Lecture Supplement
on Kant’s Foundations for the Metaphysic
of Morals [1785][1]
Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
I. Preface:
284 The present treatise
is…nothing more than the investigation and establishment of the supreme
principle of morality….”
283 ...a law, if it is to hold
morally (i.e., as a ground of
obligation), must admit that the command: “Thou shalt not lie” does not apply to
men only as if other rational beings had no need to observe it.
--the ground of
obligation here must not be sought in the nature of man or in the circumstances
in which he is placed but a priori[2]
solely in the concepts of pure reason.
283-284 As long as rules rest on
an empirical basis, they can not be called moral laws.
A metaphysics of morals is therefore necessary, because morals themselves
remain subject to all kinds of corruption as long as the “supreme norm” for
their correct estimation is lacking.
Moreover, “in order that an action be morally good, it is not enough that
it conform to the moral law, but it must also be done
for the sake of the law, otherwise
that conformity is only very contingent and uncreertain….”
-Why is a “metaphysic
of morals” necessary? As we shall
see, Kant contends that only a metaphysical foundation can ultimately secure a
“pure” morality whose laws are “absolutely” necessary!
Only a “metaphysic of morals” can explain
the objective
necessity of these laws, while
allowing for their “subjective
contingency.”
Philosophy which mixes
pure principles with empirical ones does not deserve the name
.
II. Chapter 1:
Transition from Common Sense Knowledge of Morals to the Philosophical:
285 A look at the overall structure of this work shows that
we are about to begin “The First Section: Transition from Common Sense Knowledge
to the Philosophical” [pp. 285-291].
Next we will encounter the “Chapter 2: Transition from Popular Moral
Philosophy to the Metaphysics of Morals” [pp. 291-309], and, finally, we will
encounter the “Chapter 3: Transition from the Metaphysics of Morals to the
Critical Examination of Pure Practical Reason” [pp. 309-317].
In this progression we will obviously move from
common sense morality to
the a priori metaphysical ground and
nature of moral principles.
This progression, as Kant clearly states does not constitute a move from
empirical evidence to theory which is based upon this ground.
Instead we move from common sense considerations to the true, and
a priori, moral realm.
This first section is divided into a number of subparts.
A. The Good Will:
In this section, Kant clarifies what a good will is.
285 Nothing...can possibly be
conceived which could be called good without qualification except a
GOOD WILL.
-The sight of someone with
talents and gifts of fortune but without a good will will never bring pleasure
to an impartial observer.
-Moderation, self-control, calm
disposition, etc. are good only when accompanied by a good will (coolness of a
villain). A good will isn’t good
because of its effects.
285-286 A good will is
good only because of its willing.
B. Why Reason Was Made to Guide
the Will:[3]
286 Kant is a noted proponent of “pure” (or “speculative”)
reason, and in works like his The
Critique of Pure Reason he explains the role and importance of reason in
this guise. In this work we are
talking about practical reason
however—reason as it relates to action rather than to knowledge.
In this section Kant maintains that we have practical reason not to
provide for survival, nor to provide
for happiness, but, rather,
to guide the will.
If either of the other two were to be the purpose of reason, we would be
better served by relying upon the instincts.
291 ...no organ will be
found for any purpose which is not the fittest and best adapted to that purpose.
Now if its preservation, its welfare, in a word its happiness, were the
real end of nature in a being having reason and will, then nature would have hit
upon a very poor arrangement in appointing the reason of the creature to be the
executor of this purpose.” Instinct
would serve such functions far better!
286-287 Reason’s proper function
is a practical one—it must influence the will (that is, produce a will which is
“good in itself,” and not one good merely as a means).
C. The First Proposition of
Morality: Acting From Duty:
287 Kant will present us
with three propositions (or principles) of morality.
In this section he maintains that the good will must be understood by
discussing duty—here the will is
exposed to certain subjective limitations and obstacles which allow it to shine
forth. The good will will be one
that is impelled by its duty.
That is, his “first proposition
of morality” is: to have moral worth
an action must be done from duty.
At this stage (as we are “transitioning” from common sense morality to
philosophical morality), these propositions are explained by
appeal to examples, but not given an
ultimate metaphysical grounding.
Acting in accordance with duty
vs.
acting from duty—inclinations must
be avoided and the agent must be “impelled by his/her duty.”
-Example
(a duty to others): the grocer and not overcharging of inexperienced customer—if
the “motivation” is selfishness, then it is not praiseworthy.
-Example
(a duty to oneself): maintaining one’s life while suicidal—but only because it
is a duty to do so. The important
thing is that one does one’s duty because it is one’s duty.
--Note the
extreme picture these examples
present! It is not that Kant wants
the good will to manifest itself only in dreary contexts.
