Introduction to
British Empiricism
Copyright © 2015
Bruce W. Hauptli
1. The “Schools” of
The Early Modern Period:
Philosophers often call the period from the sixteenth to
the eighteenth centuries (the period that begins with the French philosopher
Michel de Montaigne [1533-1592], the Italian scientist Galileo Galilei
[1564-1642], the British Philosopher Francis Bacon [1560-1626], and their
contemporaries, and ends with the German Philosopher Immanuel Kant [1724-1804])
the “Early Modern” Period.
This was an intense and interesting philosophical period which is
frequently discussed as containing two different philosophical “schools:” the “Continental
Rationalists” (Rene Descartes [1596-1650], Benedict Spinoza [1632-1677], and
Gottfried Leibniz [1646-1716] are the most notable exemplars) and the “British
Empiricists” (John Locke [1635-1703], George Berkeley [1685-1753], and David
Hume [1711-1776] are the most notable exemplars).
Kant brings together the
disparate strands and thoughts of these two schools and founds a new
philosophical orientation marking the beginning of what philosophers often call
the “Late Modern Period,” which, in turn, leads us up to the contemporary
philosophy of the twentieth and twenty-first centuries.[1]
It should be noted that not all the thinkers of the Early Modern period
neatly fit into either the Continental Rationalist or British Empiricist camps—Blaise
Pascal [1623-1662], for example, is clearly a different sort of thinker (one
who questions the fundamental commitment to, or faith in, reason and rationality
which is characteristic of these two camps and of the intellectual temper of
this age). Moreover, insofar as
Kant is included in this period rather than in the “Late Modern” one, one
clearly would need to say that there were, then,
four “schools” as he weaves and
intertwines elements of both Continental Rationalism and British Empiricism into
a philosophical orientation which is both and neither.
It is important to add to the above the following warning to such
historical overviews:
the tendency to try and discuss
philosophical thought in terms of various “schools-of-thought,” “common themes,”
or “intellectual traditions” can be both false and illuminating.
To speak of the history of philosophy in terms of certain “isms” and “ists”
(for example: “rationalism,” “empiricism,” “materialists,” and “idealists”) is
to skip over and ignore important differences amongst individual philosophers
who may share a number of theses, beliefs, methods, etc., yet employ them to
radically different purposes or draw from them radically different conclusions
or positions.
If one is to come to understand a philosophical “period,”
one must look for both similarities
and
differences in the views of the
various philosophers of that period.
Moreover, while it is important to understand the “intellectual temper”
of a “period,” it may well be a mistake to simply assume that a philosopher of
that period simply and fully embodies that spirit.[2]
Plato is not to be thought of simply as a representative thinker of
ancient
2. Continental
Rationalism Briefly Characterized:
The Continental Rationalists (thinkers such as Descartes,
Spinoza, and Leibniz) each helped to cement the downfall of the
Medieval world-view and the rise of
the modern scientific world-view. A
central tenet of the Medieval period was that
faith and reason could not contradict
one another:
the natural dictates of reason
must certainly be true; it is impossible to think of their being otherwise.
Nor again is it permissible to believe that the tenets of faith are
false, being so evidently confirmed by God.
Since therefore falsehood alone is contrary to truth, it is impossible
for the truth of faith to be contrary to the principles known by natural reason.[3]
The Medieval view was that faith and reason co-operated to
depict a world in which everything accorded with the divine purpose.
While this picture was the dominant one for about a thousand years (from
about 400-1400 C.E.), with the Renaissance (1400-1600) this world-view came
under substantial pressure.
The Continental Rationalists'
period is marked by a change in the attitude toward the Medieval
institutions and beliefs. These
philosophers did not so much ask new
questions, instead, they endeavored to provide answers in a “new
spirit.” These answers weren't
wholly different from the sorts of answers offered by the Medievals, but they
were offered in a new spirit, with a
new method, and in a
new manner.[4]
The Rationalists' fundamental break with the previous tradition was an
unrelenting faith in human reason.
They held we could arrive at knowledge
unaided by religious faith or revelation.
