Introduction to Plato
Copyright © 2023 Bruce W. Hauptli
1. Plato’s Life and
the “Golden Age of Greece:”
Plato lived from ~428 to ~348 B.C.E.
His was one of the wealthy and politically powerful Athenian families,
and he was a student of Socrates (~470-399 B.C.E.).
While Plato uses Socrates as the “protagonist” of many of his dialogues,
we can not just assume that Plato’s Socrates (the “character” in the dialogues
we will read) takes the “positions” and makes the “claims” which were taken and
made by the historical Socrates. At
the least, there is likely a large degree of convergence for the earliest of
Plato’s dialogues. Before we read
him, however, we should carefully consider their character at the time they were
written. In his “Plato,” Gilbert
Ryle maintains that:
no contemporary testimony tells
us how Plato and the many other writers of dialogues published their
compositions. Nor have scholars
given much consideration to the matter.
What follows is a hypothesis, based on a lot of little individually
tenuous clues. There was, of
course, no printing in ancient Greece.
Compositions published in book form[1]
were individually written by scribes.
There is the evidence of silence from Plato, Isocrates, and others that
in Plato’s day there were no libraries.
Very likely there were no bookshops displaying stocks of ready-made
handwritten books. We do not hear
of anyone browsing in such a bookshop until half a century after Plato’s death.
The number of individual collectors of books must have been very small.
Reading books was a fairly rare thing.
Inside the Academy itself, the young Aristotle seems to have acquired the
nickname “Reader” because he was exceptional in being a voracious reader.
The normal mode of publishing a composition, whether in verse or prose,
was oral delivery to an audience.
Conjecturally, the compositions of dialogue writers, including Plato,
Antisthenes, Xenophon, and Aristotle, were no exception.
The public got to know a new dialogue by hearing the author recite it.
Normally, Plato orally delivered the words of his dramatic Socrates.
The dialogues were dramatic in form because they were composed for
semi-dramatic recitation to lay and drama-loving audiences, consisting largely
of young men. A dialogue had
therefore to be short enough not to tax the endurance of its audience.
The only two mammoth dialogues...must have been intended for special
audiences that would reassemble time after time to hear the successive
installments.[2]
Clearly, we need to stand back from these works and
consider the time in which they were written as we study them!
I believe that Plato wrote his dialogues for a pedagogic purpose.
In his Orators and Philosophers: A
History of the Idea of Liberal Education, Bruce Kimball maintains that:
many generations prior to the
“pedagogical century,” the Hellenic concept of education had been founded upon
the pursuit of
aretē[3]
(excellence or virtue) defined according to the code of valor of the
Attic-Ionian aristocracy. Central
to this program was the recitation of Homeric epic poetry, both to
provide technical instruction in language and, more importantly, to inculcate
the knightly mores and noble ethic of the culture.
Upon the disintegration of this tradition with the rise of democracy in
the fifth century B.C.E., three principal groups responded with programs of
education to prepare the free citizens for their new role in governing society.
...Gorgias, Protagoras, Prodicus, and Hippias, taught the skills of
composing, delivering, and analyzing a speech....These individuals acquired the
name “wise man” or “teacher” (sophistēs),
for they claimed to teach a kind of
wisdom (sophia) or
aretē [virtue]
that was political: the ideal
methods for making one’s point and winning arguments, that is, for participating
in the democratic city-state....
Teaching next to Plato and sharing his concern over the deterioration of
Athenian mores was Isocrates
(436-338), who offered a third response both in his school and in his
writings—chiefly Against the Sophists
and Antidosis.
Though often identified with the sophists, he is more properly
distinguished from that group, as Plato acknowledged.
This is because Isocrates
criticized the sophists for their emphasis on rhetorical display and technique
at the expense of character ideals while he adopted, with very little analysis,
the noble values of the past—the traditional standards of virtue recognized in
epical heroes—as the aretē of his
educational ideal. Isocrates thus
extolled the orator who would live out the noble virtues and persuade the free
citizen of the democratic city-state to adhere to them.[4]
To clarify the Greek history before Plato’s time further,
in his Battling the Gods: Atheism In The
Ancient World, Tim Whitmarsh maintains that:
it was…the very diversity of archaic Greece that was its characteristic feature. There was no national hub, no capital, no single, stable core radiating Hellenism outward. Around 1,200 separate Greek poleis have been identified for the period between 650 and 323 BC, each with its own customs, traditions, and mode of governance…There were of course regional powers, but no single state exerted influence over the entirety.[5]
The Greeks devoted an extra ordinary amount of energy to
keeping the gods happy. But there
were close limits to the power of human clerics.
