Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
I. Kant’s Life:
Almost every account of Kant’s life characterizes it as
“uneventful.” Here is the first
paragraph from Frederick Copleston’s account:
if we prescind from the history
of his intellectual development and from the results of this development, we do
not need to spend much time in recounting the facts of Kant’s life.
For it was singularly uneventful and devoid of dramatic incident.
True, any philosopher’s life is devoted primarily to reflection, not to
external activity on the stage of public life.
He is not a commander in the field or an Arctic explorer.
And unless he is forced to drink poison like Socrates or burned at the
stake like Giordano Bruno, his life naturally tends to be undramatic.
But Kant was not even a traveled man of the world like Leibniz.
For he spent all his life in East Prussia.
Nor did he occupy the position of a philosophical dictator in the
university of a capital city, as Hegel later did at Berlin.
He was simply an excellent professor in a not very distinguished
university of a provincial town.
Nor was his character such as to provide a happy hunting-ground for
psychological analysts, as with Kierkegaard and Nietzsche.
In his later years he was noted for his methodical regularity of life and
for his punctuality, but it would hardly occur to anyone to think of him as an
abnormal personality. But perhaps
one can say that the contrast between his quiet and comparatively uneventful
life and the greatness of his influence has itself a dramatic quality.[1]
I think this is too dismissive, but it is fairly
typical—philosophers regularly turn almost directly to Kant’s thought rather
than talking about his life.
Kant lived from 1724-1804 and was one of the major figures of the
Enlightenment. He was born in
Koenigsberg in East Prussia (his father made saddles and his mother was
unschooled). His parents were
German Pietists (belonging to a branch of the Lutheran Church which emphasized
religion as an inner experience to be expressed outwardly in a simple life led
in obedience to moral commands or laws).
The local pastor made it possible for Immanuel to attend the local
Pietist school at the age of eight.
When he was sixteen, Kant enrolled at the University of Koenigsberg
intending to study theology, but a philosophy professor, Martin Knutzen,
strongly influenced him to study Christian Wolff, Isaac Newton, and current
philosophy and science. Kant
intended to pursue an academic career, but the death of his father required that
he give up the life of a student.
He became a tutor, and for nine years taught the children of several different
influential families in Koenigsberg.
According to the Encyclopedia
Britannica, during this time
he was introduced to the
influential society of the city, acquired social grace, and made his farthest
travels from his native city—some 60 miles (96 kilometers) away to the town of
Arnsdorf. In 1755, aided by the
kindness of a friend, he was able to complete his degree at the university and
take up the position of Privatdozent, or lecturer.[2]
Kant was a popular and successful lecturer, and he lectured on a wide
variety of topics (among them physics, mathematics, philosophy, fireworks,
fortifications, and physical geography).
When Knutzen died, Kant tried to obtain an appointment to his chair, but
Knutzen’s position was that of an “extraordinary professor,” and the government
chose to leave the position vacant (to save money).
Kant’s financial situation was strained for the fifteen years he served
as a lecturer (though during the last four years of this position he also was an
assistant librarian, and this position provided his some additional income).
In 1770 he became [an “Ordinary”] Professor of Logic and Metaphysics at
the University of Koenigsberg (he had earlier been offered a chair in poetry
both at Koenigsberg and at Jena].
The fifteen years prior to this appointment are often referred to as his
“pre-critical” period, while his early period as a Professor are referred to as
his “critical” one. This
designation refers not to the fact that for fifteen years he did not engage in
any critical thought, but, rather, to the fact that his main works published as
a professor were called his First,
Second, and Third Critiques.
While one can not really date the change in his thinking, throughout a
substantial portion of the time he was a lecturer he had largely thought within
the Leibnizian-Wolffian philosophical world-view.
For a substantial period of time (certainly while he was Professor, but
most likely beginning before this point), Kant began to develop his
own distinctive philosophical system.