Instead, he recognizes that it is an impossible
epistemological problem trying to
determine whether a will is a good one, because we cannot easily separate
actions done from duty and those which are done from inclination (or where the
two are both active). The only time
we can be sure that the motivation of
the will is duty is where all one’s inclinations lead one in a radically
different direction from that specified by duty!
Rae Langton provides an excellent discussion of Kant’s “extreme” picture
here.[4]
-287-288
Example (another duty to others):
beneficial acts and one so soured by circumstances that all sympathy is
extinguished. If the kind acts are
still done from duty, the acts are right:
--288 “Put the case that
the mind of the philanthropist were clouded by sorrow of his own, extinguishing
all sympathy with the lot of others, and that, while he still has the power to
benefit others in distress, he is not touched by their trouble because he is
absorbed with his own; and now suppose that he tears himself out of this dead
insensibility, and performs the action without any inclination to it, but simply
from duty then first has his action its genuine worth.”
-Example
(another duty to oneself: the duty to assure one’s happiness: the sufferer who
preservers because of the duty to seek happiness.
Biblical command to love one’s
neighbor (you can’t command love): “for love, as an affection, cannot be
commanded, but beneficence for duty’s sake may; even though we are not impelled
to it by any inclination—nay, are even repelled by natural and unconquerable
aversion. This is practical love
and not pathological—a love which is seated in the will, and not in the
propensions of sense—in principles of action and not of tender sympathy; and it
is this love alone which can be commanded.”
D. The Second Proposition of
Morality:
Kant advances what he calls “the
second proposition of morality:
“that the moral worth of an action
derives from its maxim and not from
its consequences.
288 An action done from
duty does not have its moral worth in the purpose which is to be achieved
through it but in the maxim whereby
it is determined. Its moral value,
therefore, does not depend on the realization of the object of the action but
merely on the principle of the volition by which the action is done irrespective
of the objects of the faculty of desire.
E. The Third Proposition of
Morality:
Kant maintains that
duty is acting from respect for the law.
289 Only what is
connected with my will as a principle (rather than as an inclination) can
command
respect—only law can command.
“Now an action done from duty
must wholly exclude the influence of inclination and with it every object of the
will, so that nothing remains which can determine the will except objectively
the law, and subjectively pure respect for this practical will, and consequently
the maxim that I should follow this law even to the thwarting of all my
inclinations.”
F. The Supreme Principle of Morality:
The Categorical Imperative:
Thus Kant gives us the
first statement of his fundamental
moral principle—the summation of the above three propositions of morality:
289 “As I have deprived the will
of every impulse which could arise to it from obedience to any law, there
remains nothing but the universal conformity of its actions to law in general,
which alone is to serve the will as a principle, i.e., I am never to act
otherwise than so that I could also will that my maxim should become a universal
law. Here, now, it is the simple
conformity to law in general, without assuming any particular law applicable to
certain actions, that serves the will as its principle and must so serve it, if
duty is not to be a vain delusion and a chimerical notion.”
-289-290 May I make a promise
with the intention not to keep it?
We must not simply be concerned with consequences here!
“The shortest way…to discover the answer to this question….is to ask
oneself “Should I be content that my maxim….should hold good as a universal
law….Then I presently become aware that while I can will the lie, I can by no
means will that lying should be a universal law.
For with such a law there would be no promises at all, since it would be
in vain to allege my intention in regard to my further actions to those who
would not believe this allegation….my maxim, as soon as it should be made a
universal law, would necessarily destroy itself.”
--That is, the maxim is
contradictory—it would “destroy
itself” if universalized.
Common sense reason (the
practical faculty of judgment) recognizes the categorical imperative and needs
no instruction here. Theoretical
reason (the theoretical faculty of judgment) is easily mislead—that is,
philosophical speculation is difficult.
Wouldn’t it be easier to remain within the practical sphere and settle
for the case where ordinary individuals can have the knowledge which
philosophers can have?
-290-291 We can easily
be led astray from duty by our inclinations, however, and, thus, theoretical
knowledge of our duty becomes important.
A dialectic between our inclinations and our duty works on the will—one
wherein the inclinations attempt to question, undercut, and doubt the dictates
of rational duty. [291:] “…the
common reason of man is compelled to take a step into the field of practical
philosophy, not to satisfy any speculative want…[but] in order to attain in it
information and clear instruction respecting the source of its principle, and
the correct determination of it in opposition to the maxims which are based on
the wants and inclinations, so that it may escape from the perplexity of
opposite claims and not run the risk of losing all genuine moral principles
through the equivocation into which it easily falls.”