The job of priests was to sacrifice, not to pronounce on ethical or
spiritual issues. The idea of a
Greek priest or priestess using his or her influence to sway public debates of
(for example) the definition of marriage or the treatment of the poor was
unthinkable. Priesthood was a role
within the community, not a spiritual calling.[6]
Greece was, fundamentally, an honor-based society, and
honor was generated—for humans and gods alike—through success in competition
with others. It is no accident that
sport is one of the Greeks’ most enduring legacies, for competitiveness lay at
the very heart of the Greek concept of (particularly male) honor.
Individuals can increase their own standing in the public’s eyes only by
decreasing that of another.[7]
The Homeric conception of
arête emphasizes the virtues of
wealth, courage, honor, civic concern, friendship, prosperity, and “the law of
the claw.” Think of it as
the core cultural conception from the time of Homer [~800-700 B.C.E.] to the
time of Plato, but recognize there will be changes of emphasis and so forth
through such a long period.
Of course, like his teacher Socrates,
Plato wanted to
transform his society, but they both
wanted to do this through an educational activity.
Many of their contemporaries did not understand this.
Evidence of the views of the historical Socrates comes from other writers
than Plato, and we have good reason to believe that the picture presented in the
early dialogues is a largely faithful portrait of the views of the historical
Socrates—though of course (given the student-teacher relationship, and the fact
that they share views which many would consider controversial, perverse, or
wrong), not everyone would share Plato’s veneration of Socrates.
The Greek playwright Aristophanes provides a humorous characterization of
Socrates in his play Clouds—staged
in Athens at the Dionysian Festival in 423 B.C.E. where it took third place.
In his “General Introduction” to Peter Meineck’s translation of
Aristophanes’ Clouds, Wasps, and Birds,
Ian Storey provides an excellent account of the role and production of comedies
in ancient Athens at the time of Socrates.
He notes that productions like that of
Clouds were:
...state-sponsored productions.
Especially at the City Dionysian [the festival of Athens for the deity
Dionysus] the role of the city loomed large—no public business was transacted,
the ten generals would enter formally and pour the opening libation, the
phoros (“tribute”) from the [other
Greek] cities would be paraded formally through the theatre, benefactors of the
city would be honored, and those whose fathers had died in battle would receive
a suit of armor from the city when they came of age.
Theatres in ancient Greece were large—that at Athens is estimated to have
held fifteen thousand to seventeen thousand spectators—and thus the tragedies
and comedies played to the state as audience.
Drama was not the province of a few in a covered theatre; it was for the
people as a larger body. We need to
imagine a combination of the faithful gathered in Vatican Square on Easter Day,
the crowds that fill the Mall on the Fourth of July, and the audiences on the
opening night of a great summer blockbuster.
Drama was intensely alive and intensely important to the people of
Athens.[8]
The play revolves around a wealthy farmer, Strepsiades,
whose has been placed deeply in debt by his son, Pheidippides.
Strepsiades formulates the plan of going to Socrates who is portrayed as
a Sophist (Aristophanes places the play in a school he calls the Socratic
“Pondertorium”) to learn the techniques of “The Inferior Argument” so that he
can argue his way out of his debts.
In the play Strepsiades meets a Chorus of “new deities” who preside over “new
learning,” and while he has trouble remembering anything (as he is an old man),
his study of the “Inferior Argument” allows him to avoid his debts.
The play shows that the consequences of the “new learning” are terrible,
at the end the Chorus (the Clouds) reveals itself to be champions of the
traditional deities, and Strepsiades burns down the Pondertorium.
In his introduction to the play, Storey contends that Strepsiades:
...is the ideal sort to “take the
piss” out of sophistic pretensions.
The teaching scene...shows Aristophanes at his comic best where the
less-than-bright Strepsiades foils every attempt by Socrates to teach him
anything. Yet the scene depends on
stretching the spectator’s reactions in two opposite directions: he wants to be
a sophos like Socrates...and at the same times wants to see the sophos taken
down a rung or two. We admire
Strepsiades’ low cunning and desire not to pay his debts, but at the same time
we wince at his essential dishonesty and insistence at learning the Inferior
Argument.[9]
While scholars disagree about Aristophanes’ “purpose” in the play, I side
with Storey’s view that his comic use of Socrates is meant to contain “more than
a hint of appreciation for Socrates”[10]
and for the “new learning,” while portraying the Sophists in a rather bad light.
