Hauptli’s Lecture
Supplement Introducing Berkeley [1685-1753]
Copyright © 2015 Bruce W. Hauptli
1. Berkeley’s Life:
George Berkeley received his B.A. from
while he accepted the great
scientific discoveries of his age, he quickly became and remained sharply
antagonistic to the metaphysics and epistemology that accompanied them.
Thus, in metaphysics he reacted against the Cartesian-Newtonian
world-view, according to which the universe was nothing but a great machine,
originally invented by a supreme mechanic.
In 1709,
In 1713,
Between 1724 and 1732
2. Berkeley’s Theory of Vision—An Introduction to his
Philosophy:
According to The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
...deals with one point only: the
relation between the objects of sight and those of touch.
William Molyneux had once set the problem to Locke, whether a man born
blind, if he recovered [came to have] his sight, would be able by sight alone to
distinguish from one another a cube and a sphere, with both which he had been
previously acquainted by touch.
Molyneux answered his own question negatively, and Locke agreed with his answer.[6]
This discussion provides an initial entry into
One way to offer such a view would be to adhere to
skepticism—to contend that while
ideas should represent an external world, they don’t do so.
This is not
According to
as he understands
reality, real things are subjective, since they consist of ideas, but not
merely subjective, since they are
independent of the mind that is aware of them, and so real for it.
One might say that they are both subjective and objective at once.[9]
While there are
subjective idealists,[10]
then, there are also “objective
idealists.”[11]
Recognizing this is of central importance if we are to come to understand
how
The following citation from his
Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous [1713] helps clarify why he
offers his empiricistic idealism, and what he means when he claims that
“objects” are actually ideas:
Hylas: “Pray, are not the
objects perceived by the senses of one, likewise perceivable to others present?
If there were a hundred more [people] here, they would all see the
garden, the trees, and flowers as I see them.
But they are not in the same manner affected with the ideas I frame in my
imagination. Does not this make a
difference between the former sort of objects and the latter?”
Philonous: “I grant it does.
Nor have I ever denied a difference between the objects of sense and
those of imagination. But what
would one infer from hence? You
cannot say that sensible objects exist unperceived, because they are perceived
by many.”[12]
That is, does the fact that we share the perception of
this chair show that these sensible
qualities exist outside minds altogether?
Surely there is a difference amongst our ideas, he contends but he denies
that this difference is captured by (or needs) the notion of physical objects.
3. Berkeley and The Meaninglessness of Physical
Substance:
A novel point in
At this point it would be good to note that in many ways
You may have trouble with his use of ‘idea’—he
means what we normally mean by ‘thing’.
What does he deny, then, when he maintains that the notion of a physical
substance is senseless? Well,
we usually think that physical
substances can exist independently of minds.
To understand the meaninglessness of “the notion of physical substance,”
we must understand what he means by an
abstract idea.[16]
According to
While
To understand this fully, we will have to understand
While, ultimately, Locke has three kinds of ideas
(particular, general, and abstract), I think it is best to see
4. The Role of Berkeley’s Deity:
The following limerick has often been used to summarize
There was a young man who
said:
“God must think it exceedingly
odd,
if he finds that this tree
continues to be
when there’s no one about in the
Quad.”
Reply:
“Dear Sir: Your astonishment’s
odd:
I am always about in the Quad.
And that’s why the tree continues
to be,
Since observed by Yours
faithfully.”
God.
Just as we must adjust our understanding of the things of the real world
as we read
now Locke...is too sane, and too
respectful of contemporary science, not to be somewhat half-hearted in his
mechanism. He recognized two
awkward phenomena. The first is that of
attraction. The moon influences the
tides by attraction; this is action at a distance, which cannot be thought of as
mechanical. The second is the
phenomenon of cohesion. Something
holds a lump of lead together as a lump, and not as just a heap of the particles
that constitute it. But whatever
force that does this, it is hard to think of it as mechanical.
Locke took the view that these two phenomena are and will remain
incomprehensible to us.[20]
In his “Notes” to
explanation by appeal to
attraction, e.g. explanation of the movements of the tides, was thought to be
far from satisfactory or ultimate by the physicists themselves, even by Newton,
who wrote in a letter to Richard Bentley, ‘It is inconceivable, that inanimate
brute matter should, without the mediation of something else, which is not
material, operate upon, and affect other matter without mutual
contact’....Newton’s response to this difficulty was to say that we do not know
the cause of gravity; but that it must be something real but not material.
This was to be an elastic and electric fluid which
The philosophers agreed that real action at a distance is inconceivable.[21]
For
5. The “Newness” of Idealism:
In his “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw
and Berkeley Missed” M.F. Burnyeat argues that idealism arises only with
Greek philosophy does not know
the problem of proving in a general way the existence of an external world.
That problem is a modern invention....The problem which typifies ancient
philosophical enquiry in a way that the external world problem has come to
typify philosophical enquiry in modern times is quite the opposite.
It is the problem of understanding how thought can be of nothing or what
is not, how our minds can be exercised on falsehoods, fictions, and illusions.[22]
Burnyeat notes that idealism is the one position in modern
philosophy which (contra
whatever hints Augustine
may have furnished, it was Descartes who put subjective knowledge at the center
of epistemology—and thereby made idealism a possible position for a modern
philosopher to take. I mean by this
that it is not until someone brings the question “Is there anything other than
mind?” into the center of philosophical attention that the replies to it—the
affirmative reply of realism, and a
fortiori the negative reply of idealism—will commend themselves as worthy
of, and requiring, explicit defense.
