
There are many ways of getting the answers to these two questions to
agree. In deciding which of these
resolutions to adopt, one should look for reasonable grounds for departing from
our ordinary judgments.[37]
The case for the utilization of the method of analysis and
reflective equilibrium is straightforwardly put forth here by Baergen.
Of course, there is something suspicious about such a “bootstrapping” activity
(after all, one can not, literally speaking, pull oneself up by one’s
bootstraps). But we will save that
question for later.
[1] Edmund
Gettier, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”
Analysis
v. 23 (1963), pp. 121-123.
The essay is reprinted in
Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology,
Sven Bernecker and Fred Dretske, eds. (N.Y.:
Oxford U.P., 2000), pp. 15.
These notes are to the reprint.
[2] An
“analysis,” in the sense intended here, is meant
to provide an answer to the philosophical
(Socratic) question: “What is it to have
knowledge?” or “What is knowledge?”
The skeptical challenge makes some worry
that knowledge may be unattainable, and makes
others uncertain as to what could count as
knowledge, and generally seems to raise these
questions for us.
[3]
Cf.,
Plato,
Theaetetus, trans. F.M. Cornford, in
The
Collected Dialogues of Plato, eds. Edith
Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (Princeton:
Princeton U.P., 1961), 200d-201d.
[4] Where ‘p’
stands proxy for any proposition (any assertion
or denial).
Not all sentences are propositions
(questions and commands, for example, don’t make
assertions).
[5]
Cf.,
A.J. Ayer, “Knowing As Having The Right To Be
Sure,” in
Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology,
Sven Bernecker and Fred Dretske, eds.
op. cit.,
pp. 7-12, pp. 10-11.
[6] Peter
Geach, “Plato’s Euthyphro,”
The
Monist v. 50 (1966), pp. 369-382, p. 371.
In regard to this claim, Colin Radford’s
“Knowledge—By Examples,” in
Analysis
v. 27 (1966), pp. 1-11 is an interesting
article.
[7] “iff”
stands for “if and only if.”
Such statements are intended to state the
“necessary
and sufficient conditions” for something
being an instance of the named “kind.”
Here ‘P’ stands for any proposition, and
‘S’ for any knowing subject.
[8] Note that
he is not claiming that this analysis does not
state necessary conditions for knowing!
[9] According
to Peter Klein, in his essay “Scepticism,
Contemporary” (in
A
Companion to Epistemology, eds. Jonathan
Dancy and Ernest Sosa [Oxford: Blackwell, 1992],
p. 458-462, p. 459), Gettier may be the first to
explicitly appeal to the principle.
The principle is also often called “the
closure principle”—it says that “...moving from
one proposition to another on the basis of a
recognized entailment does not get us outside of
the closed area of justified beliefs” (Matthias
Steup, An
Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology
[Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall, 1996], p. 20
[footnote] 6).
[10] Michael
Williams,
Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction
to Epistemology (N.Y.: Oxford U.P., 2001),
p. 48.
[11] In Case
I the false belief is (d), while in Case II it
is (f).
[12] John
Pollock, “The Gettier Problem,” in
On
Knowing and the Known, ed. Kenneth G. Lucey
(Amherst: Prometheus, 1996), pp. 89-101, p. 90.
The essay originally appeared in
Pollock’s
Contemporary Theories of Knowledge (Totowa:
Rowman, 1986) on pp. 183-193.
The “barn facade case” appears originally
in Alvin Goldman’s “Discrimination and
Perceptual Knowledge,”
The
Journal of Philosophy, v. 73 (1976), pp.
771-191.
It is reprinted in
Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology,
Sven Bernecker and Fred Dretske, eds.,
op. cit.,
pp. 102, and the example appears in the reprint
on p. 87.
[13]
Cf.,
Robert Shope,
The
Analysis of Knowledge (Princeton: Princeton
U.P., 1983).
[14] Matthias
Steup, An
Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology,
op. cit.,
p. 9.
Emphasis added to passage twice (bold).
[15] Richard
Foley, “Epistemic Luck and the Purely
Epistemic,”
American
Philosophical Quarterly v. 21 (1984), pp.
113-124, p. 121.
[16] Ralph
Baergen,
Contemporary Epistemology (Fort Worth:
Harcourt, 1995), p. 110.
[17] The
implication here is that
p
implies the weaker statement
p or q
(where q is any proposition.
