Hauptli's Lecture
Supplement on Lehrer & Paxson’s “Knowledge: Undefeated JTB”[1]
[1969]
Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
1. Introduction:
Lehrer and Paxson offer a version of a “defeasibility”
analysis of knowledge. According to
Bruce Hunter,
the warrant a proposition
p has for us on the basis of evidence
e is
defeasible when expanded evidence
could decrease p’s warrant.
For example, ‘The next crow I see will be black’ is less warranted when,
despite evidence e that observed
crows were black, we are told on unusually reliable authority that there are
many albino birds nearby, and have no evidence this present testimony is an
exception. Our actual warrant
depends on our total evidence.
In stock cases, we don’t ‘lose’ e,
but its import is undercut when it and the rest of our original total evidence
is combined with additional evidence
e'.[2]
It may be helpful to distinguish here between additional
facts or evidence which we are unaware of,
and the same facts or evidence when we
become aware of it. In the
former case, we can call the additional factors “defeaters,”
while in the latter case, they should be called “overriders”—once
we now have added the information to our evidence base, our original evidence is
“overridden” by the new additions.
As Ralph Baergen says (changing the order in his treatment of these),
an
overrider is some fact that when
added to S’s justification,
eliminates that justification; that
is, the new expanded body of information no longer supports the target belief.
A defeater is a
potential overrider; that is, a
defeater is a fact such that, if S
knew about it, it would act as an overrider.
Now, here’s how defeaters and overriders fit into this account of
knowledge: A defeater will prevent a JTB...from counting as knowledge (but won’t
prevent it from being a JTB), but an overrider prevents a belief from being a
JTB (because it prevents it from being justified).[3]
Lehrer and Paxson will offer an analysis of knowledge which
appeals to this notion of defeasibility to avoid “Gettier” counter-examples (to
avoid cases of lucky or accidental truth).
As Jack Crumley notes, however, a difficulty they encounter is with the
possibility of misleading defeaters:
imagine that you attend a
wedding of two close friends and that the ceremony is performed by a priest well
known to you and the others at the ceremony.
The wedding is conducted and concluded without a hitch.
On the basis of this evidence, you come to believe that the couple is
married. Clearly, your belief is
justified; you have every reason to think that you know your friends are
married. But let us suppose that
unbeknownst to you and the others present, including the priest, the bishop has
gone crazy. Among other things, the
bishop falsely denounces the priest as a fraud.
Now, there is a true proposition: The bishop has denounced the priest as
a fraud. Were you aware of this
proposition, you would not be justified in believing your friends to be married,
because fraudulent priests cannot marry anyone....Despite the apparent defeater,
we are still tempted to say that you know.
The crazy bishop can illustrate that a distinction must be drawn between
genuine and misleading defeaters.
Misleading defeaters are defeaters that can themselves be defeated; that
is, still further evidence can be obtained that would “restore” the original
justification.[4]
Before we try to understand this problem, however, we
should turn to Lehrer and Paxson's essay.
2. Basic Knowledge:
Our authors begin by distinguishing
basic knowledge from
nonbasic knowledge.
The former, of course, is to provide the basis for the latter.
According to them:
31 if a man knows that a
statement is true even though there is no other statement that justifies his
belief, then his knowledge is basic.
Basic knowledge is completely
justified true belief.
Most of our knowledge claims will be nonbasic in
character—they will depend on other beliefs and statements:
on the other hand, if a man
knows that a statement is true because there is some other statement that
justifies his belief, then his knowledge is nonbasic.
Nonbasic knowledge requires something in addition to completely justified
true belief; for, though a statement completely justifies a man in his belief,
there may be some true statement that
defeats his justification.
Clearly, for Lehrer and Paxson,
basic belief is not defeasible,
while nonbasic belief is defeasible:
nonbasic knowledge is undefeated
justified true belief.
They offer the following analysis of basic knowledge:
...S has basic knowledge that
h iff (i)
h is true, (ii) S believes that
h, (iii) S is completely justified in
believing that h, and (iv) the
satisfaction of condition (iii) does not depend on any evidence
p justifying S in believing that
h.