Storey refers to a passage in Plutarch which “...records Socrates’
alleged reaction to Clouds, “I feel
that I am being made fun of by friends at a great party”....This may be how the
joke was intended to be taken.”[11]
The Athens of Plato’s day was one of the most cultured and also one of the most politically and economically powerful of the City States which were the dominant form of political organization at the time in the West. In 408, however, Sparta (another powerful Greek city state) defeated Athens in a major battle, and this struck deep in the Athenian psyche. In 404, with the aid of the Spartans, powerful oligarchs in Athens overthrew the political “democracy” and established rule by a group of thirty aristocrats (referred to as the “Thirty Tyrants” by the subsequent democracy) in power. They had a bloody and turbulent one-year rule. Two members of Plato’s extended family were in this group.
In 399 B.C.E., after the reinstitution of the democracy, Socrates was
brought to trial (we learn more of this in the
Apology) and condemned to die.
After his death, Plato and some of his friends left Athens and traveled
to continue their
studies and learn more about other philosophers.
Plato then returned to Athens where he founded a school (The Academy) on
family land. There Plato taught
philosophy for the rest of his life.
He made several trips to Syracuse (another of the City States) at the
request of the Regent and ruler, in an attempt to teach the ruler philosophy,
but these efforts are not successful.
Plato left his Academy to his sister’s son, Speusippus, upon his death,
and The Academy continued to exist as a center of study and philosophic teaching
and learning until 529 C.E., when the Christian Emperor Justinian had it closed
because it was a pagan institution.
Founded in approximately 385 B.C.E., the Academy lasted for 916 years![12]
While many refer to the Athens of Plato’s day as being in its “Golden
Age,” Plato would disagree--he thinks that civilization is falling apart—in the
best of times there is no impetus to ask “What is right?” or “How should things
be?” Plato has a passion for
excellence, and he is a great fan of permanence and hierarchy.
His “world-view” is characterized by an aristocrat’s disdain for “the
many.”
2. Plato’s faith in
reason: “man[13]
is a potentially
rational animal:”
Many Greek thinkers
of Plato’s era “began” the “development” of the now-common view of a
cosmos (that is, the view that there
is a rational, ordered character to reality—a
logos—that what happens can be
conceived of as happening according to a rational plan [laws of nature]).[14]
This view is opposed to the then common world-view which held that any
putative plan would be inadequate, since there are unpredictable [or chance]
acts [of the various deities] which do not [or at least, do not necessarily]
follow any detailed or specific overall plan.
The reception which Socrates receives in court, and some of the ancient
portrayals of the thinkers of the period clearly show that their views were by
no means the common view of the world at the time.[15]
In his “Pre-Socratic Philosophy,” W.K.C. Guthrie provides an excellent
summary of this important aspect of these ancient Greek philosophic thinkers:
pre-Socratic philosophy differs
from all other philosophy in that it had no predecessors....Before them no
European had set out to satisfy his curiosity about the world in the faith that
its apparent chaos concealed a permanent and intelligible order, and that this
natural order could be accounted for by universal causes operating within nature
itself and discoverable by human reason.
They had predecessors of a sort, of course.
It was not accidental that the first pre-Socratics were citizens of
Miletus, a prosperous trading center of Ionian Greeks on the Asiatic coast,
where Greek and Oriental cultures met and mingled.
The Milesian heritage included the myths and religious beliefs of their
own peoples and their Eastern neighbors, and also the store of Egyptian and
Babylonian knowledge—astronomical, mathematical, technological.
Yet the Milesians consciously rejected the mythical and religious
tradition of their ancestors, in particular its belief in the agency of
anthropomorphic gods, and their debt to the knowledge of the East was not a
philosophical one. That knowledge
was limited because its aim was practical.
Astronomy served religion; mathematics settled questions of land
measurement and taxation. For these
purposes the careful recording of data and the making of certain limited
generalizations sufficed, and the realm of ultimate causes was left to
dogmatism. For the Greeks knowledge
became an end in itself, and in the uninhibited atmosphere of Miletus they gave
free play to the typically Greek talent for generalization, abstraction, and
erection of bold and all-encompassing explanatory hypotheses.
