Introductory Lecture on John Dewey
Copyright © 2021 Bruce W. Hauptli
Dewey lived in the period between the Civil War and the Korean
War (1859-1952), and was born the year that Charles Darwin’s
Origin of the Species was published.
During this time period the United States moved from being a largely
agricultural and rural country to a largely industrial and urban country.
The Burlington Vermont of Dewey’s youth was an industrialized and
urbanized town, but there were immense social changes in the country during
Dewey’s life. In his
John Dewey and the High Tide of American
Liberalism, Alan Ryan notes that there are marked similarities between
Dewey’s America and our own:
...Dewey was moved to write about
individual unease and social and political failures in a context that resembles
our own in crucial ways. Dewey’s
America was one in which the problems of the inner city were appalling.
In the early 1890s homelessness in Chicago sometimes reached 20 percent;
unemployment frequently hit one in four of the working population.
Disease was rife, and medical services were out of the reach of the
poor....The upper classes were apparently indifferent to the fate of the poor
and even to the fate of the working near poor.
In the cities the response of the better-off was to remove themselves to
the suburbs....[1]
Dewey was a social activist (though
some would have him be more active to qualify for the term) as well as a
theoretical philosopher. As Cornell
West notes, for Dewey
...philosophy is neither a form of
knowledge nor a means to acquire knowledge.
Rather philosophy is a mode of cultural critical action that focuses on
the ways and means by which human beings have, do, and can overcome obstacles,
dispose of predicaments, and settle problematic situations.[2]
The importance of “social activism” for Dewey can be gauged by
the organizations he helped found among which are: The American Civil Liberties
Union, The American Association of University Professors, and the New York City
Teachers Union. Another (although
much disputed) measure of his activism is his influence on the American
educational system. The “Lab
School” at the University of Chicago (1896-1904) was Dewey’s creation.
As West notes,
the aim of the school was not only
to serve as a model of how meaningful and enriching education could take place,
but also to make a practical intervention into the national debate on education.
This practical intervention was, for Dewey, a form of political activism
in that the struggle over knowledge and over the means of its disposal was a
struggle about power, about the conditions under which cultural capital (skills,
knowledge, and values) was produced, distributed, and consumed.
In sharp contrast to curriculum-centered conservatives and child-centered
romantics, Dewey advocated an interactive model of functionalistic education
that combined autonomy with intelligent and flexible guidance, relevance with
rigor and wonder. Of course,
Dewey’s functionalistic education, a critical education for democratizing
society, could easily be mistaken for a functional education, a fitting
education that simply adjusts one to the labor market possibilities.[3]
In his The Metaphysical
Club, Louis Menand maintains that:
Dewey’s pragmatism was a consequence
of the success of the Laboratory School.
The school established for him the validity of his hypothesis
that thinking and acting are just two names for a single process—the process of
making our way as best we can in a universe shot through with contingency.
It also showed him what was wrong with philosophy, and Dewey’s career
after Chicago can be divided into two parts: from his arrival at Columbia until
the United States entered the war in 1917, he defended pragmatism against the
arguments of other philosophers....From the war until the end of his life, he
addressed the issues of his time in a pragmatist spirit.
Philosophers, Dewey argued, had mistakenly insisted on making a problem
of the relation between the mind and the world, an obsession that had given rise
to what he called “the alleged
discipline of epistemology”—the attempt to answer the question, How do we know?
The pragmatist response to this question is to point out that nobody has
ever made a problem about the relation between, for example, the hand and the
world. The function of the hand
is to help the organism cope with the environment; in situations in which a hand
doesn’t work, we try something else, such as a foot, or a fishhook, or an
editorial. Nobody worries in these
situations about a lack of some preordained “fit”—about whether the physical
world was or was not made to be manipulated by hands.
They just use a hand where a hand will do.
Dewey thought that ideas and
beliefs are the same as hands: instruments for coping.
An idea has no greater metaphysical stature than, say, a fork.
When your fork proves inadequate to the task of eating soup, it makes
little sense to argue about whether there is something inherent in the nature of
soup that accounts for the failure.
You just reach for a spoon. But
philosophers have worried about whether the mind is such that the world can be
known by it, and they have produced all sorts of accounts of how the “fit” is
supposed to work—how the mental represents the real.
