Copyright © 2015 Bruce W.
Hauptli |
The English Civil War [1642-1646][1]
began when John Locke was ten years old—his father fought in the parliament’s
army. When he was fourteen, Locke
was sent off to school, and when he was twenty he went to Christ’s Church,
In 1667 Locke became the personal physician to the Earl of Shaftesbury
(Lord Ashley), and began a lengthy service and connection with this important
political figure (Locke served as his Secretary and political advisor).
Shaftesbury became Lord Chancellor in 1672 and Locke served as of his
Secretary in charge of ecclesiastical business and, then, as Secretary to the
Council of Trade and Plantations.
About this time, Locke also began collaborations with Thomas Sydenham (a noted
physician of the day), and he was elected to the
Shaftesbury became alienated from King Charles II, and fell from power.[4]
From 1675-1679 Locke traveled to
2. Locke On Innate
Principles and Ideas:
Locke describes his aim in the
Essay Concerning Human Understanding
[1690] as follows:
I i 2 ...to inquire into the
origin, certainty, and extent of human knowledge, together with the grounds and
degrees of belief, opinion, and assent.[5]
Like other Early Modern philosophers, he wishes to give an
account of human knowledge. He
begins his Essay with an attack on
the “doctrine of innate principles and ideas.”
This “doctrine” is at the heart of the continental rationalists’
theories. Standard examples of
innate principles for these thinkers (claims which they hold to be known
a priori, and which are held to be
intellectual intuitions that are held to be
both self-evident and
necessarily true) include: “What
is, is” and
“It is impossible for the same thing to be, and not to be.”
The classic example of an innate idea for them is
the idea of a deity.
A major problem for the continental rationalists is directly evident when
we note the diversity of basic principles or ideas which these theorists
champion, and the radically different conclusions which they draw from “shared”
postulates or ideas. Since they
wished to offer objective theories (which
all rational thinkers would have to accept), their differences at this
fundamental level undercut their claim that these principles and ideas are
innate.
Locke held that there are no
innate principles or ideas.
Indeed, he contends that even if people
universally agreed as to which principles or ideas were innate, there would
be a simpler explanation than the “innateness view”—experience of a common world
could well explain such uniformity in our conceptions.
Locke notes that there are two ways principles or ideas could be taken to
be innate:
Explicitly Innate: |
Implicitly (Virtually) Innate: |
These ideas or
principles are actually “in” us before we have
any experience at all.
|
Experience provides
the “occasion” on which these ideas or
principles manifest themselves in us.
|
He maintains that there is in fact no universal
agreement amongst individuals on either “principles” or “ideas:” consider
idiots, children, and the great proportion of mankind who have never heard of
the various innate principles or ideas which the continental rationalists
champion—individuals who never think of, experience, or contemplate such as
principles as “what is, is,” or “it is impossible for the same thing to be, and
not to be;” individuals who lack the requisite “idea” of a deity.
The fact that many people don’t have the ideas and principles which the
continental rationalists maintain are innate in all human beings means that they
will not be able to hold that these ideas and principles are explicitly innate
in us all.
This means that those who hold the innateness view will have to maintain
that these ideas are implicitly (or
virtually) innate—that they become
explicit only when we have certain experiences or reflections.
Locke maintains that if one assumes that experience is necessary for the
manifestation of the (virtually) innate ideas, however, one might as well
maintain that sense experience itself provides us with these ideas (or with an
account of our knowing such things).
This, of course, is the position his empiricism takes—our
principles and ideas originate in experience (and, hence, they have an
a posteriori, rather than an
a priori, status).
Locke contends that only certain
desires and
cognitive abilities
are “innate” in us—according to him,
our mind has only various powers of reflection, association, and abstraction,
and we naturally (innately) have a desire for happiness and an aversion to
misery. Thus, all our ideas,
thoughts, beliefs, and knowledge arise
from our sensory experience (and these powers, abilities, and desires).
Locke goes on to show how our ideas originate from sensation and
reflection, how language originates, what the different sorts of knowledge are,
and how extensive each sort of knowledge is.