Consciously, the revolt of the Milesian philosophers against both the
content and the method of mythology was complete.
No longer were natural process to be at the mercy of gods with human
passions and unpredictable intentions.
In their place was to come a reign of universal and discoverable law.
Yet a whole conceptual framework is not so easily changed.
Poetic and religious cosmogonies had preceded the schemes of the
Milesians, and the basic assumptions of these can be detected beneath the
hypotheses of their philosophic successors.
Nevertheless, the achievement of abandoning divine agencies for physical
causes working from within the world itself can hardly be overestimated.[16]
The Milesian (often called the “Ionian”) thinkers generally sought to understand the origins and mechanisms of the things in the world, and for this reason they are often called the physologoi and seen as the first true “physical scientists.” For example, according to Charles Kahn, Anaximander (~610-~546 B.C.E.) was the author of the first geometrical model of the universe, a model characterized not by vagueness and mystery but by visual clarity and rational proportion, and hence radically different in kind from all known “cosmologies” of earlier literature and myth. The highly rational character of the scheme is best indicated by Anaximander’s explanation of the earth’s stable position in the center: it remains at rest because of its equal distance from all points of the celestial circumference, having no reason to move in one direction rather than in another. This argument from symmetry contrasts not only with all mythic views but also with the doctrine ascribed to Thales [his teacher]: that the earth floats on water.”[17] Similarly Anaxagoras (~500-~428 B.C.E.) determined the true cause of solar and lunar eclipses, and maintained that the shape of the Earth's shadow on the moon during a lunar eclipse shows that the Earth is round.
Many of these thinkers relied on human sensory experience
to ground or justify their knowledge
claims, but Plato contended that sense experience was unreliable and incapable
of grounding certainty, which he took to be necessary for knowledge (rather than
mere belief). For him ultimately
our knowledge claims needed to be grounded in self-evident and absolutely
certain principles. Traditional
examples would be such truths as: “a whole is greater than its parts,”
“triangles are closed three-sided figures,” bachelors are unmarried males of the
age of consent,” Moreover, whereas many of the Milesian (or Ionian)
physologoi were interested in
cosmology and
metaphysics, Plato and Socrates were
primarily concerned with moral and
social philosophy—instead of seeking knowledge of the nature of the world,
they sought knowledge to ensure virtuous
action and character.
Plato contended that there were unchanging, transcendent, absolute, overarching, objective, rational, and knowable “forms,” and he believed that we needed to understand them, and guide our conduct by them if we are to be able to live “the good life.” Whereas the physologoi were largely concerned with knowledge as an end-in-itself, Socrates and Plato were concerned with achieving it because of its connection with virtue, justice, and human happiness.
For Plato rationality is best
exemplified by Euclidean Geometry.
Starting with self-evident notions
like “point,” “line,” and “plane” one can use
deductive reasoning to rationally
prove things like “triangles have exactly 180º:
L 1 is parallel
to L 2
_______________
L 1
a(
/ \ )c
/ ͡ e
\
/
\
____/)b___d)\____
L 2
Alternate
interior angles of parallel lines are equal, so a
= b and c = d
Since
a + e + c = 180º
(sum of angles on a line)
we can clearly
see that b + e + d = 180º (substituting equals: b for a
and d for c).
Of course Plato has to use dialectical reasoning to identify the “simples” or “forms,” and reasoning to connect them together. In geometry this was relatively easy, in thinking about piety, justice, obligation, etc. this becomes much more difficult. In the brief passage we will look at in Plato’s Meno, Plato’s Socrates argues that “no one can knowingly do wrong.” If such an argument is securely grounded in self-evident truths and deductively developed he can contend that if individuals can be made knowledgeable, they could become virtuous.18
In the Euthyphro he will suggest there is a genus-species relationship19 between piety and justice—indicating something about the “simples or “forms.” In the Apology we will learn how much value he attaches to the search for knowledge, and in the Crito we will further elaborate this and come to better understand his concept of arête. Perhaps the closest Plato comes to trying to show us a form is in his longest dialogue: The Republic but we will not get to that in this course.
I highly recommend Colin Well’s “How Did God Get Started”[20]
for a discussion of the development of the Ionian perspective and for a
discussion of the development of the monotheistic idea of a deity—it provides an
excellent characterization of the polytheistic perspective and of the
development of both the “rational” and “monotheistic” perspectives in the
ancient period, as well as a compelling account of how the two perspectives (of
faith and reason) developed together.