For the Continental Rationalists, Leibniz'
principle of sufficient reason may
be considered the basic principle: they all held that there is a complete, and
completely rational, explanation for
everything which occurs. It
should be stressed that their conception of reason is that knowledge (or truth)
is arranged in a deductive system,
and that one must “begin” with
self-evident a priori truths of
which we can be certain. That is,
their “faith in reason” was a faith in
a priori reasoning—they did not
believe that our sensory experience could provide us with knowledge of the
world. Instead, the Continental
Rationalists held that it is only via
a priori intellectual perceptions
that we grasp the fundamental nature of the universe (the notions of substance,
essence, etc.).
According to the Continental Rationalists, the appropriate methodology
for building upon the self-evident
truths is the deductive axiomatic
method of mathematics (as especially exemplified in geometry) wherein
theorems are derived from axioms and postulates.
Of course, the truth of the theorems is dependent upon the truth of these
axioms and postulates.
The Continental Rationalists believed that these axioms and postulates
were not to be accepted on faith but,
rather, that must be known by and guaranteed by some sort of
intellectual understanding (or
rational intuition). These
intuitions showed certain facts to be
necessary truths and upon this sort of
a priori, rational, and certain
basis, the Continental Rationalists would ground all of our knowledge.
They did not hold, as many now do, that logical truths (tautologies) are
mere “truths of language” (which give
us no substantial information about
the way the world is). Instead,
they held that the necessary truths they which they relied upon reflected
necessary facts and gave us
(certain) knowledge of the basic ways of the world.
In saying that the Continental Rationalists’ conception of reason is that
knowledge (or truth) is arranged in a deductive system, we speak about both
their epistemology and their metaphysics.
Metaphysically speaking, they hold that the world has a fundamentally
deductive structure. Moreover, for
all of them the ontological argument
occupies a position of central metaphysical importance.
The fact “exposed” by this proof provides the “metaphysical
ground” for the whole system of truths which constitutes the created
universe. Epistemologically
speaking, of course, this “ground” provides the explanation for all the other
truths in the total “system” of truths.
At the core of the Continental Rationalists' orientations, then, are what
are called innate principles or ideas.
These “ideas” express the intellectual intuitions which are the heart of
their systems. The classical
example of an innate idea is the idea of
a deity. Standard examples of
innate principles for these thinkers (claims which they hold to be known
a priori, and which are held to be
intellectual intuitions that are certain,
self-evident, and
necessarily true) include: “What
is, is” and “It is impossible for the
same thing to be, and not to be.”
As noted in the Encyclopedia
Britannica:
the Cartesian metaphysics is the
fountainhead of Rationalism in modern philosophy, for it suggests that the
mathematical criteria of clarity, distinctness, and absence of contradiction
among ideas are the ultimate test of meaningfulness and truth.
This stance is profoundly
antiempirical. Bacon, who had
said that “reasoners resemble spiders who make cobwebs out of their own
substance,” might well have said so of Descartes, for the Cartesian self is just
such a substance from which the idea of God originates and with which all
deductive reasoning begins. Yet for
Descartes the understanding is vastly superior to the senses, and, in the
question of what constitutes truth in science, only man's reason can ultimately
decide.[5]
A major problem for the Continental Rationalists is directly evident when
we note the diversity of basic
postulates which the different rationalists advance, and the
radically different conclusions
which they draw from shared principles, postulates, or ideas.
Since they wished to offer
objective theories (which all rational thinkers would have to accept), their
differences at this fundamental level were a matter of no small concern.
Another problem with their orientation is that they have a great deal of
difficulty admitting any degree of
contingency into their systems.
Since their model of knowledge is one which begins with
necessary truths, since their
systems posit deductive connections
between truths, and since they hold that everything is explicable through
this model and these connections, there seems no room for contingency in the
universe. After all,
deductive consequences of necessary truths are themselves necessary, and their
model leaves us with nothing else.
3. A Quick
Characterization of British Empiricism:[6]
Whereas Galileo and Descartes emphasized the role of
deductive reason in the acquisition and defense of knowledge,
Francis Bacon [1561-1626] emphasized
the experimental and
observational methodology of
induction for the acquisition and defense of knowledge.
