Lecture Supplement Introducing Mill’s
Utilitarianism [1863]
Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
I. Mill’s Life:
John Stuart Mill [1806-1873] was educated by his father,
James Mill, at home. James Mill
[1773-1836] was a Scottish philosopher, historian, and economist.
With the help of his patron, Sir James Stuart, the elder Mill attended
Edinburgh University and studied philosophy.
He moved to London in 1802 and earned his living initially as a
free-lance journalist. His
three-volume History of India [1817] was very well-received, and he earned a
post in the British East India Company.
His office and employment made it impossible for him to continue some of
the active (radical) political action he had pursued as a writer, but his
influence in the growing utilitarian movement was significant.
He was a good friend and disciple of Jeremy Bentham [1748-1832], and
other “philosophical radicals” of the day including the economist David Ricardo,
the politicians Jospeh Hume and John Black, and the jurist John Austin.
John Stuart Mill was taught Greek, Latin, geometry,
algebra, logic, history, and political economy by his father.
His father was a strict disciplinarian and had high expectations for him.
D.H. Monro says that:
the education that [James] Mill gave his eldest son was rigorously intellectual. According to John Stuart Mill’s Autobiography, he was made to learn Greek at the age of three, and by the time of eight he had read, among other authors, “the whole of Herodotus” and six dialogues of Plato, including the Theaetetus....
Mine was not an
education of cram. My father never
permitted anything which I learnt to degenerate into a mere exercise of memory.
He strove to make the understanding not only go along with every step of
the teaching, but, if possible, precede it.
Anything that could be found out by thinking, I never was told, until I
had exhausted my efforts to find it out for myself.[1]
When John Stuart was fourteen he went to France for a year.
During this period he continued his studies, and broadened his concerns
to include psychology and law. While
he considered a career in law, in 1823 he became a clerk for the British East
India Company. He held positions of
increasing importance with the company until the 1850s when the company was
dissolved.
In the early 1820s, Mill began to be regular contributor to
a number of newspapers and magazines—he began what was to be a life-long career
as a liberal (radical) public intellectual.
He wrote on political, philosophical, and economic topics taking activist
positions. While Mill’s publications
are not always noted for their philosophic depth, it is clear that he had a
significant effect upon society, and that his thought was also influential upon
subsequent thinkers. During this
time began attending the London Debating Society, and there he encountered other
forceful thinkers who helped broaden his perspective on political philosophy and
other issues. In 1826 he had a
period of deep depression, but the poetry of Wordsworth provided an emotional
cure which helped offset the largely analytical education which he had received
from his father.
Mill was introduced to Harriet Hardy, the wife of a
successful businessman in 1831, and they had what sources call a “deep Platonic
love” for twenty years. Her husband
died in 1849, and in 1851 they were married.
Sources differ on how deeply she influenced his thinking, but Mill
indicates that she deeply influenced his view of the ideals of life (both for
individuals and for society).
Mill studied logic and the philosophy of science
extensively, and his System of Logic
[1843] is a landmark in the movement to develop an inductive logic for the
sciences (in contrast to the deductive logic which had been the abstract model
throughout the Western tradition).
Mill also became well-known for his essays on political economy during the
1840s—his Principles of Political Economy
which was published in 1848.
When the British East India Company was dissolved, Mill
retired with a considerable pension.
His wife Harriet died while they were touring France, and Mill bought a home in
Avignon so he could live near her grave.
He spent the substantial portion of the remainder of his life there
writing on ethics and politics.
During this period he composed On Liberty
[1859], Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform
[1859], Considerations on Representative
Government [1861], Utilitarianism
[1861, 1863], Examination of Sir William
Hamilton’s Philosophy [1865], and
Auguste Comte and Positivism [1865]
In 1865 he stood for election to Parliament.
True to his principles, he refused to campaign, and indicated that if
elected he would not act in the manner of a normal politician (working for the
benefit solely of his constituents).
He was elected, and played an active reformist role (for example, he worked
against corruption, for land reform in Ireland, and for the representation of
women). Mill was defeated in the
next election (1868)—his championing of radical and reformist causes was his
political undoing. He was not at all
upset by this, however.
He continued to write essays, and became a champion of
women’s suffrage—his The Subjection of
Women was published in 1869.
Mill died in Avignon in 1873.
II. Introduction to
Mill’s Moral Thought:
1. Hedonism and
Utilitarianism:
Jeremy Bentham held that pleasure is the
only thing which is
intrinsically worthwhile (hedonism).
You can read an excerpt from his An
Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation [1789] in our text.
According to D.H. Monro:
what Bentham was saying is that the central fact of human
psychology is that men have desires and seek to gratify them.