In 1781 his first critique, The
Critique of Pure Reason was published, and it was quickly followed by his
other best known works: Prolegomena to
any Future Metaphysics [1783],
Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals [1785],
Metaphysical First Principles of Natural
Science [1786], The Critique of
Practical Reason [1788], The Critique
of Judgment [1790], Religion Within
the Bounds of Reason Alone [1793], and
Metaphysics of Morals [1797].
This is a prodigious intellectual output, and Copleston offers the
following description of his life at this time:
it is understandable,
therefore, that with this heavy programme Kant had to husband his time.
And his order of the day, to which he faithfully adhered during his years
as a professor, has become famous.
Rising shortly before five in the morning, he spent the hour from five to six
drinking tea, smoking a pipe, and thinking over his day’s work.
From six to seven he prepared his lecture, which began at seven or eight,
according to the time of the year, and lasted until nine or ten.
He then devoted himself to writing until the midday meal, at which time
he always had company and which was prolonged for several hours, as Kant enjoyed
conversation. Afterwards he took a
daily walk of an hour or so, and the evening was given to reading and
reflection. He retired to bed at
ten o’clock.[3]
While Kant is treated as a paradigmatic figure in the Enlightenment, and
while we will see that he emphasized the importance of a life lived according to
the dictates of reason (and while he, surely, lived such a life), it is
important to note that his life was not spent in one of the most free of
societies. During the reign of
Frederick the Great, there was little censorship, but this was not the case when
Frederick William II came to rule.
As Mary Gregor notes,
in 1788 Barron von Zedlitz—to
whom Kant had dedicated the Critique of
Pure Reason—was dismissed, and the
notorious Woellner was appointed Minister of Justice and head of the state
departments of church and schools.
Together, the King, his favorite minister, and a coterie of likeminded officials
they gathered around them launched a campaign to “stamp out the Enlightenment.”
Six days after his appointment, Woellner’s Edict on Religion paid lip
service to freedom of conscience while effectively silencing any criticism of
orthodox ecclesiastical tenets....[4]
Gregor continues by noting that
Kant was not looking for trouble
when he wrote Religion Within the Limits
of Mere Reason Alone, though he might reasonably have expected it.[5]
This is a bit ironic given that Kant’s view of the power of
reason holds that it is incapable of comprehending the deity.
Indeed
...after the second
Critique had been published, some of
Kant’s friends feared that his denial of reason’s ability to achieve knowledge
of the supersensible [e.g., the existence, or nature of a deity] might be
claimed by the fanatics in Berlin as support for their insistence on blind faith
in matters of religion.[6]
As Gregor notes, Kant did encounter difficulties with his
views on religion, however:
in 1791 Kant sent the manuscript
of Religion [Within
the Limits of Mere Reason Alone] to Biester, editor of
Berliner Monatsschrift, who planned to publish its
four sections in four consecutive issues of his journal.
The first section was submitted to the censor, received the imprimatur,
and was published in the April 1792 issue.
As for the fate of the remaining three sections, we can best quote Kant’s
account of the affair….
“The first part, “On the Radical Evil in Human Nature,” went all right:
the censor of philosophy, Herr Privy Counselor Hillmer, took it as falling under
his department’s jurisdiction. The
second part was not so fortunate, since Herr Hillmer thought it ventured into
the area of biblical theology (for some unknown reason he thought the first part
did not), and he therefore thought it advisable to confer with the biblical
censor, Oberkonsistorarah Hermes, who then of course took it
as falling under his own jurisdiction (when did a mere priest ever decline any
power?), and so he expropriated it and refused to approve it.”
Biester twice appealed the
decision, once to the Censorship Commission and once directly to the King.[7]
On October 12, 1794 Kant wrote Frederick William II
responding to the King’s demand that he “give a conscientious account of himself
for having misused his philosophy to distort and disparage many of the cardinal
and basic teachings of the Holy Scriptures” in his
Religion Within the Limits of Mere Reason.