III. Chapter 2:
Transition from Popular Moral Philosophy to the Metaphysics of Morals:
In this section Kant moves us from “common
sense morality” toward a “metaphysics
of morals,” deepening our understanding of our duty, the categorical
imperative, and the ground of both.
This section does not take us all the way to the ground of morality,
however—that awaits the “third chapter [pp. 309-317].
A. The Impossibility of an Empirical
Moral Philosophy:
292 “…unless we deny that the
notion of morality has any truth or reference to any possible object, we must
admit that its law must be valid, not merely for men but for all rational
creatures generally, not merely under certain contingent conditions or with
exceptions but with absolute necessity, then it is clear that no experience
could enable us to infer even the possibility of such apodictic laws.”
[5]
294 Thus, according to
Kant we must not only advance “...from the common moral judgment…to the
philosophical, as has been already done, but also from a popular philosophy,
which goes no further than it can reach by groping with the help of examples, to
metaphysic (which does not allow itself to be checked by anything empirical and,
as it must measure the whole extent of this kind of rational knowledge, goes as
far as ideal conceptions, where even examples fail us), we must follow and
clearly describe the practical faculty of reason, from the general rules of its
determination to the point where the notion of duty springs from it.”
--Criticism:
in his Moral Knowledge, Alan Goldman
maintains that: “if my spouse or children thought that I am moved to provide
first for them primarily because I perceive this as the rational thing to do,
they would be repelled by my peculiar psychology.
We would dismiss any conception of rationality that did not hold these
things reasonable to do; we are not guided by an independent conception of
rationality or of a rational agent as such in wanting to do them.
It is true that I am motivated to avoid doing what I consider irrational,
but that is because clearly irrational behavior is normally counterproductive in
my attempts to satisfy my first- and second-order desires, not because my
deepest desire is to be a rational agent.
(Indeed, I remain unsure that I have a concept of a rational agent apart
from that of someone who tries efficiently to satisfy desires that humans
ordinarily have.)”[6]
294-296
B. Imperatives: Hypothetical and
Categorical:
294 Here we have several
centrally important paragraphs for understanding Kant:
-Everything in nature works
according to laws.
-Only rational beings may act
according to conceptions of laws.
-Reason is requisite for
derivation of actions from laws.
-If there was some
creature whose reason necessarily determined the will, then this sort of
creature would not distinguish those acts which are objectively necessary and
those which are subjectively necessary!
-We are not such
creatures! The acts we recognize as
objectively necessary are
subjectively contingent.
-Imperatives (that is ‘ought’
statements) are formulas for objective principles which constrain our willing.
--All imperatives are expressed
by an “ought” and thereby indicate the relation of an objective law of reason to
a will which is not in its subjective constitution necessarily determined by
this law.
--A perfectly good will [he will
come to call such a will a “holy will”]...would
be equally subject to objective laws of the good, but it could not be conceived
as constrained by them to accord with them, because it can be determined to act
by its own subjective constitution only through the conception of the good.
294-295 Hypothetical
Imperatives vs. Categorical
Imperatives:
Hypothetical Imperative: |
Hypothetical Imperative: |
Categorical Imperative: |
Problematic (not ends for all) (Imperatives of Skill)
To will the end is to will
the means |
Assertoric (ends for all)
(Counsels of Prudence)
Because we don’t know what
happiness is, these are merely counsels |
Apodeictic (ends for all) (Laws of Morality) Unlike the other two, these
can’t be justified empirically (that is they
must be justified
a priori) |
-295 “If now the action
is good only as a means to something else, then the imperative is hypothetical;
if it is considered as good in itself and consequently as necessarily the
principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason, then it is
categorical.”
C. The Rational Foundations of
Hypothetical Imperatives:
295-297 Kant raises the question “How
are imperatives possible (what is their ground)?”
He notes that we can understand the imperatives of
skill and
prudence easily, but those of
morality are a different sort altogether, and this question is difficult in
their case.
296 How an imperative of
skill is possible requires no special discussion.
Whoever wills the end, so far as reason has decisive influence on his
action, wills also the indispensably necessary steps to it that he can take.
Imperatives of prudence would be
no less analytic than those of skill except for the fact that we don’t know what
happiness is and, thus, this imperative is nearly empty.
Hence the imperatives of prudence
cannot, in the strict sense, command...they are to be taken as counsels rather
than as commands.
D. The Rational Foundation of the
Categorical Imperative:
297 Kant discusses the foundation of the moral imperative
(the categorical one), noting that this ground (or “possibility”) must differ
from that for the imperatives of skill and prudence.
“…the objective necessity which
[the categorical imperative of morality] presents cannot rest on any hypothesis,
as is the case with the hypothetical imperatives.