It follows, he thought, that the only rational way to judge between the
alternative courses of action is to choose the one which gratifies the most
desires. This is scarcely trivial,
since many moralists have held that the gratification of desire is sinful, and
that virtue consists in repressing desires.
Bentham’s central contention was that
gratification as such is always good,
and that, while it may often be necessary to suppress some desires, this is only
in order that other desires may be gratified.
The opposition between duty and
desire is a false one: the real contrast is between conflicting inclinations,
and is settled by considering which...leads to the greatest pleasure.[2]
That is:
people have desires
they seek gratification
gratification is always good
where there are alternative choices, men repress desires only
in order to fulfill others.
This view has obvious similarities to ethical egoism.
Before we look at the differences between egoism and utilitarianism,
however, we should ask: “Are there other things which
are intrinsically valuable (justice, virtue, honor, freedom, etc.)?”
In his “The Real and Alleged Problems of Utilitarianism,” Richard Brandt
maintains that:
...the utilitarian says we are to identify right action by
appeal to maximizing net benefit or utility, but he leaves the definition of
these terms open. Indeed, one can
say: we should maximize what is intrinsically good, and go on to say, as “ideal
utilitarians” like Moore and Rashdall did, that various states of affairs quite
different from pleasure are intrinsically good—say, knowledge, virtue, and
friendship. One could then say, as
these ideal utilitarians did, that the right action is fixed by maximizing the
intrinsically good, and then propose that one can make justified comparative
judgments about the intrinsic worth of knowledge, virtue, and the like so as to
determine, roughly, when the good is being maximized.[3]
Mill, however, thinks that all of these things are
part of happiness, which is what he
holds utilitarianism should maximize, and which he largely equates with
pleasure.
2. Consequentialism
and Teleology:
For Mill it is the
consequences of our actions, and not our
motives which are important.
Here we must also distinguish between the valuation of the act and the
evaluation of the agent. His view is
teleological rather than
deontological (that is, rather than focusing on our
duties, he would focus on our
goals and purposes).
3. The Greatest
Happiness Principle:[4]
Read and discuss passage on p. 200![5]
Utilitarianism is not
egoistic. For utilitarians, the
principle calls for promoting the
greatest happiness for the greatest number:
205 “...the happiness which forms the utilitarian standard
of what is right in conduct is not the agent’s own happiness but that of all
concerned. As between his own
happiness and that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly
impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator.”[6]
Again, however, we must be careful. It isn’t simply the
greatest number of happy people, but the greatest overall utility which is to be
maximized here.
For Mill, it is not simply the promotion of pleasure.
This is too simplistic.
Sometimes we must settle for the “lesser of two evils.”
The Greatest Happiness Principle recommends an act if there
is no other act available to the agent which produces a higher
utility:
the utility of an act will be the sum of the pleasures and
pains which result from the act.
Several acts might have equally high utility and there might
be no act with a higher utility. As
Feldman notes, “...consider this example.
A man has one piece of unbreakable candy.
He can give it to either of the twin daughters....If he gives it to Jean,
she will feel 5 hedons of pleasure, and if he gives it to Joan, she will feel 5
hedons of pleasure. In neither case
will anyone feel any pain. A third
alternative would be to give the candy to neither twin, but that would produce
no pleasure at all.”[7]
If we are to adhere to the Greatest Happiness Principle we
need a “Hedonistic Calculus” which
allows us to rank the “utility” of different acts.
For such a calculus we must consider many factors according to Bentham:
195 intensity, duration, certainty, nearness (in time), extent
(number of people affected), the chance of being followed in kind, and the
chance of being followed by the opposite (pain or pleasure).[8]
Simply put (by considering only the first two factors) the
idea would be that we would have to multiply the intensity and the duration to
calculate the utility. Thus a very
strong but short pleasure might be worth more than an extended but very mild
pleasure.
4. Mill and “Types”
of Pleasure:
Bentham vs. Mill
(problems either way).
Bentham held that there was no qualitative difference
amongst pleasures--that one should simply “add them up.”
Mill, on the other hand, says:
-201 “if I am asked, what I mean by difference of quality in
pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, merely as
pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is but one possible answer.
Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or almost all who have
experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling of
moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure.
--scientific discovery, classical music, delight in others’
successes.
--201 “it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a
pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.”
In Mill there is an implicit appeal to the nature of man
and a valuation of a sort other than pleasure and pain!