In that letter Kant promised that:
regarding the second point—not to be
guilty in the future of (as I am charged) distorting and disparaging
Christianity—I believe the surest way, which will obviate the least suspicion,
is for me to declare solemnly, as Your
Majesty’s most loyal subject, that I will hereafter refrain altogether from
discoursing publicly, in lectures or writings, on religion, whether natural or
revealed.[8]
Kant wrote his
Conflict of the Faculties (especially the part entitled “The Conflict of the
Philosophy Faculty with the Theology Faculty”) to defend both academic freedom
and to argue that the theological faculties and the clergy had usurped authority
that properly belongs to others, and upon Frederick William II’s death in 1797
he felt released from his promise, and he published this work.
I have spent so much space on this incident because it draws our
attention to the social background of Kant’s time, emphasizes the importance and
controversial character of his views regarding religion, and, finally, because
it helps undercut the general view of Kant’s life reflected in the initial
citation above.
As a final note, according to Jostein Gaarder:
one of his most quoted
sayings is carved on his gravestone in Konigsberg: “Two things fill my mind with
ever-increasing wonder and awe, the more often and more intensely the reflection
dwells on them: the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me.”[9]
II. Introduction to
Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals [1785]
Kant was a
rationalist and an objectivist
(many would say “absolutist” here).
As an objectivist, he is interested in coming up with the “supreme principle” of
morality. As a beginning
introductory point regarding Kant’s ethics, note that we often ask individuals
who are contemplating (or doing) acts we disapprove of: “What if everyone did
that?” At times, we are pointing
out the “anti-utilitarian” consequences of the act as an example to others.
At other times, however, we are not making a utilitarian observation
about the consequences of such action.
Instead, we are claiming that the act is
wrong because
neither the agent nor ourselves would
want others to act this way; and if we don’t want the agent to act in this
manner, we have good reason not to allow ourselves to so act.
This brings out three central aspects of Kant’s moral theory: “universalizability,”
reason (or rationality), and
the [absolute]
value of persons.
Kant maintains we are rational and
passionate animals. That is he
believes our wills are capable of being determined by both our reason and by our
passions. To understand his moral
theory, we need to ask, first, “Why do
we have reason?”
Survival or happiness?
He contends that instinct would serve these ends better!
To know the world?
This would explain speculative
reason! Speculative reason
deals with knowledge detached from any consideration of action, while
practical reason deals with reason
as it relates to action.
To direct the will?
This would explain practical
reason. Practical reason
deals with the relationship between reason and will and it is here that the
problems of morality arise according to him.
For David Hume [1711-1776] there was no relationship between reason and
will without an input from the passions.
He held that reason “is, and ever ought to be, the servant of the
passions.”[10]
Kant agrees that it is often true that the input of the passions is
necessary to determine the will, but he maintains
that in the case of morality we are
talking about actions which are not undertaken to achieve some end but, rather,
because of our rational assessment of our duty.
For Kant, it is duty and not consequences which are of fundamental
importance in morality.
To understand Kant’s moral theory, clearly, we have to ask: “What
is a will?” He claims that it
is a human faculty which engenders action (the “seat” of action and activity).
For Kant, in fact, it is our will and our reason which make us what we
are. Kant wants to find out
what makes a will good—he maintains
that such a will (a good one) is the only thing which is intrinsically valuable:
285 Nothing can possibly be conceived in the
world, or even out of it, which can be called good, without qualification,
except a good will.[11]
285-286 Even if it should happen
that, owing to some special disfavor of fortune, or the niggardly provision of a
step-motherly nature, this should wholly lack power to accomplish its purpose,
if with its greatest efforts it should yet achieve nothing, and here should
remain only the good will…then, like a jewel, it would still shine by its own
light, as a thing which has its whole value in itself.
Its usefulness or fruitfulness can neither add nor take away anything
from this value.
According to Kant, moral problems arise because we are not
necessitated
to do our duty—as he would put it, we
are not subjectively necessitated to
do what is objectively necessary
(our duty).
Note
how different this account is from the Christian one (sinfulness), or the
Hobbesian one (failures of rationality and egoism).
In short, for Kant the
inclinations may dictate to the will—just as our reason can.