In the process he develops a complex metaphysical theory, and he explains
how skepticism is to be avoided.
Gottfried Leibniz criticizes Locke’s treatment of innate principles and
ideas. In his
Leibniz’s New Essays Concerning Human
Understanding: A Critical Exposition, John Dewey maintains that:
Locke always proceeds by
inquiring into the way and circumstances by which knowledge of the subject under
consideration came into existence and into the conditions by which it was
developed....In the language of our day, Locke’s
Essay is an attempt to settle
ontological questions by a psychological method.
And...Leibniz meets him, not by inquiry into the pertinence of the method
or into the validity of results, so reached, but by the more direct way of
impugning his psychology, by substituting another theory of the nature of mind
and of the way in which it works.[6]
Dewey points to an
important point here regarding the differences between the continental
rationalists and the British Empiricists.
The continental rationalists see the mind as naturally containing certain
fully formulated truths of reason (propositions which are
self-evident, certain, a priori, and
which have ontological implications).
The British Empiricists, on the other hand, hold that truths may be
arrived at only a posteriori, so for
them the mind is a “blank
tablet” until experience has “written upon” it.
Of course, the empiricists can not really believe in an utterly
blank mind—it must have some powers
of memory, abstraction, examination, and inference if it is to be anything but a
passive recipient of sensory experience.
The “debate” regarding innate ideas is perhaps best seen, then, as a
disagreement over
what is innate in the mind.
The rationalists hold that certain [determinate and specific]
ideas are innate, while the
empiricists hold that only certain powers
(those of abstraction, association, and analysis, for example) and
desires (happiness, pleasure,
aversion to pain, etc.) are basic to the mind.
Kant’s insight at the end of the Early Modern period of philosophy is
that “intuitions without concepts are
blind; concepts without intuitions are empty.”[7]
He develops a theory which relies upon elements of both the continental
rationalists’ and British Empiricists’ views.
3. Locke’s “Idea”
of Ideas:
To understand Locke’s “idea” of ideas, we need to note that
he held that the mind is a blank tablet
(that nothing is in the mind unless there has been some experience); and that
the mind has the
power to associate, abstract upon,
and reflect upon the ideas which are provided to it by sensory experience.
He also held that
bodies
have the power to cause ideas of both primary and secondary qualities, and that
the former sort of ideas are resemblances, while those of the latter sort are
not such. Finally, he held that
there is a distinction between simple
and complex ideas. According to
him, simple ideas can come from one sense (coldness, hardness, scent, color);
come from several senses (extension, figure, rest, motion); or come from any of
the sources of sensation or reflection (pleasure, pain).
All simple ideas are passively
received—the mind can not invent them.
The mind may, however, combine these together in complexes (it may make
up complex ideas out of the simples it has
passively received).
The simple ideas, or at least some of them, provide us with
direct representations.
They provide the basis for our knowledge claims.
Where the continental rationalists
rely upon innate ideas, Locke’s empiricism relies upon an appeal to our sensory
experiences, and he claims that there is a relation between some of these
experiences and the world.
4. Locke on Ideas and Knowledge:
There is a big difference between maintaining that sense
experience is the
source of all our knowledge and
maintaining that sense experience is the ultimate
basis for the justification of our knowledge: Locke is
not an empiricist in the latter
sense. Believing that he tries to
be such an empiricist, many hold that he was an inconsistent thinker—on a common
picture of Locke it is held that he would limit us to the ideas that we gain in
experience and would nonetheless speak of our knowledge of substances (a self, a
deity, and physical bodies). Since
he does not claim to have a clear idea of substance (he terms it a “something I
know not what”), however, it seems to such thinkers that he is inconsistent
here.
We must be careful in attributing inconsistency to Locke on this count
however:
whether Locke was being
consistent as an empiricist or not depends upon the kind of empiricist he was
trying to be. Locke’s empiricism
does not include the principle that nothing must figure in our account of the
world unless it has been, or could be, the subject of experience.