In his The Great Instauration
[1620], he tries to provide “...a total reconstruction of sciences, arts, and
all human knowledge, raised upon the proper foundations.”[7]
According to him,
...what the sciences stand in
need of is a form of
induction which shall analyze
experience and take it to pieces, and by a due process of exclusion and
rejection lead to an inevitable conclusion.[8]
While Bacon contends that
ordinary sensory experience is not to be trusted, he posits a “new
organon”[9]
(or experimental method) which can correct the errors of ordinary experience:
for the subtlety of experiments
is far greater than that of the sense itself, even when assisted by exquisite
instruments; such experiments, I mean, as are skillfully and artificially
devised for the express purpose of determining the point in question.
To the immediate and proper perception of sense therefore I do not give
much weight; but I contrive that the office of the sense shall be only to judge
the experiment, and that the experiment itself shall judge of the thing.
And thus I conceive that I perform the office of a true priest of the
sense (from which all knowledge in nature must be sought, unless men mean to go
mad) and a not unskillful interpreter of its oracles....[10]
Those however who aspire not to
guess and divine, but to discover and know; who propose not to devise mimic and
fabulous worlds of their own, but to examine and dissect the nature of this very
world itself; must go to facts themselves for everything.
Nor can the place of this labor and search and world-wide perambulation
be supplied by any genius or meditation or argumentation; no, not if all men’s
wits could meet in one. This
therefore we must have, or the business must be forever abandoned.
But up to this day such has been the condition of men in this matter,
that it is no wonder if nature will not give herself into their hands.[11]
Bacon is an early example of the second major “school of
thought” in the Early Modern period: the British Empiricists.[12]
These empiricists hold that most of our knowledge is empirical (or
a posteriori).
Like the Continental Rationalists, they have a faith in human reason, but
they have a different conception of the
nature of “reason”—one based upon
sensory experience rather than beginning with necessary truths.[13]
Whereas the Continental Rationalists hold that deductive reason acting
upon innate principles or ideas reveals the fundamental truths about the world,
the British Empiricists maintain that deductive reasoning “...can only reveal
the logical connections between our ideas; it never increases our knowledge of
what exists; it only results in claims like “All triangles have three sides.””[14]
There are, of course,
many other possible sources of knowledge:
e.g., revelation, testimony, memory, authority,
etc.
We must be careful as we attempt to initially characterize empiricism
here, however. It is often said
that empiricists assign a central role to experience.
This broad characterization is insufficient—when someone says that
everything is based on experience (or justified by appeal to experience, or
originates in experience, etc.), we must
know what concept of experience is being appealed to (atomistic, Romantic,
religious, etc.). As Thomas Grey
points out in his critical review of several books on Oliver Wendell Holmes:
one must always read Holmes’s
scientistic pronouncements remembering that he was also a Romantic.
His skepticism was of the Wordsworthian kind that revels in the sublimity
of the unknown, and when he said law had been and likely always would be based
largely in “experience,” he was invoking the Romantic historicist idea of a
collective unconscious made up of custom and tradition that could never be fully
captured by articulate reason.[15]
As the above discussion of Bacon should illustrate,
‘empiricism’,[16]
in the sense in which we will be using the term, refers to philosophers who
assign a central role to sensory
experience. It should be noted,
however, that there are a variety of distinct ways in which such experience
could “play a central role.” Some
of these can be usefully distinguished by noting the differences between the
following claims:[17]
(a) that human ideas,
understanding, or knowledge have their
source in sense experience;
(b) that they have their
sole source in sense experience;
(c) that human understanding or
knowledge, have sense experience as their
object;
(d) that human understanding or
knowledge arises when sense experience is (properly) used to
test propositions (or hypotheses, or
theories), or ideas; or
(e) that we should
limit our claims to understanding to
those claims which can be
established by appeal to the method which uses sense experience to test
propositions (or hypotheses, or theories), or ideas.
[18]
Whichever version of empiricism one adheres to, however,
there is a clear-cut contrast with Continental Rationalism.
Whereas the rationalists sought to derive knowledge from
a priori axioms (truths which are
held to be “indubitable”) by means of strictly deductive procedures; the British
Empiricists assign a fundamental role to sensory experience (whether as the
source of, object of, or justificatory check upon our knowledge claims).
Thus they contend that our knowledge is fundamentally
a posteriori—as noted above, the
empiricists tend to believe that deductive reasoning can only reveal logical
connections between our ideas and can not reveal truths about what exists—the
latter requires inductive procedures.[19]
Like the Continental Rationalists, the British Empiricists begin with our
ideas, but where the rationalists
begin with a priori innate principles
or ideas which are self-evident and form the basis for deductive knowledge, the
empiricists “begin with” sensory ideas
which form the source or basis for (or object of, or test for)
a posteriori knowledge.