According to him, while our passions often direct our actions, there is
a class of actions (the moral ones) where
reason must lead, guide, or rule the passions.
Thus, for him, duty is to be strongly contrasted with inclination—a
grocer may be inclined to give the correct change to customers because doing so
is good business, but the grocer will be moral only if the grocer gives the
correct change because it is the her
or his duty.
Here it is appropriate to note the title of the work we will be examining
(Foundations for the Metaphysics for
Morals). The title is
important—he is going to show the “groundwork” of the metaphysical foundations
of morals! He doesn’t believe that
this work does a full job of laying the groundwork, but it does sketch out what
the metaphysical presuppositions of morality are, and we have just touched on
several of the essential presuppositions:
the fact that we are not
subjectively necessitated to do what is objectively necessary (normally this is
called “freedom of the will”); and
the role of reason in determining
what the will should “will” (the view that
the objective moral laws are rational and
knowable).
When the will is determined by reason, according to Kant, there is a
maxim behind the action—a rule which
describes the reasoning which determines the will.
Kant maintains that when the will is motivated by appropriate maxims, it
is a good will. That is, he
maintains that we judge the moral worth
of a will independently of the consequences of its willing—in fact,
consideration of the consequences of our actions is irrelevant on his view.
In short, Kant’s moral theory is
deontological rather than
teleological:
[12]
As Pojman notes, “whereas
teleological systems...place the ultimate criterion of morality in some nonmoral
value (for example, happiness) that results from acts, deontological systems
assert that certain features in the act itself have intrinsic value.”[13]
Kant warns against what he calls the “serpent-windings of
utilitarianism”[14]
which require that we treat people as means and pay attention to consequences.
For him, what is important is our acting from duty, and he holds to this
rigorously: “even if civil society resolved to dissolve itself with the consent
of all its members—as might be supposed in the case of a people inhabiting an
island resolving to separate and scatter themselves throughout the whole
world—the last murderer lying in the prison ought to be executed before the
resolution was carried out. This
ought to be done in order that every one may realize the desert of his deeds,
and that bloodguiltiness may not remain upon the people; for otherwise they
might all be regarded as participators in the murder as a public violation of
justice.”[15]
As we shall see, Kant is
unrelenting in his demands that we adhere to our duties.
As noted above, Kant’s question for the practical [moral] philosopher is:
“What motivates the will—what makes it
good? He maintains that the
good will (1) knows its duty and (2)
does the dutiful act
because it is
dutiful.
What makes a person praiseworthy is not what she or he achieves, but
rather whether she or he acts [solely]
from regard (or “reverence”) for duty.
To see whether an act is praiseworthy we look not at its consequences but
rather at the question of motivation, and we judge it praiseworthy only if the
motivation is one of duty. Notice
that we make a distinction between murder1, murder2,
murder3, and justifiable homicide; and the distinction is
not drawn from a consideration of
consequences.[16]
For
Kant, we need to distinguish:
actions done
from (or
because of) the moral law,
from
actions which are (merely)
in accord with the moral law.
Kant does not praise the latter.
For him, to be praiseworthy, one’s actions must be the result of a will
which is motivated [solely] by respect for the [rational] law.
What, then,
does reason dictate to us?
Kant distinguishes rational maxims (or imperatives) which guide our
action into two classes:
categorical and
hypothetical imperatives.
According to Kant, the tests of moral [categorical] maxims
are rational tests:
we must consider
consistency and noncontradiction,
we must consider
universalizability,
we must consider
respect for rational beings,
we must consider
respect (or “reverence”)
for rationality itself.
The dominant classical moral
theories were teleological.
With the spread of Christianity, however, the notion of
obligation or
duty came more to the cultural
foreground in the West—the correct act was seen to be the one which was
done because it was the law of the deity.
Like such Christians, Kant holds that the correct act is the one done
from an awareness of, and out of a respect for, the law.
But this raises the question of the law-giver, and unlike such
Christians, Kant does not ground morality
in a deity (though he talks a lot about one).