Only here we must never leave out of consideration that we cannot make
out by any example, in other words empirically, whether there is such an
imperative at all, but it is rather to be feared that all those which seem to be
categorical may yet be at bottom hypothetical.”
The possibility of the [categorical]
imperative of morality, then, will have to be established completely
a priori.
But, he adds, this imperative can
not be true analytically and
necessarily, since it is to be an
imperative of practical reason.
Thus, it must be a synthetical
a priori proposition!
Such propositions
are characterized by “transcendental”
(rather than “logical”) necessity—that is to say, if we are to have the
character, experience, and knowledge that we do, these propositions and
judgments are necessary.
-In his “Royce: The Absolute and
the Beloved Community Revisited,” John E. Smith maintains that “the quest for
the conditions which make the actual
possible is the task of transcendental philosophy.
This reflective enterprise is novel in that it cannot be carried out on
the basis of either of the two classical forms of thought: deduction, and
induction or probable inference.”[7]
-That is, where
a priori propositions are
characterized by logical
necessity, and while synthetic propositions are characterized by
logical
contingency, this “new” set of
propositions are supposed to be neither.
They are transcendental
propositions which describe the preconditions which make the possible
actual—they, then, have what might be called
transcendental necessity.
Consider what J.W.N. Watkins and K. Popper call “all and some
propositions:” (x)($y)Fxy
(e.g.: “Every event has a cause”)
they are unverifiable and unfalsifiable:
such propositions certainly could
not be known a posteriori; if true,
they must be known a priori if they are to be known at all.
The difficulty is just this—how are they to be known at all?
Thus, it may be better to distinguish between a priori propositions and
non-empirical propositions of this kind.
A priori propositions are those which can be known to be true and whose
truth is ascertainable by a procedure that makes no reference to experience;
non-empirical propositions of the kind in question are not like this, for their
truth is, strictly speaking, not ascertainable at all.
If we accept them, it must be as mere postulates or as principles whose
force is regulative in some sense.[8]
Philip Kitcher helps us
characterize these propositions using another sort of example:
frequently...it is maintained
that only necessary truths can be known a priori.
Behind this contention stands a popular argument.
Assume that a person knows a priori that p.
His knowledge is independent of his experience.
Hence he can know that p without any information about the kind of world
he inhabits. So, necessarily p.
...there are propositions which could not both be false and also be
believed by us in particular definite ways.
Obvious examples are propositions about ourselves and their logical
consequences: such propositions as those expressed by tokens of the sentences “I
exist,” “I have some beliefs,” “There are thoughts,” and so forth.
Hence the...[argument above]...breaks down and...[we must allow] for the
possibility of a priori knowledge of some contingent propositions.”[9]
This “new” sort of proposition is
necessary if we are to produce the proper sort of ground for a universal law of
practical reason—one which can be have the requisite objective and subjective
(necessary and contingent) character.
297-299
E. The First Formulation of the
Categorical Imperative: Universal Law:
297 There is only one categorical
imperative:
-“...act
only on that maxim whereby which you can at the same time
will that it should become a
universal law.”
-298 In talking about what this
imperative commands, we need to distinguish the cases of “perfect”
and “imperfect” duties: the former
are absolutely required actions wherein there is no “free play” for personal
discretion or variation regarding how or when to perform the actions; while the
latter require action, at least at times, from individuals but leave open to the
individual the choice of actions to fulfill the goals.
As Michael Bayles and Ken Henley note, “a maxim that proposes a violation
of perfect duty cannot be universalized, for the state of affairs in which it
would be universally adopted cannot be consistently described.”[10]
“A maxim that proposes a violation of imperfect duty cannot be
universalized, for although its universal adoption can be consistently
described, the agent cannot will such universal adoption without a conflict.”[11]
Illustrations:
1. The tragic suicide case.
Contradiction in the
maxim.
2. Borrowing money with a lying
promise case.
Contradiction in the maxim.
3. The reluctant talent
development case.
Contradiction in the
attempt to will the maxim.
4. 298-299 The
unconcerned benevolence case.
Contradiction in the
attempt to will the maxim.
299 “We must be able to
will that a maxim of our action
should become a universal law. This
is the canon of the moral appreciation of the action generally.
Some actions are of such a character that their maxim cannot without
contradiction be ever conceived as a
universal law of nature, far from it being possible that we should will that it
should be so. In others this
intrinsic impossibility is not found, but still impossible to
will that their maxim should be
raised to the universality of a law of nature, since such a will would
contradict itself.”
When we transgress against duty
we don’t will that our maxim be a universal law, instead we make an
exception for ourselves!