Again, a caution regarding the use of “isms and ists” may be in order
here. In his “Rationalism,” Edwin
Curley maintains that the distinction between Continental Rationalism and
British Empiricism is as misleading as it is useful:
none of the three great
philosophers commonly counted as paradigms of epistemological rationalism was as
dismissive of experience or as trusting of a priori intuition as traditional
accounts of rationalism imply. Such
difficulties have made specialists increasingly reluctant to accept that
classification....Determining the exact relation between reason and experience
in the three paradigm ‘rationalists’ is difficult; an accurate account would be
too complicated to make for a readable general history, and would probably not
conclude that they had any significant epistemological programme in common, or
that they constituted a school of thought to which empiricism could usefully be
opposed.[20]
Curley goes on to discuss several other possible ways of
usefully contrasting the orientations of the early modern philosophers.
4. Some Important
Qualifications Regarding the “Quick Characterization:”
Locke might have severe reservations about the above
characterization. Moreover, both
Berkeley and Hume would likely have strong reservations to be being
characterized as
British empiricists.
In his “Scepticism, Theology and the Scientific Revolution
in the Seventeenth Century,” Richard H. Popkin maintains that the common claim
that the “early modern” period contains a “battle” between theology and science
wherein the latter tries to restrict and restrain the growth of the former, is
an overly simplistic (and incorrect) picture.
Popkin maintains that:
by-and-large, my suspicion is
that the period from Copernicus to
The serious conflict between
theology and science developed, I believe, not from the rise of Copernican
astronomy or mechanism, but from the application of new data and new scientific
concepts to Judeo-Christianity. One
such kind of conflict was involved in explaining Mysteries and Miracles in terms
of seventeenth century science.
Transsubstantiation was a most serious problem for Catholic Cartesians, though,
of course, not for the Protestant ones.
Moreover the more dramatic cases develop from the attempt to comprehend
key events in Biblical history in terms of modern science.
The flood, and the descendence of all of mankind from Noah and his family
provided serious difficulties when examined in light of new geographical,
anthropological, meteorological data, and mechanistic physics.[22]
Popkin talks about the work of Isaac La Peyrere (Pereira)
and Richard Simon, who began modern Biblical scholarship by pursuing “scientific
study” of the Bible, and, thus, posing many problems for theology.
5. Dates of
important publications in the Early Modern Period:
1580 Montaigne’s
Essays.
1610 Galileo’s The
Starry Messenger.
1620 Francis Bacon’s
Great Instauration and New Organon.
1632 Galileo’s
Dialogues Concerning Two Chief World Systems.
1638 Galileo’s
Discoursi (theory of dynamics).
1641 Descartes’
Meditations.
1651 Hobbes’
Leviathan.
1662 Arnauld and Nichole’s
The Art of Thinking.
1670 [post] Pascal’s
Pensees.
1678 [post] Spinoza’s
Ethics.
1686 Leibniz’
Discourse on Metaphysics.
1687
1690 Locke’s Essay
Concerning Human Understanding.
1702 Bayle’s
Dictionaire Historique et Critique.
1710
1716 [post] Leibniz’
Monadology.
1739 Hume’s A
Treatise of Human Understanding.
1759 Voltaire’s
Candide.
1762 Rousseau’s The
Social Contract.
1764 Reid's Inquiry
Into the Human Mind.
1781 Kant’s Critique
of Pure Reason.
[1] The
phrases used to designate these different
periods seem antiquated, and as we sit near the
cusp of two centuries, it seems that what is to
be called “modern” or “contemporary” may soon
require some other form of designation.
It is to be noted that many contemporary
thinkers would contend that we are now in a
“post-modern” era.
Consideration of this takes us too far
afield, but, clearly, an understanding of what
the modern thought is will be requisite if one
is to come to understand what “postmodern
thought” is.
[2] One
philosopher who makes such a linkage is Albert
William Levi in
his
Philosophy As Social Expression (Chicago:
Univ. of Chicago, 1974).