Instead, he maintains that it is [pure
a priori]
reason which
tells us what our duty is.
Here, of course, he is a characteristic (some would say “the
prototypical”) Enlightenment thinker.
Throughout this work Kant uses four cases to illustrate what reason tells
us:
a. First example (a perfect duty[17]
to oneself): refraining from committing suicide.
b. Second example (a perfect duty
to others): giving a lying promise.
c. Third example
(imperfect duty to oneself): the neglect of natural talents.
d. Fourth example
(imperfect duty to others): the duty to help others who are in distress.
These four examples are discussed in the context of three
different formulations of Kant’s
categorical imperative:[18]
1. Universalize the maxim
à
consistency—the first treatment of the four cases argues that our maxims
must be consistently willable.
2. Treat people as ends not as
means only
à
end-in-itself—the second treatment of the four cases argues that
we must not act so as to treat people as
means only.
3. Will and follow the law
autonomously
à
autonomy—the third formulation of the categorical imperative sees every will as
a universally legislative will.
A will which contained on the rational component (one unmoved by
inclinations) would be what Kant calls a “holy
will.” It would always do its duty.
For it there would be no imperatives because what is objectively
necessary would also be subjectively necessary!
According to Kant,
a categorical imperative is possible only if there is something which
commands
absolute obedience—that is some
imperative which is not as a hypothetical
imperative! For him, this
categorical imperative is
respect (or “reverence”)
for reason:
that is, each of us regards our
“self” as an end and not as a
mere means—and what’s true of one is true
of all. According to Kant,
“rational nature exists as an end-in-itself.”
That is, it is never right to treat a person (rational creature)
merely as a means.
-301 “…man and generally any
rational being exists as an end it himself, not merely as a means to be
arbitrarily used by this or that will;, but in all his actions, whether they
concern himself or other rational beings, must be always regarded at the same
time as an end. All objects of the
inclinations have only conditional worth….
-“…that which is necessarily an
end for everyone because it is an end in itself, constitutes an objective
principle of will, and can therefore serve as a universal practical law.
The foundation of this principle is: rational nature exists as an end in
itself. Man necessarily conceives
his own existence as being so; so far then this is a subjective principle of
human actions. But every other
rational being regards its existence similarly, just on the same rational
principle that holds for me: so that it is at the same time an objective
principle, from which as a supreme practical law all laws of the will must be
capable of being deduced.
Accordingly the practical imperative will be as follows:
So act as to treat humanity, whether in
your own person or in that of any other, in every instance as an end withal,
never as a means only.”
Ultimately, for Kant, all talk of morality involves talk of an
autonomous will and its duty:
morality and
self-imposed laws which are universal.
According to Kant,
stones, dogs, and men are all subject to universal laws.
But a will which acts on principle
is subject to laws in a different sense from a stone or dog.
Morality, for Kant, requires an
autonomous will which follows self-imposed principles—or maxims.
These are dictated by one’s reason!
The contrast here is to
heteronomous wills which are subject to externally dictated laws.
Of course, the idea of autonomous wills requires the notion
of [metaphysical] freedom—we must be
free to follow the dictates of reason and, thus, freedom is a
necessary [metaphysical] postulate of
practical reason. According to
Kant, morality is possible only on this postulate.
Moreover, he argues, since we do make moral judgments, we may conclude
that we are free!
But, one may ask, “How can Kant
legitimately conceive of us as free?”
Can we know that we are
[metaphysically] free? Kant offers
a qualified “No.”
This brings us to his famous distinction between
noumena and
phenomena:
introduce the distinction by
distinguishing between observable phenomena and underlying atomic structure,
then clarify by Kant’s view that physical/empirical experience is always
conditioned by “the categories” (such as space and time).
Can we make any justified
knowledge claims about noumena?
Well, according to Kant, all of our knowledge claims are, really, about
phenomena.