Dewey’s point was that “mind” and “reality,” are like “stimulus” and
“response,” names for nonexistent entities: they are abstractions from a single,
indivisible process.[4]
It should not be surprising, then,
that Dewey’s activism was a consistent part of his life, and it is consistent
with his “theoretical philosophy.”
He maintained that philosophy is the intellectual expression of conflicts in
culture, and he maintained that the main
task for philosophy in his day was to find a solution to the divisive and
destructive cleavage between science (or “facts”) and values:
the problem of restoring integration
and cooperation between man’s beliefs about the world in which he lives and his
beliefs about the values and purposes that should direct his conduct is the
deepest problem of modern life. It
is the problem of any philosophy that is not isolated from that life.[5]
Philosophy is called upon to be the
theory of the practice, through ideas sufficiently definite to be operative in
experimental endeavor, by which the integration may be made secure in actual
experience. Its central problem is
the relation that exists between the beliefs about the nature of things due to
natural science and beliefs about values—using that word to designate whatever
is taken to have rightful authority in the direction of conduct.[6]
Dewey’s Early
Philosophical Orientation:
In his [early] intellectual autobiography (“From Absolutism to
Experimentalism”), Dewey says that “social interests and problems from an early
period had to me the intellectual appeal and provided the intellectual
sustenance that many seem to have found primarily in religious questions.”[7]
He identifies four main aspects of his intellectual development: (a) the
importance of the practice and theory of education; (b) the scandal involved in
the dualism (of both the logic and method) of science and morals;[8]
(c) the importance of William James’
Psychology;[9]
and (d) a recognition of the importance of social categories.
As Gail Kennedy notes:
when Dewey was an undergraduate,
during the late seventies, at the University of Vermont, philosophy was still in
what Professor Morris Cohen has called its “glacial age.”
The Scottish “common-sense realism” introduced into this country before
the Revolution by President Witherspoon of Princeton was designed primarily as a
defense of Christian faith against the deism, materialism, and scepticism of the
eighteenth century. Favored by the
peculiar American combination of church and college, it became here the orthodox
academic philosophy grafted on to Protestantism.
For a hundred years it was taught in virtually all the New England
colleges as an arid and abstract rationalization of theological doctrines.[10]
It was in this tradition that Dewey began his philosophical
studies. After graduation, he
taught high school in Oil City, Pennsylvania and Charlotte, Vermont.
He read German and German philosophers (especially Kant and Hegel) with
one of his Vermont professors and submitted essays
to The Journal of Speculative Philosophy
(“The Metaphysical Assumptions of Materialism,” and “The Pantheism of Spinoza”).
He then went to Johns Hopkins for two years where he studied German
Idealism (with George Morris) and developed a life-long interest in psychology
(through his studies with G. Stanley Hall).
As Kennedy notes, the “German Idealism” which attracted Dewey:
...was a better means of defending
religious traditions and of putting science in its proper subordinate place that
German idealism came so rapidly to supplant the moribund Scotch [sic] realism
within academic halls. Here was a
way, it seemed, by which one could keep the faith and believe in “evolution”
too....What interested him was Hegel’s treatment of human culture, of
institutions and the arts. In
Hegelian idealism, and particularly in Thomas Hill Green’s version of it, Dewey
found...a basis for his social idealism....Dewey, then, at this stage was, like
Marx, a “left-wing Hegelian” (though they developed very differently).
Each of them thought he had found in Hegel the clue to the means of
utilizing the results of science in the interests of social progress.[11]
In 1884 Dewey began teaching at the
University of Michigan. He moved
from Michigan to the University of Minnesota and then back to Michigan.
Throughout this period Dewey worked on Kant, Hegel, and T.H. Green, and
on psychological issues. As Kennedy
notes:
...Dewey was attempting what he
later realized to be impossible, a consistent synthesis of his Hegelian idealism
with the results of science. He was
trying to bring the experimentalism of Hall within the framework of his own
metaphysics.[12]
In 1890 William James’s
Principles of Psychology appeared and
had a profound influence upon Dewey.
In his
Philosophy and Civilization
[1931] Dewey maintains that two
fundamental theses of James’ were highly influential upon the development of his
instrumentalism:
the one is a reinterpretation of
introspective psychology, in which James denies that sensations, images, and
ideas are discrete and in which he replaces them by a continuous stream which he
calls “the stream of consciousness.”