“...if we considered all
cases from one and the same point of view, namely, that of reason, we should
find a contradiction in our own will, namely, that a certain principle should be
objectively necessary as a universal law, and yet admit of exceptions”
299-300
F. Transgression of the Moral Law and The Need for an
A Priori Proof:
Kant explains how we go morally wrong, and notes that we
are after fundamental moral
principles which can not come out of merely contingent facts:
reason alone can dictate them!
300 “Thus every empirical element
is not only quite incapable of being an aid to the principle of morality, but is
even highly prejudicial to the purity of morals, for the proper and inestimable
worth of an absolutely good will consists precisely in this, that the principle
of action is free from all influence of contingent grounds, which alone
experience can furnish.”
-300 Thus we will have
to take up the (pure) metaphysics of morals—we will have to precind from all
that is empirical: “...the question then is: “Is it a necessary law for all
rational beings that they should always judge of their actions by maxims of
which they can themselves will that they should serve as universal laws?”
If it is so, then it must be connected (altogether
a priori) with the conception of the
will of a rational being generally.
But in order to discover this conception, we must, however reluctantly, take a
step into metaphysics, although into a domain of it which is distinct from
speculative philosophy, namely the metaphysics of morals.
In a practical philosophy, where it is not he reasons of what happened
that we have to ascertain, but the laws of what ought to happen….”
--Criticism:
in her “The Place of Emotions in Kantian Morality,” Nancy Sherman maintains
that: “beneficence is not a moral principle for angels, but for human beings
whose rational capacities happen to be finite and who therefore need the
collaborative assistance and resources of others.
A maxim that seeks to gain self-advantage by denying mutual aid is
incoherent in the universalized world of that maxim only because the agent of
such a maxim will be denied what she needs for effective human willing.
It is because of our human condition that a policy of mutual disinterest
is impermissible, and its opposite, beneficence, morally required.
Put differently, dependence is a contingent matter for us, and the
obligation to be beneficent requires appeal to that empirical premise.
We contradict our wills by a maxim of nonbeneficence insofar as we deny a
standing fact about our wills....the other substantive human virtues and the
categorical imperatives that correspond to them are similarly justified by
appeal to certain empirical facts.
But if this is the case, then not only
how we express what we are morally required to do is contingent upon our
constitutions, but equally, what we
are morally required to do. That
is, substantive moral principles or ends depend upon empirical facts.”[12]
G. Second Formulation of the Categorical
Imperative: Humanity As An End In Itself:
300-302 Kant offers the
second of his three formulations of
the categorical imperative. The
first was: “act according to that maxim which one may will should be a universal
law”.
The second formulation deepens our
understanding of the relationship of the imperative to reason.
300-301 Kant notes that only
rational beings are able to determine their wills in accord with conceptions of
laws. In cases where we are dealing
with objective (rather than subjective) purposes, the will must be determined by
reasons that would be accepted by all rational agents.
That is, if we are dealing with actions that serve merely relative
purposes, we will get only hypothetical
imperatives. To get a
categorical imperative, one must
suppose [301] “...that there were something whose existence has in itself an
absolute worth, something which,
being an end in itself, could be a source of definite laws; then in this and
this alone would lie the source of a possible categorical imperative, i.e., of a
practical law.
Now I say man and
generally any rational being exists as an end in himself, not merely as a means
to be arbitrarily used by this or that will, but in all his actions, whether
they concern himself or other rational beings, must be always regarded at the
same time as an end.”
-301 “If then there is a
supreme practical…it must be one which...is necessarily an end for everyone
because it is an end in itself....rational nature exists as an end in itself....So
act as to treat humanity, whether in your own person or that of any other, in
every cases as an end withal, never as a means only.
301-302
Illustrations [though examples
shouldn’t be used as we are to have moved to the metaphysical foundations, he
uses them here to clarify the second formulation of the Categorical
Imperative—his use of them is pedagogical
rather than justificatory or
philosophical]:
1. The tragic suicide case.
-Treats oneself as a means only.
301-302 2. Borrowing money with a
promise case.
-Treats others as means
only.
302 3. The reluctant talent
development case.
-Treating humanity—in
the “body” of the self—as means only (tending only to the maintenance of
humanity and not to its promotion/development).
4. The unconcerned benevolence
case.
-Treating humanity in
general as a means only rather than as an end.
302-303
H. Third Formulation of the Categorical
Imperative: The Autonomy of the Will as Universal Legislator:
In this section Kant provides the deepest formulation of
his categorical imperative, tracing it as fully as he can within the
“metaphysics of morals” to its metaphysical grounding.