In regard to the noumena [things-in-themselves], however, we may make
assumptions and, according to Kant,
these assumptions may be justified
transcendentally:
In his “Royce: The
Absolute and the Beloved Community Revisited,” John E. Smith maintains that “the
quest for the conditions which make the actual possible is the task of
transcendental philosophy. This
reflective enterprise is novel in that it cannot be carried out on the basis of
either of the two classical forms of thought: deduction, and induction or
probable inference.”[19]
-Consider a black-box
experiment in science (or an unknown element experiment).
If these results are observed, we may justifiably conclude that the
original has such and such characteristics—as long as we have antecedently
determined that the original could have such characteristics.
For Kant, transcendental arguments establish the truth of a
class of
synthetic
a priori propositions.
These propositions are characterized by “transcendental”
(rather than “logical”)
necessity—that is to say, if we are to have the character, experience,
and knowledge that we do, these propositions and judgments must be necessary
though their denials are not
contradictions. This class of
propositions is, according to many, odd.
Shouldn’t all propositions be
either a priori or
synthetic—but
not both? Kant doesn’t agree.
He holds that some propositions are
both a priori and synthetic.
The distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions is best made
in terms of an alleged connection between
meaning and truth: analytic propositions are supposed to be such that when
one understands their meaning, one sees that they
must be true—they are
not ampliative (they do not present
any new information)—and they are characterized by
necessity and
universality. Note that we can not
simply say that the “analytic” is simply a function of meaning however—it is a
mistake to consider analytic propositions as merely “definitional” truths.
Definitions are about words
and the analytic propositions are taken to be about
things: “All bodies are extended
things” as an analytic truth is not to be taken as a truth about `bodies’ and
`extended things’ but, rather, about bodies and extended things!
Kant distinguishes between analytic and synthetic propositions first by
asking whether the concept of the predicate is “contained in” the concept of the
subject;” and, secondly, by asking whether the denial of the judgment involves a
contradiction. He also maintains
that all analytic judgments are a priori
ones (since their truth may be ascertained by considering concepts only and not
by appealing to experience). For
him, synthetic judgments are to be ampliative (or informative)—they tell us
something about the subject by connecting or “synthesizing” two different
concepts under which the subject is subsumed.
Analytic judgments are not informative—they simply elucidate or analyze
the concept under which the subject falls.
The synthetic a priori
propositions, of course are “synthetic,” and, thus, their denials aren’t
contradictions and the “predicate” is not “contained in” the “subject.”
Nonetheless, they can not be established by appeal to our experience—they
are a priori.
Consider, for example “Everything which happens has a cause.”
This is universal and necessary, but the predicate (“having a cause”) is
not “contained in” the subject (“an event”).
Consider, also “everything in space is in time” and “the world has a
beginning.” For Kant, these truths can
not be proved a posteriori, they are
metaphysical claims which extend our understanding, and their denials are not
logical contradictions. their necessity, then, can only be established
“transcendentally.” While there is
much more to be said on this subject, I will confine our attention to here to
the status of the Categorical Imperative.
For Kant, the Categorical
Imperative is a synthetic a priori
truth—it can not be established empirically, yet its denial is not a logical
contradiction. It is
informative,
universal,
necessary, and
true.
According to him it is requisite if we are to conceive of ourselves as
free, rational, autonomous agents, and we can not but think of ourselves as
such.
Thus for him,
freedom (and, in addition,
a deity and
immortality) are the assumptions
which are necessary postulates for the
existence of practical reason.
Morality, then, is possible only if we do make judgments and, thus, are
free.
To understand this, however, we need to turn to the readings.
(end)
[1] Frederick
Copleston,
A History
of Philosophy v. 6 [1960] (N.Y.: Image,
1994), p. 180.
Even Copleston recognizes that his
account is too minimalistic here—see his account
of the reaction of Frederick William II to
Kant's
Religion Within The Bounds of Reason Alone
(pp. 183 ff.).
[2] "Immanuel
Kant," Encyclopedia Britannica Online,
http://www.eb.com:180/bol/topic?eu=114813&sctn=3,
accessed 22 February 2001.