This conception necessitates a consideration of relations as an immediate
part of the field of consciousness, having the same status as qualities....[and
this leads to James’ criticism]...of the atomism of Locke and Hume as well as
the a priorism of the synthesis of
rational principles by Kant and his successors....
The other aspect...is of a biological nature.
It shows itself in its full force in the criterion which James
established for discovering the essence of mind.
“The pursuance of future ends and the choice of means for their
attainment are thus the mark and criterion of the presence of mentality in a
phenomenon.”[13]
Dewey found in James the basis for his instrumentalism in a
manner which allowed him to fuse his Hegelian view that the workings of mind are
objectively expressed in social traditions and institutions with his
evolutionary views.[14]
While it took Dewey a while to free himself from his Hegelian idealism,
he replaced it with a naturalistic orientation which treated idealism as an
example of what he came to call “the intellectualist fallacy” of treating the
real as both known and firmly fixed.
Dewey’s Theory of
Inquiry:
Dewey’s view of inquiry was heavily influenced by Darwinian
biology. The theory of inquiry
offers an “organic” conception of thought and action—it takes
organic interaction as its basic
notion. That is, it emphasizes the
organism, the
environment,
and the
interaction between them.
According to this theory, this interaction often yields a
tension (either discrete or continuous) which, in turn, leads to
efforts to resolve the tension so as to “return to” an
equilibrium state. The
first step in a thoughtful inquiry process is the
specification of the initial problem.
This is important since the problematic situation is, initially,
indeterminate.
This may be done either by habit
or by thought.
In thoughtful inquiry the
problem is specified, the conditions in the environment are examined in light of
the specified problem, a hypothesis is formed, its consequences are examined,
and, then, the hypothetical action is either undertaken or the process begins
anew.
Human beings, for Dewey, are neither
primarily souls nor are they primarily matter.
Instead, they are creatures of
habit and instinct inhabiting a world
which is neither malevolent nor benevolent.
At times, human habitual ways of functioning are insufficient (they reach
impasses where their habits break down).
At these times human beings pause to consider which way to turn.
Dewey’s instrumentalism holds that mind
or intelligence develops from and is an instrument for problem-solving.
Dewey rejects the “spectator” view of knowledge (which holds that our
knowledge or beliefs are to “mirror” the essential, and unchanging, character of
the world) and believes that our experimental processes are piecemeal
processes—they proceed gradually, and their results are temporary.
Dewey did not offer an exclusive
emphasis upon the “practical” side of our lives however.
He also emphasized the importance of the aesthetic experiences of human
beings. He characterized aesthetic
experience as immediate, individualized, and consummatory or final.
Religious experience for him is an especially intense aesthetic one.
As we shall see his discussion of
consummatory experience is crucial to his project of integrating facts and
values.
Thought and Action:
Like the other pragmatists, Dewey emphasizes the relationship
between thought and action. He
preferred to term his pragmatism an “instrumentalism”
(or “experimentalism”) however.
In his “The Influence of Darwinism on Philosophy,”
The Quest for Certainty, and
Experience and Nature, Dewey
emphasizes how the pragmatic philosophy differs from the classical philosophical
orientations. In the former article
he argues that we can seek knowledge either in something transcendent or in the
mutual interaction of things. The
change from the traditional orientation (which sought knowledge in the
transcendent) to the orientation which Dewey recommends (which seeks knowledge
in the mutual interaction of things) is a change which moves from “purpose” to
“significance” (signs) and it is exemplified by the change in the science of
biology from the teleological orientation of Aristotle to Darwinistic
significance considerations. Dewey
believed that the new (practical or instrumental) procedures of thought should
not be merely confined to our scientific or epistemological thinking.
He maintained that they should characterize our moral, political, and
educational thinking also.
In his
Philosophy and Civilization Dewey maintains that a central differentiation between
instrumentalism or pragmatism, on the one hand, and traditional empiricism, on
the other, is that the former is forward-looking (looking at “consequent”
phenomena) rather than backward-looking (looking at “antecedent” phenomena).[15]
He goes on to maintain that this shows that pragmatism or instrumentalism
has metaphysical implications:
pragmatism thus has a metaphysical implication.
The doctrine of the value of
consequences leads us to take the future into consideration.
