Lecture Supplement on Descartes’ Sixth
Meditation[1]
Copyright © 2018 Bruce W. Hauptli
The main problem in this
Meditation is: “Does material substance exist?” or, perhaps better, “Can
we know that material substance exists?”
To provide an answer, he offers two
proofs: an initial, or tentative one; and a second, more careful, one.
After these proofs, Descartes distinguishes what we are “taught by
nature” from what is known via the
“natural light,” and discusses the composite of the body and mind which we call
the “self”—what I will call the “body-mind.”
While it is natural to focus attention on the proof(s) regarding material
substance, it is profitable to briefly hold on to what may well be a
non-standard reading, and consider that this
Meditation might well be considered to be primarily about the
science of “psychology” rather than about the “physical sciences.”
Thus far we have seen Descartes claim that the self exists, that it is,
essentially, a thinking thing, that it has several faculties (notably
understanding and
willing), that “agent-causation”
applies to it (though the extent of this is still under scrutiny), and that it
is finite. In this Meditation
we learn much more about the self, or mind—(and such learning, surely, falls
under the general banner [now] of psychology).
In this Meditation we learn
about two other “faculties:”
imagination and perception,
we learn that it is in our perceptions of
pleasure and
pain (that is, certain of our “ideas”) that we get our best
knowledge about the “external world” (which causes these ideas as they can not
be caused either by us or by his deity), and that these “perceptions” are
fallible, and
caused by “other things.”
As is the case with the wax experiment (though Descartes does not note
this here as he does there), what we learn with the greatest certainty is things
about our minds, and what is less (far, far less) “certain” is any understanding
of “bodies.”
(A) He begins with a
“tentative” proof which holds that our
faculty of imagination shows that
material things
probably exist.
92 “...imagination...appears to
be a certain application of the knowing faculty to a body immediately present to
it, which therefore exists.”
-92-93 Distinguish understanding
and imagining triangles, on the one hand, and understanding and imagining
“chiligons” (one thousand sided figures), on the other.
Consider also the case of pentagons.
We can see that [94] “...a particular sort of effort on the part of the mind is necessary in
order to imagine, one that I do not employ in order to understand.”
-93 “...this
power of imagination...is not required for my own essence....”
-Thus,
there is something different from the mind upon which this faculty depends.
“...were a body to exist
to which a mind is so joined that it may apply itself in order, as it were, to
look at it any time it wishes, it could happen that it is by means of
this body that I imagine corporeal things.
As a result, this mode of thinking may differ from pure intellection only
in the sense that the mind, when it understands, in a sense turns toward itself
and looks at one of the ideas that are in it; whereas when it imagines, it turns
toward the body, and intuits in the body something that conforms to an idea
either understood by the mind or perceived by sense.”
“To be sure, I easily understand
that the imagination can be actualized in this way, provided a body does exist.
And since I can think of no other way of explaining imagination that is
equally appropriate, I make a probable conjecture from this that a body exists.”
-Note the more reserved
conclusion—compare his claim here with his knowledge of self, his deity,
mathematics, or (again) of his deity!
-Note, also that there is here
the kernel of the contemporary epistemological notion of inference to the best
available explanation.[2]
Problem: we might imagine other explanations [which don’t seem to
require bodies], and so we need a more careful consideration and a better
argument.
(B) The “second,” and
more careful, proof:
removing the reasons for doubting:
94 “...I will review...all the
things I previously believed to be true because I had perceived them by means of
the senses and the causes I had for thinking this.
Next I will assess the causes why I called them into doubt.
Finally, I will consider what I must now believe about these things.”
1. What he believed and why—that his “sensory” ideas truly represented
“things:”
-“…I sensed that I had a head,
hands, feet, and other members that comprised this body which I viewed as part
of me, or perhaps, even as the whole of me.
I sensed that this body was found among many other bodies....”
-“...these ideas came upon me
utterly without my consent, to the extent that, wish as I may, I could not sense
any object unless it was present to a sense organ.
Nor could I fail to sense it when it was present.
And since the ideas perceived by sense were much more vivid and explicit
and even, in their own way, more distinct that any of those that I deliberately
and knowingly formed through mediation or that I found impressed on my memory,
it seemed impossible that they came from myself.
Thus the remaining alternative was that they came from other things.
Since I had no knowledge of such things except from those same ideas
themselves, I could not help entertaining the thought that they were similar to
those ideas.”
95
2. Why he doubted:
-Perceptual problems: towers
from afar; external and internal senses subject to error—phantom limb pains;
dreaming; and the evil genius.