[3] Frederick
Copleston,
A History
of Philosophy v. 6,
op. cit.,
p. 183.
[4] Marry J.
Gregor, "Translator's Introduction" to
The
Conflict of the Faculties [1798] by Immanuel
Kant, trans. Mary J. Gregor (N.Y.: Abaris,
1979), pp. vii-xxix, p. ix.
[5]
Ibid.,
p. ix.
[6]
Ibid.,
p. xii.
[7]
Ibid.,
p. xiv.
[8] Immanuel
Kant to Frederick William II, reprinted in
The
Conflict of the Faculties, op. cit., pp.
13-19, p. 19.
[9] Jostein
Gaarder,
Sophie's World: A Novel About the History of
Philosophy, trans. Paulette Moller (N.Y.:
Farr, Straus and Giroux, 1994), p. 259.
[10] David
Hume, A
Treatise of Human Nature [1739], ed. L.A.
Shelby-Biggie [1888] (second edition), revised
by P.H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford U.P., 1978), p.
455.
The passage is reprinted in the selection
from Hume in
Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings
(sixth edition), eds. Louis Pojman and James
Fieser (Belmont: Wadsworth, 2011), p. 501.
[11] Immanuel
Kant, Foundations
for the Metaphysic of Morals [1785], trans.
T.K. Abbott.
The citation is from the selection in
Ethical
Theory: Classic and Contemporary Readings
(sixth edition), ed. Louis Pojman and James
Fieser (Belmont: Wadsworth, 2011), pp., 282-319.
All further citations to this work are to
this selection and the page references are
included with the citations.
[12] In
ethical theory a
deontological theory is very unlike a
teleological one, it “...does not regard
principles of duty or obligation as owing their
status to the fact that acting in the way they
prescribe tends to realize certain desirable
states of affairs, whereas a teleological
theory...holds that this is what renders a
principle of obligation acceptable” (William
Alston, “Concepts of Epistemic Justification"
[1985], in
his
Epistemic Justification (Ithaca: Cornell
U.P., 1989), p. 15.
Cf.
his “The Deontological Conception of Epistemic
Justification” [1988] p.115 in the same volume).
In
teleological ethical systems, ends are taken
as fundamental, and norms or imperatives are
derivative from them; while in deontological
systems norms or imperatives are taken as
fundamental.
[13] Louis
Pojman, “Kantian and Deontological Systems,” in
Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings,
op. cit.,
pp. 276-280, p. 276.
[14]
Cf.,
Kant’s
The Philosophy of Law
[1797], as cited in James
Rachels,
The Right Thing to Do (New York: Random
House, 1989), p. 234.
[15]
Ibid.,
p. 235.
[16] Murder1
is premeditated murder (and murder committed
during certain felonies), while murder2
is unpremeditated, but intentional, murder.
Murder3 is murder committed
during certain more minor felonies.
Voluntary manslaughter arises where one
intends to hurt but not kill, and
involuntary manslaughter is unintended
killing.
[17] As Fred
Feldman points out in his
Introductory Ethics, “by ‘perfect duty,’
Kant says he means a duty ‘which admits of no
exception in the interests of inclination’....On
the other hand, if a person has an imperfect
duty to do a kind of action, then he must at
least
sometimes perform an action of that kind
when the opportunity arises” (Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice-Hall, 1978), p. 106.
This work is available on Reserve in the
Green Library.
[18] There
are three versions (or formulations) in the
work, but only two are presented in our reading
selection.
I will discuss the third in this
supplement as a background understanding of it
helps place Kant’s overall view in a clearer
perspective.
[19] John E.
Smith, “Royce: The Absolute and the Beloved
Community Revisited” [1982] in Smith’s
America's Philosophical Vision (Chicago:
Univ. of Chicago, 1992), pp. 121-137, p. 126.
The essay originally appeared in
Boston
Studies in Philosophy and Religion, ed.
Leroy S. Rouner (Notre Dame: Univ. of Notre
Dame, 1982).
File revised on: 09/28/2013.