And this taking into consideration of the future takes us to the
conception of a universe whose evolution is not finished, of a universe which is
still, in James’ term, “in the making,” “in the process of becoming,” of a
universe up to a certain point still plastic.[16]
Given that he believes that the traditional philosophical
orientations asked bad questions, Dewey holds that the “reconstruction of
philosophy” which he recommends leads to the disappearance” or “evaporation” of
the old questions.[17]
Dewey and Realism:
Dewey’s instrumentalism and his conception of reality as
plastic diverges significantly from the sort of German Idealism which he adhered
to early in his philosophical career (as he, of course, makes quite clear in his
“From Absolutism to Experimentalism”).
In his “The Realism of Pragmatism” [1905] Dewey claims that:
instrumentalism is thus thoroughly
realistic as to the objective of fulfilling conditions of knowledge.
States of consciousness, sensations and ideas as cognitive, exist as
tools, bridges, cues, functions...to affect a realistic presentation of things
in which there are no intervening states of consciousness as veils or
representatives. Known things, as
known, are direct presentations in the most diaphanous medium conceivable.
And if getting knowledge, as distinct from having it, involves
representatives, pragmatism carries with it a reinterpretation, and a realistic
interpretation, of ‘states of consciousness’ as representations.
They are practically or effectively, not transcendentally representative.
They represent in the sense in which a signature, for legal purposes,
represents a real person....They are symbols, in short, and are known and used
as such.[18]
According to Ernest Nagel, “naive realism” (the view that the
world is made up of sheep, clouds, rainbows, and trees), is undercut by
“scientific realism” (the view that reality is made up of atoms, fields, and
forces), but this appears to create a “paradox”:
...naive realism leads to physics,
but if physics is true then naive realism is false.
On this analysis, therefore, one is left with the choice of either
accepting natural science but rejecting as basically illusory the things that
constitute men’s most familiar and valued experience, or accepting the objective
character of common-sense views of things but denying the validity and relevance
of modern science for matters of prime human concern.”[19]
According to Nagel, Dewey resolves this “paradox:”
...the adequacy or validity of ideas
is not warranted by their supposed derivation from materials of sense, but
rather by the consequences of their use….The central thesis of Dewey’s theory of
science is that it does not disclose realms of being antithetical to the
familiar things of life, simply because scientific objects are formulations of
complex relations of dependence between things in sense experience...the
constructions of theoretical physics are viewed
as intellectual means of organizing the discontinuous occurrences of
directly experienced qualities, as ways of thinking about matters in gross
experience in order to obtain some measure of control....[20]
Of course, if Dewey’s experimentalism is committed to realism,
it is not anti-metaphysical. As we
look at his views in greater depth, we will have to look to see whether his
experimentalism (or naturalism, or pragmatism) can consistently offer the sort
of metaphysical theory which he advances.[21]
Dewey’s Theory of Value:
To bring this overly long introduction to an end, I must
briefly expand upon some earlier remarks about Dewey’s theory of value.
As I noted above, Dewey believes that some of our experiences have a
“consummatory” (or aesthetic) character.
Gail Kennedy maintains that after reading James, Dewey developed a
pragmatic (or naturalistic) theory which argued that:
...values and purposes are created
by man in his efforts to “adapt” himself to the world of nature and of society
within which he lives and moves and has his being.
What these values shall be is not predetermined by the appeal to some
antecedent reality or cosmic purpose.
They occur as effects or
products of the conflicts that arise and the choices which are made in the
particular situations of daily life....With man intelligence has reached a level
where he may, within the limits of the forces at his disposal, control the
future. But this is always a
piecemeal control and the ends-in-view of limited human beings must always vary
with the changing situation. Values
are altered as knowledge develops.
A philosophy which accepts this evolutionary definition of intelligence
thus “forswears enquiry after absolute origins and absolute finalities in order
to explore specific values and the specific conditions that generate them.”
If this is the role of philosophy, then method, the method of
intelligence is supreme. Philosophy
must “become a method of locating and interpreting the more serious of the
conflicts that occur in life and a method of projecting ways for dealing with
them: a method of moral and political diagnosis and prognosis.[22]
In short, for Dewey,
values are to be subjected to the same sort of future-oriented experimental
and instrumentalistic analysis as are
facts. Of course, given his
view of inquiry, and his “plastic” conception of reality, he is also committed
to the existence of meaningful freedom.
To come to understand Dewey’s theory of value and his view of democracy,
however, we must turn to our readings.
[1] Alan
Ryan,
John Dewey and the High Tide of American
Liberalism (New York: Norton, 1995), p. 24.