-95-96 “As to arguments that
used to convince me of the truth of sensible things, I found no difficulty
responding to them. For since I
seemed driven by nature toward many things about which reason tried to dissuade
me, I did not think that what I was taught by nature deserved much credence.
And even though the perceptions of the senses did not depend on my will,
I did not think that we must therefore conclude that they carry from things
distinct from me, since perhaps there is some faculty in me, as yet unknown to
me, that produces these perceptions.”
96
3. Why these doubts should now be
rejected:
“But now, having begun to have a
better knowledge of myself and the author of my origin, I am of the opinion that
I must not rashly admit everything that I seem to derive from my senses; but
neither, for that matter, should I call everything into doubt.”
-(i) “First, I know that all the
things that I clearly and distinctly understand can be made by God such as I
understand them. For this reason, my
ability clearly and distinctly to understand one thing without another suffices
to make me certain that the one thing is different from the other, since they
can be separated from each other, at least by God.”
-(ii) Mind and body are (clearly
and distinctly) separable—body is no part of my essence.
-(iii) The
faculties of imagining and perceiving
are distinct from me—as are the faculties of motion and taking on shape.
-96-97 (iv) “But it is clear
that these faculties, if in fact they exist, must be in a corporeal or extended
substance, not in a substance endowed with understanding.
For some extension is contained in a clear and distinct concept of them,
though certainly not any understanding.
Now there clearly is in me a
passive faculty of sensing, that is, a faculty for receiving and knowing the
ideas of sensible things; but I could not use it unless there also existed,
either in me or in something else, a
certain active faculty of producing or bringing about these ideas.”
-97 (v)
This active faculty can not be in me
[that is, in me essentially and
insofar as I am a thinking thing]—it does not presuppose thought and the ideas
in question are frequently caused against my will.
-(vi) “Therefore
the only alternative is that it is in some substance different from me
containing either formally or eminently all the reality that exists objectively
in the ideas produced by that faculty....Hence, this substance is
either a body, that is, a corporeal
nature, which contains formally all that is contained objectively in the ideas,
or else it is God,
or some other creature more noble than a
body, which contains eminently all that is contained objectively in the
ideas.”
-(vii) His
deity can not be the substance in which
this active faculty inheres (because he is not a deceiver) and, therefore,
it must exist in
bodies.
--“For since God has given me no
faculty whatsoever for making this determination, but instead has given me a
great inclination to believe these ideas issue from corporeal things, I fail to
see how God could be understood not to be a deceiver, if these ideas were to
issue from a source other than corporeal things.
And consequently corporeal things exist.”
(C).
We are taught “by nature”
about bodies (and about the
“body-mind”):
97 Regarding “particular” claims
regarding corporeal bodies (that the sun is of such and such a size, what light,
sound, and pain are, etc.), we can reach some understanding: in such cases, we
are “taught by nature:”
Descartes discusses, in order of
“clarity,” a number of things which are disclosed “by
nature.” Here we see why he is
ultimately willing to assign significant
epistemological authority to this sort of “teaching:”
and surely there is
no doubt that all that I am taught by
nature has some truth to it; for
by “nature,” taken generally, I
understand nothing other than God himself or the ordered network of created
things which was instituted by God….
The
first thing he is so taught is that:
“there is nothing that this nature
teaches me more explicitly than that I have a body that is ill-disposed when
I feel pain, that needs food and drink when I suffer hunger or thirst, and the
like. Therefore, I should not doubt
that there is some truth in this.”
98
Secondly, he maintains he is taught
by nature that “…I by means of these sensations of pain, hunger, thirst and so
on, nature also teaches not merely that I am present to my body in the way a
sailor is present in a ship, but that I
am most tightly joined and, so to speak, commingled with it, so much so that
I and the body constitute one single thing.”
-In her “Cartesian Passions: The
Ultimate Incoherence,” Marjorie Grene may go further than Descartes does here
maintaining that for him we know the mind
and body: “...by natural light, but [the union of the mind and body] only through
that ‘natural impulse’ which
Descartes has warned us in the Third Meditation has so often misled us, not only
in the search for truth but in the choice of goods.
It seems predestined, therefore, that the interrelations of mind and
body, the events of our lives as united minds and bodies, that our human
histories, in short, and therefore our human
being, can be comprehended only in
this relatively obscure, non-scientific and instinctive rather than in that
luminous, intellectual way. As
Descartes emphasizes, the union of the body and mind is accessible to us, not
through science, but through the experience of ordinary life; and it is
precisely the experience of everyday life that has been definitively undermined
in the programmatic doubt of Meditation One, followed by the demonstration in
Meditation Two of its incurable confusion.”[3]
Thirdly, nature teaches me that
my body is surrounded by other bodies.
