Introduction to Dewey’s Philosophy Continued
Dewey’s Theory of
Inquiry:
Dewey’s view of inquiry was heavily influenced by Darwinian
biology. The theory of inquiry
offers an “organic” conception of thought and action—it takes
organic interaction as its basic
notion. That is, it emphasizes the
organism, the
environment,
and the
interaction between them.
According to this theory, this interaction often yields a
tension (either discrete or continuous) which, in turn, leads to
efforts to resolve the tension so as to “return to” an
equilibrium state. The
first step in a thoughtful inquiry process is the
specification of the initial problem.
This is important since the problematic situation is, initially,
indeterminate.
This may be done either by habit
or by thought.
In thoughtful inquiry the
problem is specified, the conditions in the environment are examined in light of
the specified problem, a hypothesis is formed, its consequences are examined,
and, then, the hypothetical action is either undertaken or the process begins
anew.
Human beings, for Dewey, are neither
primarily souls nor are they primarily matter.
Instead, they are creatures of
habit and instinct inhabiting a world
which is neither malevolent nor benevolent.
At times, human habitual ways of functioning are insufficient (they reach
impasses where their habits break down).
At these times human beings pause to consider which way to turn.
Dewey’s instrumentalism holds that mind
or intelligence develops from and is an instrument for problem-solving.
Dewey rejects the “spectator” view of knowledge (which holds that our
knowledge or beliefs are to “mirror” the essential, and unchanging, character of
the world) and believes that our experimental processes are piecemeal
processes—they proceed gradually, and their results are temporary.
Dewey did not offer an exclusive
emphasis upon the “practical” side of our lives however.
He also emphasized the importance of the aesthetic experiences of human
beings. He characterized aesthetic
experience as immediate, individualized, and consummatory or final.
Religious experience for him is an especially intense aesthetic one.
As we shall see his discussion of
consummatory experience is crucial to his project of integrating facts and
values.
Thought and Action:
Like the other pragmatists, Dewey emphasizes the relationship
between thought and action. He
preferred to term his pragmatism an “instrumentalism”
(or “experimentalism”) however.
In his “The Influence of Darwinism on Philosophy,”
The Quest for Certainty, and
Experience and Nature, Dewey
emphasizes how the pragmatic philosophy differs from the classical philosophical
orientations. In the former article
he argues that we can seek knowledge either in something transcendent or in the
mutual interaction of things. The
change from the traditional orientation (which sought knowledge in the
transcendent) to the orientation which Dewey recommends (which seeks knowledge
in the mutual interaction of things) is a change which moves from “purpose” to
“significance” (signs) and it is exemplified by the change in the science of
biology from the teleological orientation of Aristotle to Darwinistic
significance considerations. Dewey
believed that the new (practical or instrumental) procedures of thought should
not be merely confined to our scientific or epistemological thinking.
He maintained that they should characterize our moral, political, and
educational thinking also.
In his “The Development of American
Pragmatism,” Dewey maintains that a central differentiation between
instrumentalism or pragmatism, on the one hand, and traditional empiricism, on
the other, is that the former is forward-looking (looking at “consequent”
phenomena) rather than backward-looking (looking at “antecedent” phenomena).[1]
He goes on to maintain that this shows that pragmatism or instrumentalism
has metaphysical implications:
the doctrine of the value of
consequences leads us to take the future into consideration.
And this taking into consideration of the future takes us to the
conception of a universe whose evolution is not finished, of a universe which is
still, in James’ term, “in the making,” “in the process of becoming,” of a
universe up to a certain point still plastic.[2]
Given that he believes that the traditional philosophical
orientations asked bad questions, Dewey holds that the “reconstruction of
philosophy” which he recommends leads to the disappearance” or “evaporation” of
the old questions.[3]
Dewey and Realism:
Dewey’s instrumentalism and his conception of reality as
plastic diverges significantly from the sort of German Idealism which he adhered
to early in his philosophical career (as he, of course, makes quite clear in his
“From Absolutism to Experimentalism”).
In his “The Realism of Pragmatism” Dewey claims that:
instrumentalism is thus thoroughly
realistic as to the objective of fulfilling conditions of knowledge.
States of consciousness, sensations and ideas as cognitive, exist as
tools, bridges, cues, functions...to affect a realistic presentation of things
in which there are no intervening states of consciousness as veils or
representatives. Known things, as
known, are direct presentations in the most diaphanous medium conceivable.
And if getting knowledge, as distinct from having it, involves
representatives, pragmatism carries with it a reinterpretation, and a realistic
interpretation, of ‘states of consciousness’ as representations.
They are practically or effectively, not transcendentally representative.