(What I have ascribed to antiquity is an unquestioned, unquestioning
assumption of realism: something
importantly different from an explicit philosophical thesis.)[23]
Burnyeat then goes on to say that:
...it is no accident that
in Descartes’ philosophy the following elements are found in the closest
association: hyperbolical doubt and the problem of the existence of the external
world, subjective knowledge and truth, the dualism which makes one’s own body
part of the external world—and the refutation of the ancient skeptical
tradition. All these are
substantially new with Descartes, and derive from the very seriousness (in one
sense) with which he took the traditional skeptical materials.
It is essential here that this seriousness is entirely methodological.[24]
Burnyeat concludes his treatment with the following:
...Descartes’ hyperbolical doubt,
going beyond all ancient precedent in its use of the idea of a powerful
malignant deity, brought into the open and questioned for the first time the
realist assumption, as I have called it, which Greek thought even at its most
radical never quite managed to throw off.
That was what
To understand what his idealism amounts to, however, we
need to turn to a study of his work.
[1] ‘Dean’
here designates an ecclesiastical officer in the
Anglican Church—a minister who is the chief
officer of a cathedral or a collegiate church,
or a pastoral or visiting ecclesiastic who acts
as a deputy of a bishop or archdeacon.
[2] Colin
Turbayne, “Editor’s Introduction,”
in George
Berkeley: Principles, Dialogues, and
Philosophical Correspondence, ed. Colin
Turbayne (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965),
pp.vii-xxxiv, p. xiii.
[3] George
Berkeley,
A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human
Knowledge [1710, 1734], ed. Kenneth Winkler
(
[4]
[5] In his
Bertrand
Russell: The Spirit of Solitude 1872-1921,
Ray Monk maintains that: “...in his famous
polemic against Newton,
The
Analyst,...[Berkeley] ridiculed Newton’s
Calculus for its theory of ‘infinitesimals’, for
pretending that a Something could, if it is
small enough, be regarded as a Nothing, and yet
still be used in calculations.
What are these ‘infinitesimals’?
More generally...[this sort of critique]
might also be seen as a restatement and
confirmation of the old idea that analysis is to
some degree always a falsification” (Ray Monk,
Bertrand
Russell: The Spirit of Solitude 1872-1921
(N.Y.: Free Press, 1996), p.109).
In his “Editor’s Introduction,” Colin
Turbayne notes that: “
[6] Cf.,
John Locke,
An Essay
Concerning Human Understanding [1690], II ix
8, ed. Kenneth Winkler (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1996).
The reference here, following the
standard model, is to Book II, Chapter ix,
Section 8.
Further references will refer to the work
as “Essay” and the relevant divisions of the
work.
[7] “George
Berkeley,”
The
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy [1996],
ed. James Fieser
(http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/), p.2.
The citation is taken from the electronic
version of February 20, 1998.
The latter portion of the passage from
[8] It is
helpful to look at the title page of the
[9] Jonathan
Dancy, “Editor’s Introduction,” in
George
Berkeley: A Treatise Concerning Human Knowledge,
ed. Jonathan Dancy (Oxford: Oxford U.P., 1998),
pp. 5-69, p. 16.
[10] That is,
individuals who contend that there is nothing
beyond what “subjectively” exists—exists for
one’s subjectivity.
[11] That is,
individuals who contend that there is an
objective reality “beyond” how things “appear”
to any individual, but, at the same time,
contend that this reality is itself
“idealistic”—is “mental.”
Most such idealists, of course, appeal to
a deity maintaining that the “ideas” had by the
deity are not “subjectivistic,” but, rather, are
“objective”—though not “material.”
[12] George
Berkeley,
Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous
[1713],
in Principles, Dialogues, and Philosophical
Correspondence, ed. Colin Turbayne,
op. cit.,
p. 193.
[13] That is,
he contends that “to be is to be perceived, or
to be a perceiver.”
[14] Of
course, there is also an obvious parallel with
John Locke, who intended to avoid empty
metaphysical discourse (especially that of the
Scholastics) by ensuring that we had a method of
reducing our complex conceptions to their simple
components so that we could ensure that our
words were being used meaningfully—that we had
something meaningful in mind.
[15]
Cf.,
John Locke,
Essay
II xxiii 2-4,
op. cit.
[16] Note
that for him an abstract idea is not a species
of idea, but, rather, a mere “notion” which is
not actually before the mind—a sign of mental
confusion.
[17]
Cf.,
[18] John
Locke thought of naming as the basic linguistic
activity (he held that naming one’s own ideas
was the initial move in language use, followed
by the communication of ideas between
individuals, this is then followed by the use of
words to refer to things).
[19] Garrett
Thomson,
Bacon to Kant: An Introduction to Modern
Philosophy (second edition) (
[20] Jonathan
Dancy, “Editor’s Introduction,”
op. cit.,
pp. 12-13.
[21] Jonathan
Dancy, “Notes: The Principles,” in
George Berkeley: A Treatise Concerning the
Principles of Human Understanding, ed.
Jonathan Dancy,
op. cit.,
pp. 194-218, p. 212.
[22] M.F.
Burnyeat, “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What
Descartes Saw and
[23]
Ibid.,
p. 33.
[24]
Ibid.,
p. 39.
[25]
Ibid.,
p. 40.
Go to Lecture Supplement on Berkeley's Principles
File last revised on 02/23/15.