In his On Liberty he says:
I regard utility as the ultimate appeal on all ethical
questions; but it must be utility in the largest sense grounded on the permanent
interests of man as a progressive being.[9]
Similarly, in his
Principles of Political Economy Mill says: “but there are other things, of
the worth of which the demand of the market is by no means a test; things of
which the utility does not consist in ministering to inclinations, nor in
serving the daily uses of life, and the want of which is least felt where the
need is greatest. This is peculiarly
true of those things which are chiefly useful as tending to raise the character
of human beings. The uncultivated
cannot be competent judges of cultivation.
Those who most need to be made wiser and better, usually desire it least,
and if they desired it, would be incapable of finding the way to it by their own
lights. It will continually happen,
on the voluntary system, that, the end not being desired, the means will not be
provided at all....”[10]
The distinction between kinds of pleasures engenders
problems for Mill however. To say
that pleasure is the only valuable thing and to say that there are distinctions
(of value) amongst the different kinds of pleasures is somewhat like saying: “I
care about nothing but money, but I wouldn’t come by it dishonestly.”
5. Mill’s “Proof” of
his Doctrine:
214 The only proof that something is desirable is that it
is desired.
6. Act
vs. Rule Utilitarianism:
Act utilitarians
maintain we should choose the actions
which provide the highest utility.
If breaking a promise, for example, had better positive than negative
consequences, they would maintain that it was right for one to break one’s
promise.
Rule utilitarians,
on the other hand, maintain that we should act on the
rule which tends to promote the highest utility.[11]
If promise keeping generally is conducive to positive utility, they would
contend that one must keep one’s promise even in those cases where breaking it
would, this time, have positive consequences.
7. Correctness
Considerations:
punishment of the innocent
difficulty of calculation
“greatest?”
kinds of pleasure
do we desire things other than happiness (intrinsically)?
could someone not desire happiness?
8. Sanctions for
Utilitarianism:
In Chapter III of his
Utilitarianism, Mill maintains that:
213-214 the deeply rooted conception which every individual
even now has of himself as a social being tends to make him feel it one of his
natural wants that there should be harmony between his feelings and aims and
those of his fellow creatures....This feeling in most individuals is much
inferior to their selfish feelings, and is often wanting altogether.
But to those who have it, it possesses all the characters of a natural
feeling. It does not present itself
to their minds as a superstition of education or a law despotically imposed by
the power of society, but as an attribute which it would not be well for them to
be without. This conviction is the
ultimate sanction of the greatest happiness morality.
This it is which makes any mind of well-developed feelings work with, and
not against, the outward motives to care for others....
[1] D.H. Monro,
“James Mill,”
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy v. 5, ed. Paul
Edwards (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1967), pp. 312-314, p.
314.
Monro cites the second paragraph from Mill’s
Autobiography.
[2] D.H. Monro,
“Jeremy Bentham,” in
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy v. 1,
op. cit.,
pp. 280-285, p. 282.
Emphasis added twice.
[3] Richard Brandt,
“The Real and Alleged Problems of
Utilitarianism,” in
Right
Conduct: Theories and Applications (second
edition), eds. Michael Bayles and Kenneth Henley
(N.Y.: Random House, 1989), pp. 122-130, p. 125.
Brandt’s essay originally appeared in
Hastings
Center Report v. 13 (April 1983), pp. 37-43.
[4]
Cf.,
Fred Feldman,
Introductory Ethics (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1978), pp.
21-29 for a good treatment of Mill’s principle.
[5] John Stuart
Mill,
Utilitarianism [1863], selections
in Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings
(6th edition), eds. Louis Pojman and James
Fieser (Belmont: Wadsworth, 2011), pp. 197-236.
References to this work throughout the
remainder of the supplement are to these
selections.
[6]
Cf.,
Fred Feldman,
Introductory Ethics, op. cit., pp. 21-26 for a discussion of various
different formulations of a “utilitarian maxim”
in an effort to precisely specify what Mill is
saying.
[7]
Ibid.,
p. 25.
[8]
Cf.,
Jeremy Bentham, “The Utilitarian Calculus”
(excerpted from his
An
Introduction to the Principles of Morals and
Legislation [1789]) in
Ethical
Theory: Classic and Contemporary Readings
(sixth edition), op. cit., pp. 194-196, pp.
194-195.
[9] John Stuart
Mill, On
Liberty [1859], in
Classics
of Western Philosophy (fourth edition), ed.
Steven M. Cahn (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1995), p.
1177.
[10] Cited in R.J.
Arneson, “Democracy and Liberty in Mill’s Theory
of Government,”
Journal of the History of Philosophy v. 20
(1982), pp. 43-64, p. 63.
[11]
Cf.,
Louis Pojman, “Utilitarianism,” in
Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings
(fifth edition),
op. cit.,
pp. 179-182,
esp.
p. 181.
Last revised: 09/10/2013