Levi discusses Plato, Aquinas, Descartes,
and Moore and treats their philosophical thought
and theories as “expressions” of their
respective “ages.”
[3] Aquinas,
Summa
Contra Gentiles [~1260],
[4] In his
“Introduction,” Martin Hollis maintains that
“the novelty of Rationalism lies in its method
of enquiry, which owed more to logic and
mathematics and, at the same time, to scientific
experiment than any before.
The results of the method, however, often
owed more to the past than the Rationalists
admitted.
Presumptions made about God, about human
nature and about the character of rational
order...” (Martin Hollis, “Introduction” to
The Light
of Reason: Rationalist Philosophers of the 17th
Century, ed. Martin Hollis (London:
Fontana/Collins, 1973), pp. 9-36, pp. 10-11).
[5]
“Philosophy, history of,”
Encyclopedia Britannica Online,
<http://www.eb.com:180/bol/topic?artcl=108652&seq_nbr=4&page=p&is
ctn=12>, accessed 19 August 1999, emphasis has
been added to the passage.
[6] An
excellent introduction to empiricism in general,
and British Empiricism in particular, is offered
by D.W. Hamlyn in his “Empiricism,” in
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy v. 2, ed. Paul
Edwards (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1967), pp. 499-505.
[7] Francis
Bacon, The Great Instauration and New Organon
[1620], selections in The English
Philosophers from Bacon to Mill, ed. Edwin
Burtt (N.Y.: Modern Library, 1939), pp. 5-123,
pp. 5-6.
Bacon recommends employment of a form of
eliminative induction (whereas the common form
prior to his recommendation was enumerative
induction).
[8] Ibid.,
p. 16, emphasis added to passage.
[9] ‘Organon’
is from a Greek word meaning “instrument.”
Aristotle's logical writings are
traditionally known as “The Organon,” and in
Bacon and Locke, one uses this word when one is
speaking of an instrument for seeking truth (or
reasonable belief).
[10] Francis
Bacon, The Great Instauration and New Organon
[1620], op. cit., p. 17.
[11] Ibid.,
p. 19.
[12] Above I
noted that it is important to take such labels
with a grain of salt because the differences
between thinkers are as important as the
similarities.
It is also important to note that only
one of the three standard exemplars of this
“school of thought” was English—John Locke.
George Berkeley was Irish, and David Hume
was Scottish.
[13] The
distinction is partially an epistemological
one—a distinction between what is validated or
justified by appeal to experience and what is
not.
As long as a non-empirical procedure of
validation exists, we are confronted with the
a priori.
The distinction is also partially a
metaphysical one.
According to Aristotle, A is prior to B
in nature if and only if B could not exist
without A; A is prior to B in knowledge if and
only if we cannot know B without knowing A—cf.,
Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, Bk. 1.2.
[14] Garrett
Thomson, Descartes to Kant: An Introduction
to Modern Philosophy (Prospect Hill:
Waveland, 1997), p. 110.
[15] Thomas
Grey, “Bad Man from Olympus,” in
The
[16]
Philosophers use single quotes to surround a
word when they are
mentioning it rather than
using
it.
For example, in the sentence “‘Long’ is a short
word,” the word ‘long’ is mentioned (discussed)
while the word ‘short’ is used!
[17]
Cf.,
Frederick Will, “Empiricism,”
Dictionary of Philosophy, ed. Dagobert Runes
(N.Y.: Philosophical Library, 1960), pp. 89-91.
[18] Will
adds several other variant to the list
including: that “the nature of meaning, ideas,
concepts, or universals [is] that they “consist
of” or “are reducible to” references to directly
presented data or content of [sensory]
experience” (ibid.,
p.90).
[19] That is
to say, they tend to conceive of logical truths
as fundamentally linguistic—they are “mere
tautologies” which expose relations amongst
ideas, propositions, or concepts.
[20] Edwin
Curley, “Rationalism,” in
A
Companion to Epistemology, eds. Jonathan
Dancy and Ernest Sosa (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1992), pp. 411-415, p. 414.
[21] Richard
H. Popkin, “Scepticism, Theology and the
Scientific Revolution in the Seventeenth
Century,” in Problems in the Philosophy of
Science, eds. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave
(Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1968), pp. 1-28), p.
5.
[22] Ibid.,
p. 17.
File last revised on 01/05/15.