302 “This principle,
that humanity and generally every rational nature is an end in itself (which, is
the supreme limiting condition of every man’s freedom of action), is not
borrowed from experience, firstly, because of it is universal, applying, as it
does to all rational beings whatsoever, and experience is not capable of
determining anything about them; secondly, because it does not present humanity
as an end to men (subjectively), that is as an object which men do of themselves
actually adopt as an end; but as an objective end, which must as a law
constitute the supreme limiting condition of all our subjective ends, let them
be what they will; it must therefore spring from pure reason.
In fact the objective principle of all practical reason lies (according
to the first principle) in the rule and its form of universality, which makes it
capable of being a law...but the subjective principle is in the end; now by the
second principle the subject of all ends is each rational being, inasmuch as it
is an end itself. hence follows
the third practical principle
of the will, which is the ultimate condition of its harmony with universal
practical reason, viz.: the idea of the will of every rational being as a
universally legislative will.
On this principle all maxims are
rejected which are inconsistent with the will being itself a universal
legislator. Thus the will is not
subject simply to the law, but so subject that it must be regarded as itself
giving the law and, on this ground only, subject to the law (of which it can
regard itself as the author).”
303 Here we need to
distinguish heteronomy from
autonomy.
303-306
I. The Kingdom of Ends:
In this section, Kant discusses the “location” of the
autonomous wills.
303 By a kingdom I understand the
union of different rational beings in a system by common laws.”
-Rational beings are
both subjects and sovereigns in such
a realm! A rational being belongs
to such a realm of ends as a member
when he gives universal laws which he is subject.
He belongs to it as sovereign
when legislating as he is subject to the will of no other [that is, he is
autonomous].
-304 Dignity
vs.
value—things which have the latter
can be replaced by something else of equivalent value.
Things which have dignity are without equivalence.
304-306 According to Kant, the
three versions of the Categorical Imperative are all the same!
Criticism: in his “Trust,
Affirmation, and Moral Character: A Critique of Kantian Morality,” Laurence
Thomas offers the following critique of Kantian ethics: “...wholly rational
moral selves do not need one another for moral support and affirmation.
Since all are metaphysically constituted so that of necessity they act in
accordance with the moral law, there can be no sense in which their moral
endeavors sustain one another.
Indeed, if their moral endeavors did, then they could not be members of the
kingdom of ends, since in that case they would not be acting for (and only for)
the sake of the moral law. With
wholly rational moral selves we have absolute autonomy, but we lack moral
community.
I cannot see why human beings should embrace this moral ideal.
For it is an ideal that tells us that
human life at its very best
nevertheless misses the moral mark.
The good life, if only we could achieve it, is one where individuals are
mutually supportive of one another and trust abounds, where individuals find
strength in one another’s moral victories and learn from one another’s moral
shortcomings, and where in general the biological capacity for love...and the
good will anchored in it give morality a foothold in our lives that it would not
otherwise have. I can see nothing
frail or imperfect in life thus lived.
Nor can I see that we should want to think of life thus lived as at best
a limited expression of what living morality is all about.”[13]
Criticism: in his “A Critique of
Kantianism,” Richard Taylor maintains that: “Kant peoples a veritable utopia,
which he of course does not imagine as existing, with these Ends in Themselves,
and calls it the Kingdom of Ends.
Ends in Themselves are, thus, not to be thought of as those men that live and
toil on the earth; them are not suffering, rejoicing, fumbling, living, and
dying human beings; they are not men that anyone has ever seen, or would be apt
to recognize as men if they did see them, or apt to like very much is he did
recognize them. They are abstract
things, reifications of Rational nature, fabricated by Kant and now called
Rational Beings or Ends in Themselves.
Their purpose, unlike that of any creature under the sun, is not to
sorrow and rejoice, not to love and hate, not to beget offspring, not to grow
old and die, and not to get on as best they can to such destinies as the world
has allotted them. Their purpose is
just to legislate—to legislate
morally and rationally for this rational Kingdom of Ends.”[14]
306-307
J. The Autonomy of the Will as the
Supreme Principle of Morality:
In this section Kant
maintains that the principle of autonomy is a
synthetical proposition and, thus,
cannot be proven to be an [the practical] imperative by an analysis of its
terms.
307-309
K. Heteromony of the Will as the Source
of All Spurious Principles of Morality:
Kant notes that when the will looks outside itself for its
laws or imperatives, it finds only
hypothetical imperatives.
IV. Third Section:
Transition from the Metaphysic of Morals to the Critical Examination of Pure
Practical Reason
In this section Kant moves us from a “metaphysic of morals”
toward a “critical examination of Pure Practical Reason.”
According to him, to understand morality and the categorical imperative,
we must understand how
the will,
reason, and
freedom are intertwined.
This discussion requires a distinction between
the
empirical and
a posteriori
world of our experience, and
the a priori world of
reason (or rationality).