3. Plato’s view of
the philosopher’s methodology:
Plato offered a three-part method for uncovering knowledge
of the rational order of the universe:
elenchus (refutation),
aporia (perplexity), and
dialectic.[21]
He holds that it is our
reason, and not our
sensory experiences, which uncovers
(and justifies our claims to) knowledge.
4. Plato and the
Forms:
If dialectic is the
process of achieving knowledge,
what does its
object
(the object of knowledge) look like?
The Forms are
conceived by Plato to be: unchanging,
absolute, transcendent, objective,
rational, and knowable—they provide the underlying constant basis
(the criteria for) the changing things we are familiar with, they are the
objects of knowledge, and they are
epistemically and ontologically prior to the particular things.
5. Plato’s view of
man:
Plato’s view of the nature of man—psyche
[soul]—make it clear this is
not (at least not primarily)
a religious conception—hearken to the
Euthyphro.
Reason, the
emotions or passions, and the
appetites.
Martha Nussbaum maintains that “‘emotions’ is the more
common modern generic term, while “passions” is both etymologically closer to
the most common Greek and Latin terms and more firmly entrenched in the Western
philosophical tradition....what I mean to designate by these terms is a genus of
which experiences such as fear, love,
grief, anger, envy, jealousy, and other relatives—but not bodily appetites
such as hunger and thirst—are the species....This family of experience, which we
call emotions as opposed to appetites, is grouped together by many Greek
thinkers, beginning at least with Plato, and his account of the soul’s middle
part.”[23]
Note that Plato’s concern is with
society—for him, man is a social
animal (here we should note the economic, psychological, biological, and
dialectical roots of this social facet of man).
‘Man’ and “men and women:” we must be careful in attributing either a
feminist or a sexist character to Plato’s views.
In his Republic, Plato argues
that men and women should have similar roles in the ideal state (that women as
well as men would be rulers, soldiers, and workers—cf.,
451c-456c). Nonetheless, in many
passages he speaks in an extremely disparaging manner about women.
As one reads Plato’s works, one must critically examine what he says and
consider whether or not he truly believes that they have the same nature (or
natures), and whether or not he wishes to treat men and women “equally.”[24]
It may be helpful here for us to know something about the role women
played in ancient Greek society if we are to be able to properly interpret what
Plato has to say about their role.
In this regard, John Gould’s “Law, Custom and Myth: Aspects of the Social
Position of Women in Classical Athens,” is very helpful.
Gould provides a clear-cut picture of the legal status of women at the
time:
a woman, whatever her status as
daughter, sister, wife or mother, and whatever her age or social class, is
in law a perpetual minor: that is,
like a male minor, but throughout her life she was [always] in the legal control
of a male kyrios who represented her
in law. If unmarried she was in the
kyrieia of her father, her brother(s)
by the same father, or her paternal grandfather.
Upon marriage a kind of divided
kyrieia arose: the evidence seems to suggest that a father could dissolve
his daughter’s marriage, even against her wishes, whereas in other respects the
husband acted as kyrios.
On her husband’s death she either passes to the
kyrieia of her son(s) (if any) or
reverts to that of her father if still alive: if her sons are minors she falls
under the kyrieia of their
kyrios.
If she is pregnant on her husband’s death she may (and perhaps must)
remain in the kyrieia of whatever
male affine will become her future child’s guardian.[25]
Gould offers a summary of an ancient description of the
good husband which was meant to be a straightforward and uncontroversial
description of the normal relations between husband and wife:
he describes the lay-out of his
house, with its separate quarters for men and women, and how his wife, who was
feeding their baby, frequently slept in the women’s quarters so that she could
feed and wash it in the night. The
picture that emerges is...[of] a wife who
leads a private, sheltered life, who goes out little...whose shopping is
done by a slave woman; who, once her child is born, is no longer under her
husband’s surveillance, but who is not expected to be present when [he] brings
home a male friend for an evening meal....evidence of eating and drinking
together with males who are not kinsmen is frequently presented in Athenian law
courts as establishing that a woman is...not a [proper] wife.[26]
Nussbaum “qualifies” this view in one important respect:
...in the world of fourth-century
[B.C.E.] Athens, hetairai
[courtesans, or mistresses] would be more likely than other women to be
literate, and to have the freedom to move around at their own discretion....a
recent papyrus discovery has confirmed Diogenes’ report—long dismissed—that
Plato taught two courtesans in his school....[such women could have enrolled]
also in any of the three major Hellenistic schools [Epicurean, Stoic, and
Skeptic]. The career of Pericles’
mistress Aspasia illustrates the degree of sophistication and intellectual
influence a women of the hetaira
class could achieve, even in a culture as restrictive of women as Athens.[27]
Clearly, women in ancient Greece led a different sort of
life than is the case today. The
fact that Plato clearly, at times, talks of treating them in the same way as men
are treated is enough (given this picture) to establish that there is certainly
some positive reason for using ‘man’ in this context as speaking of human beings
generally and not simply the male creatures of the species.