Finally, “...there are many
other things that I seem to have been
taught by nature; nevertheless it was not really nature that taught them to
me but a certain habit of making reckless judgments.
And thus it could easily happen that these judgments are false....to
ensure that my perceptions in this matter are sufficiently distinct,
I ought to define more precisely what
exactly I mean when I say that I am “taught something by nature.”
We are “taught by nature” to:
-99 avoid things that produce
sensations of pain,
-pursue things that produce
sensations of pleasure,
-“but it does not appear that
nature teaches us to conclude anything besides these things, from these sense
perceptions unless the intellect has first conducted its own inquiry regarding
things external to us. For it seems
to belong exclusively to the mind, and not to the composite of mind and body, to
know the truth in these matters.”
-“...I use the perceptions of
the senses (which are properly given by nature only for signifying to the mind
what things are useful or harmful to the composite of which it is a part, and to
the extent that they are clear and distinct enough) as reliable rules for
immediately discerning what is the essence of bodies located outside us.
Yet they signify nothing about that except quite obscurely and
confusedly.”
-I may be mistaken even about
pleasure and pain—pleasant taste and poison, the ill who desire food or drink
which will make them worse! This
means that this “knowledge” is not the same sort of knowledge as that which he
gets when he confines himself to the mental domain!
100 While a poorly designed
clock doesn’t tell time well, we can not conclude that our bodies have been
poorly designed (that they don’t “tell well” the nature of external things).
To see that his deity is not to be “blamed” for misconstruction, we must
better understand the mind, body, and
body-mind.
100-101 Bodies are divisible,
minds are indivisible,
-101 the mind is not affected by
the whole body, but only by the brain,
-the body is a composite such
that “remote” movements require “intermediate” movements, and the sensory
“results” could be achieved by the intermediate movements only (pain “in foot”
requires transmission through intermediates, which could alone cause the pain).
-102 “...notwithstanding
the immense goodness of God, the nature of man, insofar as it is composed of
mind and body, cannot help being sometimes mistaken.
For if some cause, not in the foot but in some other part through which
the nerves extend from the foot to the brain, or perhaps even in the brain
itself, were to produce the same motion that would normally be produced by a
badly injured foot, the pain will be felt as if it were in the foot, and the
senses will naturally be deceived.”
Ditto, of course, for “dryness of the throat” in an ill individual.
-103 “...I know that all
the senses set forth what is true more
frequently than what is false regarding what concerns the welfare of the body.
Moreover, I can nearly always make use of several of them to examine the
same thing. Furthermore, I can use
my memory, which connects current happenings with past ones, and my intellect,
which now has examined all the causes of error.
Hence I should no longer fear that those things that are daily shown me
by the senses are false. On the
contrary, the hyperbolic doubts of the
last few days ought to be rejected as ludicrous.”
--“This
goes especially for the chief reason for doubting, which dealt with my failure
to distinguish being asleep from being awake.
For I now notice that there is a considerable difference between these
two; dreams are never joined by the memory with the other actions of life, as is
the case with those actions that occur when one is awake....and when I connect
my perception of them with the rest of my life, I am clearly certain that these
perceptions have happened to me not while I was dreaming but while I was awake.
Nor ought I have even the least doubt regarding the truth of these
things, if, having mustered all the senses, in addition to my memory and my
intellect, in order to examine them, nothing is passed on to me by one of those
sources that conflicts with the others.
For from the fact that God is no
deceiver, it follows that I am in no way mistaken in these matters.
But because the need to get things done does not always permit us the
leisure for such a careful inquiry, we must confess that the life of man is apt
to commit errors regarding particular things, and we must acknowledge the
infirmity of our nature.”
[1] This supplement,
and the others for Descartes’
Meditations on First Philosophy, reference
the pages in Donald A. Cress’ translation in
René
Descartes: Discourse on Method and Meditations
on First Philosophy, Fourth Edition
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1998.
They were developed over 40 years of
teaching, however, and the citations are
sometimes to other translations.
In
addition emphasis (italics, underlines, and
bolding are regularly added to citations to help
direct your attention.
[2]
Cf.,
Gilbert Harman,
Thought
(Princeton: Princeton U.P., 1973) His discussion
on pp. 130-141, and 155-172 provides a concise
account of this orientation.
[3] Marjorie Grene,
“Cartesian Passions: The Ultimate Incoherence,”
in her
Descartes (Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota,
1985), pp. 23-52, p. 33.
Emphasis is added to the passage.
Go to my Supplement Concluding the course.
Email: hauptli@fiu.edu
Last revised: 04/25/18.