[2] Cornel
West, The
American Evasion of Philosophy (Madison:
University of Wisconsin, 1989), p. 86.
West is among those who would have liked
to see a more socially activist Dewey.
[3]
Ibid.,
p. 84.
[4] Louis
Menand,
The Metaphysical Club (N.Y.: Farrar, Straus
and Giroux, 2001), pp. 360-361.
[5] John
Dewey,
The Quest for Certainty [1929], reprinted as
v. 4 of
John Dewey: The Later Works, ed. Jo Ann
Boydston (Carbondale, Southern Illinois
University Press, 1988), p. 204.
A standard way of referring to Dewey’s
works is by citing the volume and page in the
collections
John
Dewey: The Early Works; John Dewey: The Middle
Works; or
John
Dewey: The Later Works (EW, MW, LW) all
edited by Boydston—here, then: LW 5: 204.
I will often do citations directly to the
original publications however.
[6]
Ibid.
[7] John
Dewey, “From Absolutism to Experimentalism” in
Contemporary American Philosophy v. 2, Adams
and Montague (eds.) (London: Unwin, 1903), pp.
13-27, p. 20.
[8] Dewey
says that it was this which led him to his
instrumentalism.
[9] Dewey
maintains that there is an underlying conflict
between James’ critique of earlier psychologies,
his retention of a subjectivism, and an
“objective” strain in James’ thought: “I may
cite as an illustration the substitution of the
“stream of consciousness” for discrete
elementary states: the advance made was
enormous.
Nevertheless the point of view remained
that of a realm of consciousness set off by
itself.
The other strain is objective, having its
roots in the return to the earlier biological
conception of the
psyche,
but a return possessed of a new force and value
due to the immense progress made by biology
since the time of Aristotle” (John Dewey, “From
Absolutism to Experimentalism,”
op. cit.,
p. 24).
[10] Gail
Kennedy, “Introduction” to the Dewey chapter, in
Classic
American Philosophers, ed. Max Fisch (New
York: Appleton, 1951), pp. 327-335, pp. 329-330.
[11]
Ibid.,
p. 331.
[12]
Ibid.
[13] John
Dewey,
Philosophy and Civilization (NY:
G.P. Putnam’s Sons, 1931).
The passage is in a reprint entitled:
“The Development of American Pragmatism,” in
Pragmatism: The Classic Writings, ed. H.S.
Thayer (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1982), pp. 35-36.
[14] Ryan
maintains that a decisive step in Dewey’s
philosophical development from absolutistic
German idealism to instrumentalistic
experimentalism was his publication in 1896 of
“The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology” (cf.,
Alan Ryan,
John
Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism,
op. cit.,
pp. 124-127.
[15] John
Dewey,
Philosophy and Civilization,
op. cit.,
pp. 32-33.
[16]
Ibid.,
p. 33.
[17]
Cf.,
John Dewey, “The Influence of Darwinism on
Philosophy,” in
Classic
American Philosophers, ed. Max Fisch, op.
cit., pp. 336-344, p. 344.
Cf.,
also, John Dewey,
Reconstruction in Philosophy (Boston:
Beacon, 1957 [originally published in 1920]).
[18] John
Dewey, “The Realism of Pragmatism,”
The
Journal of Philosophy (1905), pp. 324-327,
p. 325.
[19] Ernest
Nagel, “Dewey’s Theory of Natural Science,” in
John
Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom,
ed. Sidney Hook (York: Dial, 1950), pp. 233-234.
[20]
Ibid.,
p. 236.
[21] In his
“Dewey’s Naturalistic Metaphysics” (The
Journal of Philosophy v. 22 (1905), pp.
673-688), George Santayana maintains that
Dewey’s “metaphysics” is inconsistent with his
“naturalism.”
Richard Rorty offers a similar argument
in his “Dewey’s Metaphysics” (in
New
Studies in the Philosophy of John Dewey, ed.
Steven M. Cahn (Hanover: University of Vermont,
1977), pp. 45-69).
[22] Gail
Kennedy, “Introduction” to the Dewey chapter, in
Classic
American Philosophers, ed. Max Fisch,
op. cit.,
p. 333.
Kennedy cites Dewey’s “The Influence of
Darwin On Philosophy,”
op. cit.,
p. 341.
Go to Midcoast Senior College Webpage
File revised on 10/13/21