That is, the truth of “Hauptli is
teaching class” implies the truth of “Either
Hauptli is teaching the class or a world-class
logician is teaching the class.”
[18] For
excellent introductory discussions of the
“responses” to the Gettier problem,
cf.,
Louis Pojman’s “The Analysis of Knowledge,” in
his edited collection
The
Theory of Knowledge (third edition)
(Belmont: Wadsworth, 2003), pp.121-125; George
Pappas and Marshall Swain, “Introduction,” in
their edited collection
Essays on
Knowledge and Justification (Ithaca: Cornell
U.P., 1978), pp. 11-40; Ralph Baergen,
Contemporary Epistemology, op. cit., Chapter
5; and Paul Moser’s “Gettier Problem,” in
A
Companion to Epistemology, eds. Jonathan
Dancy and Ernest Sosa,
op. cit.,
pp. 157-159.
[19]
Cf.,
Alvin Goldman, “A Causal Theory of Knowing,”
The
Journal of Philosophy v. 64 (1967), pp.
335-372.
Goldman has considerably modified his
view, and his more mature view is developed in
his
Epistemology and Cognition (Cambridge:
Harvard U.P., 1986).
We will be turning to his essay (and
another) next.
[20]
Cf.,
Keith Lehrer and Thomas Paxson, “Knowledge:
Undefeated Justified True Belief,” which
originally appeared in
The
Journal of Philosophy v. 66 (1969), pp.
225-237, and which we will be studying after we
discuss Goldman’s approach.
Cf.,
also David Annis, “Knowledge and Defeasibility,”
which originally appeared in
Philosophical Studies v. 24 (1973), pp.
199-203—it is reprinted in
Essays on
Knowledge and Justification, eds. George
Pappas and Marshall Swain,
op. cit.,
pp. 155-159, which is on reserve in the Green
Library.
[21] Ralph
Baergen,
Contemporary Epistemology, op. cit., pp.
119-120.
[22]
Cf.,
Fred Dretske, “Conclusive Reasons,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy v. 49
(1971), pp. 1-22.
It is reprinted in
Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary
Epistemology, Sven Bernecker and Fred
Dretske, eds. op. cit., pp. 42-62.
Dretske has come to abandon this sort of
approach for one which involves a complex
analysis of “information”—cf.
his
Knowledge and the Flow of Information
(Cambridge: Bradford Books, 1981)—Dretske’s
“Précis” to this work is reprinted also in
Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary
Epistemology, Sven Bernecker and Fred
Dretske, eds. op. cit.,.
103-117
[23] Ralph
Baergen,
Contemporary Epistemology, op. cit., p. 110.
[24] John
Pollock, “The Gettier Problem,”
op. cit.,
p. 95.
[25] Fogelin
calls this the “performance” clause, the other
is called the “grounds” clause—both italics and
bold.
[26] Robert
Fogelin,
Pyrrhonistic Reflections On Knowledge and
Justification (N.Y.: Oxford U.P., 1994), p.
20.
[27]
Ibid.,
pp. 20-21.
[28] Michael
Williams,
Problems of Knowledge, op. cit.,, p. 51.
Emphasis added to passage.
[29] Robert
Fogelin,
Pyrrhonistic Reflections On Knowledge and
Justification, op. cit., p. 28.
[30] Susan
Haack,
Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in
Epistemology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), p.
7.
Emphasis added to passage twice (bold).
[31] Stanley
Cavell, “Must We Mean What We Say?”, in his
Must We
Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays
(Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1969), pp. 1-43, p.
39.
[32] The
sense of ‘intuition’ used here is not that of a
“special faculty of knowledge,” but, rather,
that of our ordinary, everyday, pre-reflective
judgments about whether a concept is to be
applied to a specific situation—whether, for
example, “bean bag chairs” are properly
considered to be chairs.
[33] Fred
Dretske,
Naturalizing The Mind (Cambridge: MIT U.P.,
1995), p. 147.
[34] Stephen
Stich, “Reflective Equilibrium, Analytic
Epistemology, and the Problem of Cognitive
Diversity,”
Synthese
v. 74 (1988), pp. 391-413.
[35]
Cf.,
Roderick Chisholm,
The
Problem of the Criterion (Milwaukee:
Marquette Univ., 1973), and
Theory of
Knowledge (third edition) (Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice Hall, 1989).
[36] Ralph
Baergen,
Contemporary Epistemology, op. cit., p. 23.
[37]
Ibid.
File revised on 09/19/2013.