What examples do they give us of such knowledge claims?
Well, it turns out that they don’t
provide any which they are willing to countenance.
Indeed, they say they are “agnostic” as to whether or not there are cases
of basic knowledge. Their analysis
allows for the “possibility.”
Moreover, one may ask why they use ‘h’
rather than ‘p’ here—I believe that
they conceive of it as standing for a “hypothesis”
(rather than a “proposition”).
We should also note, in passing,
that they require “complete” justification here, and we might wonder what this
is, whether it is attainable, whether it is too strong a requirement, and
whether or not it will leave us with the sort of skepticism which Lehrer
advanced in his “Why Not Scepticism?”[5]
32 They do mention Unger’s
example of the crystal-ball-gazing gypsy who is always right, but has no
evidence to this effect and, generally [but not this time] believes s/he is
wrong about his/her beliefs. They
also briefly mention that many philosophers have held that certain memory and
perceptual beliefs fit this category.
It is important for
us to note, here, that if there are such cases of knowledge, then the notion
of “complete justification” will not be appropriately conceived in terms of
“reasons, evidence, or justifications which the agent explicitly has.”
3. Nonbasic
Knowledge:
32-33 They discuss “Gettier
counterexamples” to traditional JTB analysis of knowledge:
-33 Brian Skyrms’ pyromaniac and the
sure-fire matches example (the matches are wet but there is also a burst of
Q-radiation which ignites the match).
--As I have noted, the problem raised by such cases is that of “lucky” (or
“accidental”) truths. The belief is
believed, it is true, and the believer has evidence (which prevents his belief
being a “lucky guess”), but the evidence
isn’t appropriately related to the truth
and to the believing, and so the truth’s truth is “lucky”
(or accidental) on the evidence at hand.
Following a suggestion of Chisholm’s, Lehrer and Paxson
offer a “defeasibility analysis,” because they contend that
justifications are defeasible:
in the examples referred to
above, there is some true statement that would defeat any justification of S for
believing that h.
-S has nonbasic knowledge that h
iff (i)
h is true, (ii) S believes that
h, and (iii) there is some statement
p that completely justifies S in
believing that h and no other
statement defeats this justification.
They note that this leaves us in
need of a “definition” of ‘defeats’!
I would note that it there seems a tension here within the “third
condition:” p is to be
both
defeasible and supposed to “completely
justify” S in believing that h!
Lehrer and Paxson propose the following “initial” definition of
‘defeats’:
-...when
p completely justifies S in believing
that h, this justification is
defeated by q
iff (i)
q is true, and (ii) the conjunction
of p and
q does not completely justify S in
believing that h.
33-34 This is too restrictive a definition, however—it doesn’t take account of
the possibility of misleading defeaters!
Consider the Tom Grabit example:
-Tom is a student, the professor sees him steal a book from the library.
Tom’s mother says it was his evil twin brother John.
--The mother’s statement defeats the professor’s knowledge claim.
-34 Suppose that the mother is a pathological liar.
“The fact that Mrs. Grabit said what she did should not be allowed to
defeat any justification I have for believing that Tom Grabit removed the book,
because I neither entertained any beliefs concerning Mrs. Grabit nor would I
have been justified in doing so.
More specifically, my justification does not depend on being completely
justified in believing that Mrs. Grabit did
not say the things in question.”
According to Lehrer and Paxson, we need
to define ‘defeat’ in a way which allows us to avoid misleading defeaters
(as in the “Grabit” example) while
capturing the sort of defeaters we encounter in the “Nogot/Havit” case
(discussed in detail on p. 140):
-34-35 In the case of Tom Grabit, the true statement that Mrs. Grabit said Tom
was not in the library and so forth, should not be allowed to defeat my
justification for believing that Tom removed the book, whereas in the case of
Mr. Nogot, the true statement that Mr. Nogot does not own a Ford, should defeat
my justification for believing that someone in my class owns a Ford.
Why should one true statement but
not the other be allowed to defeat my justification?
The answer is that in one case my justification depends on my being
completely justified in believing the true statement to be false while in the
other it does not....a defeating
statement must be one which, though true, is such that the subject is completely
justified in believing it to be false.