They represent in the sense in which a signature, for legal purposes,
represents a real person....They are symbols, in short, and are known and used
as such.[4]
According to Ernest Nagel, “naive realism” (the view that the
world is made up of sheep, clouds, rainbows, and trees), is undercut by
“scientific realism” (the view that reality is made up of atoms, fields, and
forces), but this appears to create a “paradox”:
...naive realism leads to physics,
but if physics is true then naive realism is false.
On this analysis, therefore, one is left with the choice of either
accepting natural science but rejecting as basically illusory the things that
constitute men’s most familiar and valued experience, or accepting the objective
character of common-sense views of things but denying the validity and relevance
of modern science for matters of prime human concern.”[5]
According to Nagel, Dewey resolves this “paradox:”
...the adequacy or validity of ideas
is not warranted by their supposed derivation from materials of sense, but
rather by the consequences of their use….The central thesis of Dewey’s theory of
science is that it does not disclose realms of being antithetical to the
familiar things of life, simply because scientific objects are formulations of
complex relations of dependence between things in sense experience...the
constructions of theoretical physics are viewed
as intellectual means of organizing the discontinuous occurrences of
directly experienced qualities, as ways of thinking about matters in gross
experience in order to obtain some measure of control....[6]
Of course, if Dewey’s experimentalism is committed to realism,
it is not anti-metaphysical. As we
look at his views in greater depth, we will have to look to see whether his
experimentalism (or naturalism, or pragmatism) can consistently offer the sort
of metaphysical theory which he advances.[7]
Dewey’s Theory of Value:
To bring this overly long introduction to an end, I must
briefly expand upon some earlier remarks about Dewey’s theory of value.
As I noted above, Dewey believes that some of our experiences have a
“consummatory” (or aesthetic) character.
Gail Kennedy maintains that after reading James, Dewey developed a
pragmatic (or naturalistic) theory which argued that:
...values and purposes are created
by man in his efforts to “adapt” himself to the world of nature and of society
within which he lives and moves and has his being.
What these values shall be is not predetermined by the appeal to some
antecedent reality or cosmic purpose.
They occur as effects or
products of the conflicts that arise and the choices which are made in the
particular situations of daily life....With man intelligence has reached a level
where he may, within the limits of the forces at his disposal, control the
future. But this is always a
piecemeal control and the ends-in-view of limited human beings must always vary
with the changing situation. Values
are altered as knowledge develops.
A philosophy which accepts this evolutionary definition of intelligence
thus “forswears enquiry after absolute origins and absolute finalities in order
to explore specific values and the specific conditions that generate them.”
If this is the role of philosophy, then method, the method of
intelligence is supreme. Philosophy
must “become a method of locating and interpreting the more serious of the
conflicts that occur in life and a method of projecting ways for dealing with
them: a method of moral and political diagnosis and prognosis.[8]
In short, for Dewey, values are to be subjected to the same
sort of experimental and instrumentalistic analysis as are facts.
Of course, given his view of inquiry, and his “plastic” conception of
reality, he is also committed to the existence of meaningful freedom.
To come to understand Dewey’s theory of value and ethics, however, we
must turn to our readings.
[1] John
Dewey, “The Development of American Pragmatism,”
op. cit.,
pp. 32-33.
[2]
Ibid.,
p. 33.
[3]
Cf.,
John Dewey, “The Influence of Darwinism on
Philosophy,” in
Classic
American Philosophers, ed. Max Fisch, op.
cit., pp. 336-344, p. 344.
Cf.,
also, John Dewey,
Reconstruction in Philosophy (Boston:
Beacon, 1957 [originally published in 1920]).
[4] John
Dewey, “The Realism of Pragmatism,”
The
Journal of Philosophy (1905), pp. 324-327,
p. 325.
[5] Ernest
Nagel, “Dewey’s Theory of Natural Science,” in
John
Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom,
ed. Sidney Hook (York: Dial, 1950), pp. 233-234.
[6]
Ibid.,
p. 236.
[7] In his
“Dewey’s Naturalistic Metaphysics” (The
Journal of Philosophy v. 22 (1905), pp.
673-688), George Santayana maintains that
Dewey’s “metaphysics” is inconsistent with his
“naturalism.”
Richard Rorty offers a similar argument
in his “Dewey’s Metaphysics” (in
New
Studies in the Philosophy of John Dewey, ed.
Steven M. Cahn (Hanover: University of Vermont,
1977), pp. 45-69).
[8] Gail
Kennedy, “Introduction” to the Dewey chapter, in
Classic
American Philosophers, ed. Max Fisch,
op. cit.,
p. 333.
Kennedy cites Dewey’s “The Influence of
Darwin On Philosophy,”
op. cit.,
p. 341.
File revised on 10/15/2014