He wants to show ‘whence the understanding may get all the
ideas it has’; that it is in
experience that ‘all our knowledge is
founded, and from that it ultimately
derives itself’; and that sensation and reflection together supply ‘our
understandings with all the materials
of thinking.’ This implies that the
understanding is able to work on these materials.
He nowhere appears to be committed to the slogan ‘Nothing in the mind
which was not first in the senses.’
He does not aspire to membership of the Vienna Circle[8]....[his]
is the empiricism of the natural
philosopher and is perfectly respectable if we recognize as Locke clearly did,
that natural philosophy may not give us knowledge, in the strict sense, but may
give us something valuable, namely, probable ‘conjecture’.[9]
Locke believes that while our knowledge (in the strictest
sense of the term) falls short of “all that exists,” it is sufficient for our
purposes.[10]
Here his orientation is significantly different from those of the
continental rationalists—they thought that the new developments in mathematics
and science showed that all of
reality could be rationally grasped.
While Locke believed in the reality of substance, he held
that human understanding could not know
the “real essences” of substances.
According to him, full knowledge and certainty were to be had by limiting
ourselves to claims about the immediate agreement (or disagreement) of our ideas
and he did not think this gave us a full picture of the world.
Nonetheless, Locke held that we could come to form
appropriate
judgments about the world.
According to him, our senses provide us with particular ideas, and the
mind may abstract from these.
As Larry Laudan notes, his abstraction process can yield
judgments that provide us, if not with
knowledge in the strict sense, with
probable knowledge about the world:
we need...[to pay attention to]
Locke’s pivotal distinction between
knowledge and judgment.
Knowledge, for him, is based on a true and infallible intuition of
the relation of ideas.
To know that a statement x is true is to perceive that we could not
conceive things to be other than the state of affairs which x specifies.
In this way we ‘know’ the truth of mathematics.
But we do not ‘know’ anything about the physical world.[11]
For Locke,
knowledge requires the direct
perception of agreement and disagreement amongst ideas, while
judgment is the process “...whereby
the mind takes its ideas to agree or disagree, or which is the same, any
proposition to be true or false, without perceiving a demonstrative evidence in
the proofs.”[12]
Of course we will have to be careful with such passages—he says that “the
mind takes the ideas to agree,” but doesn’t explicitly say
what they are in agreement with!
Locke contends that while judgment
doesn’t provide knowledge in the pure sense of the term, it provides something
almost as good, and it extends the scope of human understanding far beyond what
can be gained if one limits oneself to the immediate agreement and disagreement
of ideas.
As noted above, Locke also distinguished between
primary and secondary qualities
(of bodies)—distinguishing those properties of bodies that are
utterly inseparable from bodies from
those that can be so separated.
Secondary qualities are those powers in bodies to cause ideas in us that don’t
directly reflect actual properties of the bodies (color, taste, etc.).
The ideas we have which are caused by primary qualities, on the other
hand, provide a direct bridge to the
objects in the world themselves. An
example of this distinction would be the “power” in a body to cause in us an
idea of the shape of the body (a primary quality) and the “power” in the same
body to cause in us an idea of the color of the body—while its shape is an
actual property of the body, and our idea of the shape directly represents this
property, the idea of its color does not directly represent a property of the
body (instead, this idea is the result of the body’s action upon
us.
Whatever epistemological problems this distinction raises for Locke, he
was convinced that the new corpuscular natural philosophy required it:
[Robert] Boyle
[1627-1691] was arguing against
explanations of natural phenomena in terms of the real and occult qualities and
substantial forms of the scholastics, the alchemists and others.
He was looking for explanations of as many phenomena as possible in terms
of as few basic concepts as possible, those concepts to be derived as directly
as possible from sense-experience.
Locke, in putting forward an empiricist basis for knowledge, was codifying the
principles of the experimental natural philosophy which Boyle was championing
against speculative natural philosophy.[13]
Thus, Locke held
that the ideas caused by the primary qualities are indeed representations of
things in the world—that is, he held to a representational theory of perception.
