Lecture Supplement on Dewey’s
“Intelligence and Morals” [1908][1]
Copyright © 2021
Bruce W. Hauptli
In contrast to his “The Ethics of Democracy” [1888] which
is rooted in his Hegelian Idealism, this essay written twenty years later is
rooted in Dewey’s pragmatic theory.
He wants to free us from a philosophical propensity to focus attention in moral
thought upon the transcendent, absolute, and
a priori and, instead focus attention
on human practices in the natural and social environments.
In
her “Dewey’s Moral Philosophy,” Elizabeth Anderson maintains that:
Dewey's ethics replaces the goal
of identifying an ultimate end or supreme principle that can serve as a
criterion of ethical evaluation with the goal of identifying a method for
improving our value judgments. Dewey
argued that ethical inquiry is of a piece with empirical inquiry more generally.
It is the use of reflective intelligence
to revise one's judgments in light of the consequences of acting on them.
Value judgments are tools for enabling
the satisfactory redirection of conduct when habit no longer suffices to direct
it. As tools, they can be evaluated
instrumentally, in terms of their success in guiding conduct.
We test our value judgments by putting
them into practice and seeing whether the results are satisfactory—whether they
solve the problems they were designed to solve, whether we find their
consequences acceptable, whether they enable successful responses to novel
problems, whether living in accordance with alternative value judgments yields
more satisfactory results. We achieve
moral progress and maturity to the extent that we adopt habits of reflectively
revising our value judgments in response to the widest consequences for everyone
of living them out. This pragmatic
approach requires that we locate the conditions of warrant for our value
judgments in human conduct itself, not in any a priori fixed reference
point outside of conduct, such as in God’s commands, Platonic Forms, pure
reason, or “nature,” considered as giving humans a fixed telos.
To do so requires that we understand
different types of value judgments in functional terms, as forms of conduct that
play distinctive roles in the life of reflective, social beings.
Dewey thereby offers a naturalistic
metaethic of value judgments, grounded in developmental and social psychology.[2]
He believed that
the new social conditions arising in in the United States, and throughout the
world, required a new form of social theory.
We begin the selection with a cursory discussion of Greek, Feudal, and
Renaissance philosophical thought patterns and the development of a “democratic
polity, commercial expansion, and scientific reorganization.”
Dewey sees the development here as a “liberation” or “emancipation,” but
believes we need a [philosophical] theory for our new practices.
According to him:
67 theory may therefore become
responsible to the practices that have generated it; the good [should] be connected with
nature, but with nature naturally, not metaphysically, conceived, and social
life [should] be cherished in behalf of its own immediate possibilities, not on the
ground of its remote connections with cosmic reason and absolute end.
He points out that while many believe that Greek thought
surrendered the individual to the state, it is more true to say that
[67] none has ever known better
than the Greek that the individual comes to himself and to his own only in
association with others. But Greek
thought subjected…both state and individual to an external cosmic order; and
thereby it inevitably restricted the free use in doubt, inquiry and
experimentation of human intelligence.
I believe it is important to emphasize here that he concurs
with the Greek emphasis on our social nature (that "individuals come into
themselves only in association with others"). His "biological view does
not conceive of us as "atomic individuals" (separable from others), but as
social creatures who can only live a "good life" in the company of others--but
more will be made of this further later. The passage emphasizes, instead,
that as
attention shifted from the fixed and static to the natural, science could
develop. Because it began to
take motion and change as natural and worthy of study, industry has become truly
useful:
68-69 the industrial life had
been condemned by Greek exaltation of abstract thought and by Greek contempt for
labor as representing the brute struggle of carnal appetite for its own satiety.
The industrial movement, offspring of science, restored it to its central
position in morals. When Adam Smith
made economic activity the moving spring of man’s unremitting effort…to better
his own lot, he recorded this change.
And when he made sympathy the central spring in man’s conscious moral
endeavor, he reported the effect which the increasing intercourse of men, due
primarily to commerce, had in breaking down suspicion and jealousy and in
liberating man’s kinder impulses.
This transformation from attending to the fixed,
unchanging, and final, to attending to the changing, industrial, and social lays
a foundation for
democracy:
[69] democracy is an absurdity
where faith in the individual as individual is impossible; and this faith is
impossible where intelligence is regarded as a cosmic power, not an adjustment
and application of individual tendencies.
It is also impossible when appetite and desires are conceived to be the
dominant /factor in the constitution of most men’s character, and when appetite
and desire are conceived to the manifestations of the disorderly and unruly
principle of nature.
Against Plato, then, Dewey would refocus our attention on
the changing world and the application of human intelligence to the dynamic
social lives of human beings. But
he does not believe the progress we have made over the period has been smooth
and orderly. On pp. 69-73 he
discusses utilitarianism and French thinkers who endeavored to create social
systems which would “force” individuals to pursue the welfare of others, and
German idealists and transcendentalists who looked for “natural laws” which
would govern social and moral affairs.
As he sees it these thinkers effectively continued the classical search for a single,
final good which would provide a moral force that could govern and perfect human
beings. Dewey thinks that this sort
of theory continues the mistakes of the ancient thinkers:
[73] the transformation in
attitude, to which I referred, is the growing belief that the proper business of
intelligence is discrimination of multiple and present goods and of the varied
immediate means of their realization; not search for one remote aim.
The progress of biology has accustomed our minds to the notion that
intelligence is not an outside power presiding supremely but statically over the
desires and efforts of man, but is a method of adjustment of capacities and
conditions within specific situations.
Instead of trying to provide a fixed body of moral rules
and a single final end, ethics should
[73-74] …utilize physiology,
anthropology and psychology to discover all that can be discovered of man, his
organic powers and propensities….its business is not to search for the one
separate moral motive, it is to converge all the instrumentalities of the social
arts, of law, education, economics and political science upon the construction
of intelligent methods of improving the common lot.
Dewey believes that the transformation he is recommending
doesn’t lessen the role for reason (or, better, intelligence).
To see how this can be the case, however, we need to understand that
Dewey rejects the conception of nature as something which is unchangeable,
fixed, and deductively rational. In
place of this view he substitutes a view which sees natural laws as
[74-75] …convenient formulations
of selected portions of change followed through a longer or shorter period of
time, and then registered in statistical forms that are amenable to mathematical
manipulation….Knowledge of nature does not mean subjection to predestination,
but insight into courses of change; and insight which is formulated in “laws.”
That is methods of subsequent procedure.
Knowledge of the processes and conditions of physical and social change
through experimental science and genetic history has one result with a double
name: increase of control and increase of responsibility; increase of power to
direct natural change, and increase of responsibility for its equitable
direction toward fuller good.
[76] Dewey ends by contending that the motive [or sanction]
for morality is that humans seek “…the consent of their kind.”
We will see that the importance of our social nature is, here, a key to
his moral theory and its defense of democracy.
[1] John
Dewey, “Intelligence and Morals,” first
published in his
Ethics
(NY: Columbia U.P., 1908).
It is revised and reprinted
The
Influence of Darwin on Philosophy [1910],
and appears
The
Middle Works, v. 4.
The selection we are discussing appears
in John
Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra
Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1993), pp. 66-77.
The page references here refer to this
reprint and emphasis has sometimes been added to
the passages.
[2] Elizabeth
Anderson, “Dewey’s Moral Philosophy,”
The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dewey-moral/,
accessed 04/21/17.
Go to Midcoast Senior College Webpage
File revised on 10/13/21