The objective [universal] laws of the empirical world apply to us
heteronomously (they are imposed
upon us). In contrast, objective
[universal] moral laws (that is, the Categorical Imperative) apply
autonomously to us, and this means
that they must be subjectively contingent.
Here we encounter statements which Kant calls “synthetic
a priori.”
Such statements are characterized by “transcendental”
(rather than “logical”)
necessity—that is to say, if we are to have the character, experience, and
knowledge that we do, these propositions and judgments are necessary.
In his A History of Western
Philosophy: Philosophy From the Renaissance to the Romantic Age, A. Robert
Caponigri offers the following useful characterization of Kant’s “critical”
orientation in metaphysics and epistemology:
the critical problem has at its
base the desire of Kant to evade...scepticism, by raising and resolving the
basic issue: how is it possible for objects to correspond to the concepts of the
understanding. This is equivalent
to the question, how are the philosophical disciplines, that is, sciences which
reach their objects independently of experience of the senses, possible.
The clue to his resolution of that problem has already been suggested in
the manner in which, in the Dissertation,
he had solved the problem of the objects of the senses.
The formal statement of the problem is made by Kant...in terms of the
logic of propositions. The typical
statement of the sciences that proceed by analysis is an analytical proposition.
The character of such propositions is that all that is explicated in the
predicate is already contained implicitly in the concept of the
subject....Synthetic propositions are those in which the predicates affirmed of
the subject are not to be discovered by analysis of its concept.
Such synthetic propositions would,
according to the prevailing view, have all to be derived from experience and
have a value as knowledge that is wholly a function of experience.
We are confronted, therefore, Kant believes, by the unhappy alternative
of believing that there are sciences of experience, which proceed by a method of
synthesis “a posteriori,” which have genuine objects in experience and which are
dynamic and expansive in that they are always open to the novelty of the content
of experience, but which can never have that character of universality and
necessity which is the classical attribute of science.
On the other hand, there are sciences that proceed by a method of “a
priori” analysis, which have, indeed, an indisputable character of universality
and necessity within the limits of their terms and methods, but which have no
objects in the order of existence.
Consequently, between the wings of these alternatives, Kant introduces a
third possibility that alone, he believes, could correspond to the concept of
science. That is to say, an order
of sciences which should indeed proceed by a method “a priori,” but by a method
at the same time synthetic, a method which would, consequently, assure them both
of universality and necessity, and at the same time, of an order of objects in
existence and a dynamism which is the quality of existence itself.
Such sciences, consequently, would consist of propositions, in their
positive aspects, which would be neither analytical “a priori” nor synthetical
“a posteriori,” but rather synthetic a
priori. The most formal way,
consequently, in which this critical problem can be put is this: how are
propositions synthetical a priori
possible?[15]
A. The Concept of Freedom Is the Key
That Explains the Autonomy of the Will:
In his “We Can Act Only Under the Idea of Freedom,” Henry
Allison maintains that: “...freedom is not simply a property that we may
attribute to ourselves as rational agents on heuristic grounds; it is rather the
defining feature of this very
conception.”
[16]
In this section, Kant clarifies the importance of the concept of freedom
for the will.
309 “The will is a kind
of causality belonging to living beings in so far as they are rational, and
freedom would be this property of such causality that it can be efficient,
independently of foreign causes determining it; just as physical necessity is
the property that causality of all irrational beings has of being determined to
activity by the influence of foreign causes.”
-“On the hypothesis,
then, of freedom of the will, morality together with its principle [the
Categorical Imperative] follows from it by mere analysis of the conception.
However, the latter is a synthetic proposition….[and] such propositions
are only possible in this way: that the two cognitions are connected together by
their union with a third in which they are both to be found.
The positive concept of freedom furnishes this third cognition, which
cannot, as with physical causes, be the nature of the sensible world….”
B. Freedom Must Be Presupposed as the
Property of the Will of All Rational Beings:
In this section Kant maintains that since morality applies
to all rational beings, its laws must be universal and rational.
According to him morality also requires “the Idea of freedom:”
310 “Now I affirm that we must
attribute to every rational being which has a will that it has also the idea of
freedom and acts entirely under this idea.
For in such a being we conceive a reason that is practical, that is, has
causality in reference to its objects.
Now we cannot possibly conceive a reason consciously receiving a bias
from any other quarter with respect to its judgments, for then the subject would
ascribe the determination of its judgment not to its own reason, but to an
impulse.”
C. The Two Points of View:
In this section, Kant clarifies the distinction between the
noumenal and
phenomenal vantage points and
concerns. They are introduced on p.
311.