Thus, we get
their “first” revised definition of
defeasibility:
35 ...when
p completely justifies S in believing
that h, this justification is
defeated by q
iff (i)
q is true, (ii) S is completely
justified in believing q to be
false, and (iii) the conjunction of p
and q does not completely justify S
in believing that h.
-There is a “technical problem” with this definition however: the fact that
q may not be
relevant to
p (for example if I wrongly believe
that I was born is Miami while I am thinking about the Grabit case).
Where we are dealing with a complex situation wherein there are
consequences of a fact some of which might be irrelevant and some of which might
be relevant and defeaters we need to come up with a better definition.
Thus we get to their Final
Revised Definition of Defeasibility:
...if
p completely justifies S in believing
that h, then this justification is
defeated by q
iff (i)
q is true, (ii) the conjunction of
p and
q does not completely justify S in
believing that h, (iii) S is
completely justified in believing q
to be false, and (iv) if c is a
logical consequence of q such that
the conjunction of c and
p does not completely justify S in
believing that h, then S is
completely justified in believing c
to be false.
Here, Lehrer and Paxson contend, we have an adequate
analysis of nonbasic knowledge, and when it is coupled with the definition of
basic knowledge, we have a full analysis of [propositional] knowledge.
4.
Comparison with Other Analyses:
36-40 They go
on to discuss how their analysis differs from, and is better than, those of
Brian Skyrms, Roderick Chisholm, and Peter Unger (in his pre-skeptical
incarnation). I am not going to discuss
this material and will not hold you responsible for the discussion, but the
additional examples discussed enrich one's set of intuition-challenging examples
in the Gettier discussion.
41 They end the
discussion with the claim that:
...on any
satisfactory theory of justification, some knowledge must be undefeated
completely justified true belief, and the rest is basic.
5. Difficulties for
Defeasibility Analyses:
As noted above, one of the fundamental problems encountered
by such analyses will be that of the existence of “misleading defeaters.”
Another problem with the sort of analysis offered by Lehrer and Paxson is
stated by Baergen as follows:
a further difficulty is found in
the claim that to count as knowledge a belief must be “completely (or fully)
justified.” What are we to make of
this? Justification, it will be
remembered, admits of degree, and not just any degree of justification will
satisfy the justification of the JTB requirements for knowledge.
A rather high degree of justification is needed, but the question is, How
high? Saying that justification
must be full or complete suggests that it must be justification to the highest
possible degree. This is awkward,
for there is reason to believe that we rarely—if ever—attain this sort of
justification; certainly, we do not attain it in every case that we want to
count as knowledge. But if the
threshold for justification is set lower than this, we need to be told how this
[level] is to be determined.[6]
[1] Keith
Lehrer and Thomas Paxson, “Knowledge: Undefeated
Justified True Belief,” in
The
Journal of Philosophy v. 66 (1969), pp.
225-237.
The essay is reprinted in
Knowledge: Readings In Contemporary Epistemology,
Sven Bernecker and Fred Dretske, eds. (N.Y.:
Oxford U.P., 2000), pp. 31-41.
These notes are to the reprint.
[2] Bruce
Hunter, “Defeasibility,” in
A
Companion to Epistemology, eds. Jonathan
Dancy and Ernest Sosa (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992),
p. 91, emphasis added to passage once.
[3] Ralph
Baergen,
Contemporary Epistemology (Fort Worth:
Harcourt, 1995), p. 120.
Emphasis (bold) added to passage four
times.
[4] Jack
Crumley II,
An
Introduction to Epistemology (Mountain View:
Mayfield, 1999), p. 55.
[5]
Cf.,
Keith Lehrer, “Why Not Skepticism?”
The
Philosophical Forum v. 2 (1971), pp.
283-298; it is reprinted in
The
Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary
Readings (third edition), ed. Louis Pojman,
op. cit.,
pp. 56-63.
Cf., my lecture supplement on this essay.
[6] Ralph
Baergen,
Contemporary Epistemology, op. cit., p. 123.
File revised on 10/08/2013.