Of course, given that he frequently speaks of women in a negative
fashion, we should not just simply assert that “When we find him talking about
‘man’, what Plato really means to be talking about is ‘human beings’.”
[1] Of
course, there were no “books” at the time.
Scrolls would have been what was the
state of the art at the time and bound pages
weren’t invented for another 600 years.
“By
the end of antiquity, between the 2nd
and 4th centuries, the scroll was
replaced by the codex.
The book was no longer a continuous roll,
but a collection of sheets attached at the back.
It became possible to access a precise
point in the text directly.
The codex is equally easy to rest on a
table, which permits the reader to take notes
while he or she is reading.
The codex form improved with the
separation of words, capital letters, and
punctuation, which permitted silent reading.
Tables of contents and indices
facilitated direct access to information.
This form was so effective that it is
still the standard book form, over 1500 years
after its appearance”—“The History of Books,”
Wikipedia, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/History_of_books#Greece_and_Rome
, accessed on 03/13/17.
[2] Gilbert
Ryle, “Plato,” in
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy v. 5, ed. Paul
Edwards (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1967), pp. 314-333, p.
315.
[3]
In its
“reference” section Dictionary.Com characterizes
arête
as follows:
…in its basic
sense…[it] means “goodness” “excellence",
“virtue” of any kind.
In its earliest appearance in Greek, this
notion of excellence was bound up with the
notion of the fulfillment of purpose or
function; the act of living up to one’s full
potential.
The Ancient Greeks applied the term to anything:
for example, the excellence of a chimney, the
excellence of a bull to be bred and the
excellence of a man.
The meaning of the word changes depending
on what it describes, since everything has its
own peculiar excellence; the
arête
of a man is different from the
arête
of a horse….
By
the fourth and fifth centuries BC,
arête
as applied to men had developed to include
quieter virtues, such as… (justice)… and
(self-restraint)….
In
Homer’s
Iliad and
Odyssey, “arête”
is used mainly to describe heroes and nobles and
their mobile dexterity, with special reference
to strength and courage, but it is not limited
to this….The excellence of the gods generally
included their power, but, in the
Odyssey
(13.42), the gods can grant excellence to a
life, which is contextually understood to mean
prosperity.
See
Arête - Wikipedia
(accessed on 09/12/23).
[4] Bruce
Kimball,
Orators and Philosophers: A History of the Idea
of Liberal Education (expanded edition)
(N.Y.: College Entrance Examination Board,
1995), pp. 16-18.
Emphasis has been added to the passage.
[5]
Tim
Whitmarsh,
Battling the Gods: Atheism In The Ancient World
(NY: Knopf, 2015), pp.
19-20.
[6]
Ibid.,
pp. 21-22.
[7]
Ibid.,
p. 44.
[8] Ian
Storey, “General Introduction,” in
Aristophanes 1: Clouds, Wasps, and Birds,
trans. Peter Meineck (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1998), pp. vii-xxxv, pp. xx-xxi.
Cf., pp. xviii-xxxvi for Storey’s full
account of such productions.
[9] Ibid.,
pp. 2-7, p. 3.
[10]
Ibid.,
p. 5.
[11]
Ibid.,
p. 6.
[12] If we
were to conceive of it as a “university”—one
might claim it is, the longest lasting Western
one so far.
This statement would be true until 2023
when the University of Bologna, which was
founded in 1119 C.E. would take the crown.
The medical school at Salerno is even
older—it was founded in 850 C.E., but it was not
a full university (the current one was
incorporated, in fact, in 1970 C.E.).
Bologna is generally considered the first
“European” university.