312 “…a rational being must[17]
regard himself qua intelligence (not from the side of his lower faculties) as
belonging not to the world of sense, but to that of understanding; hence he has
two points of view from which he can regard himself, and recognize laws of the
exercise of his faculties, and consequently of all his actions: first, so far as
he belongs to the world of sense, he finds himself subject to laws of nature
(heteronomy); secondly, as belonging to the intelligible work, under laws which
being independent of nature have their foundation not in experience but in
reason alone.”
D. How Is A Categorical Imperative
Possible?
He allows the there appears to be a question-begging
progression here from morality to freedom to morality.
But he contends that we can see that there really is no question begging
here.
313 “...what makes the
categorical imperatives possible is this, that the idea of freedom makes me a
member of an intelligible world….and this categorical “ought” implies a
synthetic a priori proposition, inasmuch as besides my will as affected by
sensible desires there is added further the idea of the same will but as
belonging to the world of the understanding, pure and practical of itself, which
contains the supreme condition according to reason of the former will; precisely
as to the intuitions of sense there are added concepts of the understanding….”
316 The question
How is a categorical imperative
possible,” can be answered to this extent, that we can assign the only
hypothesis on which it is possible, namely, the idea of freedom; and we can also
discern the necessity of this presupposition, and this is sufficient for the
practical exercise of reason.”
The “Concluding Remark brings this altogether.
(end)
[1]
Supplement to T.K. Abbott’s translation of
Kant’s
Foundations for the Metaphysics of Morals
[1785] which was first published in 1873 which
appears in
Ethical
Theory: Classical and Contemporary Readings
(sixth edition),
eds. Louis Pojman and James Fieser (Boston:
Wadsworth, 2011), pp. 282-319.
Subsequent references to the text will be
accompanied with the appropriate pages in the
reprint.
[2] A
proposition is
a priori
if it can be known (or justified) independently
of sensory experience.
That is, if it can be known or justified
through reason once its constituents are
understood.
An argument is an
a priori
one if all of its premises are
a priori.
[3] I will
not always adhere to the section headings of the
editors and translator—sometimes those others
have chosen seem preferable to me.
[4] Cf.,
Rae Langton, “Duty and Desolation,”
Philosophy v. 67 (1992), pp. 481-505.
[5] That is
laws which are demonstrable and indisputable.
[6] Alan
Goldman,
Moral Knowledge (London: Routledge, 1988),
p.107.
[7] John E.
Smith, “Royce: The Absolute and the Beloved
Community Revisited” [1982] in Smith’s
America’s Philosophical Vision (Chicago:
Univ. of Chicago, 1992), pp. 121-137, p. 126.
The essay originally appeared in
Boston
Studies in Philosophy and Religion, ed.
Leroy S. Rouner (Notre Dame: Univ. of Notre
Dame, 1982).
Emphasis is added to the passage.
[8] D.W.
Hamlyn’s “A Priori and A Posteriori” in
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Paul Edwards
(N.Y.: Macmillan, 1967), v. 1, p. 142.
[9] Philip
Kitcher,
“A Priori Knowledge” in
Naturalizing Epistemology, ed. H. Kornblith
(Bradford Books: New York, 1985), p. 139.
[10] Michael
Bayles and Kenneth Henley, “Kant and
Contractarianism,” in
Right Conduct: Theories and Applications
(N.Y.: Random House, 1989), pp. 58-69, p. 62.
[11]
Ibid.,
p. 63.
[12] Nancy
Sherman, “The Place of Emotions in Kantian
Morality,” in
Identity,
Character, and Morality, eds. Owen Flanagan
and Amelie Rorty (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990),
pp. 149-170, p. 167.
[13] Laurence
Thomas, “Trust, Affirmation, and Moral
Character: A Critique of Kantian Morality,” in
Identity,
Character, and Morality,
op. cit.,
pp. 235-257, pp. 254-255.
[14] Richard
Taylor, “A Critique of Kantianism,” in
Right and
Wrong Basic Readings in Ethics, ed.
Christina Hoff Sommers (San Diego: Harcourt,
1986), pp. 62-69, p. 67.
The essay originally appeared in Taylor’s
Good and
Evil (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1970).
[15]
Cf.,
A. Robert Caponigri,
A History of Western Philosophy: Philosophy From
the Renaissance to the Romantic Age (Notre
Dame: Univ. of Notre Dame, 1963), p. 449-450.
[16] Henry
Allison, “We Can Act Only Under the Idea of
Freedom,”
Proceedings and Addresses of the American
Philosophical Association v. 71 (1997), pp.
39-50, p. 42.
Emphasis added to the passage.
[17] Which
sense of `must’ is employed here?
File revised on: 10/15/2013.