Berkeley and Hume accept Locke’s empiricistic principle (that
all of our ideas originate in experience) while attempting to indicate what
aspects of Locke’s epistemology and metaphysics are inconsistent with an
empiricism which speaks not only of the
origins of our empirical knowledge but also of
its justifications or grounds.
[1] Cromwell
led the followers of Parliament to victory over
the Royalists; but there was almost as much
dissension between the army and the Parliament
as there had been amongst the followers of
Parliament and the Royalists.
While much of the country and Parliament
wished to reunite itself with King Charles I and
establish some new form of government with him
at the head, Cromwell and the army did not.
They fought against and conquered the
lot.
The army set up a Parliament to its
liking, tried Charles I, and (on January 30,
1649) executed him.
Cromwell was established as “Lord
Protector.”
Following his death in 1658, Cromwell’s
son served as Lord Protector for one year, and
then a year of anarchy followed.
The Stuart line was then “restored” in
1660 when the son of Charles I (Charles, the
Prince of Wales) was invited to become King of
England (Charles II) and reined until his death
in 1685.
From 1685-1688 his brother, James II
ruled, but his Catholicism aroused Anglican
opposition, and in 1689 William of Orange (a
Protestant prince) and his Wife, Mary (James
II’s daughter) were invited to England to rule.
[2] Much of
the information about Locke's life and
activities which is contained in this section is
taken from James Clapp, “John Locke,” in
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy v. 4, ed. Paul
Edwards (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1967), pp. 487-503.
[3] Robert
Boyle [1627-1691] was instrumental in the
popularization of experimental science and
corpuscular theory against the natural
philosophy of Aristotelian Scholasticism.
His
Skeptical
Chymist was published in 1661.
[4]
Shaftesbury was tried for treason in 1681 and
had to flee to
[5] John
Locke,
Essay Concerning Human Understanding [1690],
abridged and edited by Kenneth Winkler
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996), p. 4.
Citations to the
Essay
are generally indicated by the following device:
Book, Chapter, Section—thus the reference here
would be: to the First Book, Chapter 1, Section
2.
I will use this method of reference throughout
rather than referring to the page numbers of the
text.
[6] John
Dewey, Leibniz’ New Essays Concerning Human
Understanding: A Critical Exposition
[1888].
The citation is from selection reprinted
in From
Plato to Wittgenstein: The Historical
Foundations of the Modern Mind, ed. Daniel
Kolak (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1994), pp. 317-360,
p. 335.
[7] Immanuel
Kant,
Critique of Pure Reason [1781], trans.
Norman Kemp Smith (N.Y.: St. Martins, 1965), A
51/B 75.
[8]
Philosophers of the twentieth century who held
that metaphysics is “meaningless nonsense,” and
that the only meaningful propositions are either
tautologies or empirically testable statements.
[9] Peter
Alexander, “Boyle and Locke on Primary and
Secondary Qualities,” in Locke on Human
Understanding, ed. Ian C. Tipton (Oxford:
Oxford U.P., 1977), pp. 62-76, pp. 74-75.
The essay originally appeared in
Ratio
v. 16 (1974), pp. 51-67.
[10] His
metaphor at I i 6 of the sailor’s fathoming line
being useful even if it can not “fathom” the
depth of the ocean is indicative of his view of
knowledge as an instrument—it is useful even if
it can not wholly reflect or embrace all that
is.
His discussion in I i 7 deepens this view, and
he clearly indicates that we may well be lost if
we attempt to “let loose our thoughts into the
vast ocean of being.”
[11] Larry
Laudan, “The Nature and Sources of Locke’s Views
on Hypothesis,” in Locke On Human
Understanding, ed. Ian Tipton, op. cit.,
pp. 149-162, p. 152.
The essay originally appeared in
Journal of the History of Ideas v. 28
(1967), pp. 211-223.
Emphasis (italics) has been added to the
passage.
[12] Locke,
Essay, op. cit., IV xiv 3.
[13] Peter
Alexander, “Boyle and Locke on Primary and
Secondary Qualities,”
op. cit.,
p. 66.
File last revised on 01/23/15.