Daniel Del Castillo notes that al-Azhar
University in Cairo was founded by the Fatimids
(followers of Fatima, the daughter of the
prophet Muhammad) in 970 C.E. and continues unto
today—cf.,
Daniel Del Castillo, “A 1,000-Year-Old
University Takes on A New and Troubling Role,”
The
Chronicle of Higher Education v. 47 (May 11,
2001), pp. A 47-48, p. A 47.
Scholars do note that the site Plato
founded was destroyed in 86 B.C.E., and while
Platonic thought and teaching continued in
Athens it was not until about 410 C.E. that a
formal fixed location of the Academy is clearly
established by philosophers who stylized
themselves as the successors.
Moreover it is not clear that the Academy
always taught the breadth of topics to make it
clearly a contender for university status.
Whichever way one conceives of this,
however, Plato clearly established a long-lived
and significant educational institution.
[13] The
question of who is covered by such a statement
is a serious one.
It is often said that ‘man’ in such
contexts is meant to include all human
beings—that it is used “generically” to cover
both men and women.
This question will be addressed more
carefully in Section 5.
[14] I refer
here to a broad period from Thales, who is
widely regarded as the founder of the Ionian
school of natural philosophy in the 580’s B.C.E.
up to Socrates and Plato in the 400s-350s B.C.E.
[15] As the
above remarks about Aristophanes suggest.
[16] W.K.C.
Guthrie, “Pre-Socratic Philosophy,” in
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy v. 6, ed. Paul
Edwards (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1967), pp. 441-446,
pp. 441-442.
[17] Charles
Kahn, “Anaximander,” in
The
Encyclopedia of Philosophy v. 1, ed. Paul
Edwards (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1967), pp. 117-118, p.
117.
18 Just as
“triangles” are a species of the more
encompassing genus “figure,” (essentially
differentiated by the characteristic of
“three-sidedness”), so “piety” is specie of the
genius “justice” (having something to do with
“treating the deities justly”).
19Cf., Plato’s Meno, trans. W.K.C. Guthrie, in The Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (Princeton: Princeton U.P., 1961), 77b-78b. The marginal page references in the text refer to a collection of Plato’s works (Platonis Opera [Paris: 1578]) edited by Henri Stephanus. This edition’s pagination has become the standard way of identifying and referring to Plato's works.
[20] Colin
Wells, “How Did God Get Started?”,
Arion
v. 18 (Fall 2010).
Available online at:
http://www.bu.edu/arion/archive/volume-18/colin_wells_how_did_god_get-started/
.
[21] The
central characteristic of this third “step” in
the philosophers’ overall procedure which marks
it off is the fact that as individual
philosophers advance their theories or beliefs
here, they do so tentatively, critically, and
publicly--or at least that is what they
should do.
[22] The
distinction between necessary and sufficient
conditions may be made in a number of ways.
Necessary conditions may be described as
“those which must be there for an event to
occur” (thus paying your parking fines is
necessary for graduation), while sufficient
conditions are conditions such that the event
must occur (thus a direct double shotgun blast
to the head is sufficient for death).
Note that conditions may be sufficient
without being necessary (as in the example), and
that necessary conditions need not be sufficient
(as in the example).
An alternate way of drawing the
distinction is to say that “p
is a necessary condition for
q”
means “if
q is true, then
p is
true” (symbolically
q->p),
while “p
is a sufficient condition for
q”
means “if
p is true, then
q is
true” (symbolically:
p->q).
[23] Martha
Nussbaum,
The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in
Hellenistic Ethics (Princeton: Princeton
U.P., 1994), p. 319.
[24]
Cf.,
Lynda Lange, “The Function of Equal Education in
Plato’s Republic, in
The
Sexism of Social and Political Theory: Women and
Reproduction from Plato to Nietzsche, eds.
Lorenne Clark and Lynda Lange (Toronto: Univ. of
Toronto, 1979), pp. 3-15) for a critique of
Plato’s sexist treatment of the nature of women.
Cf.,
C.D.C. Reeve, “The Naked Old Women in the
Palaesatra: A Dialogue Between Plato and
Lashenia of Mantinea,” in the
1992
Catalogue of Hackett Publishing Company for
a defense of Plato’s treatment of the nature of
women.
[25] John
Gould, “Law, Custom and Myth: Aspects of the
Social Position of Women in Classical Athens,”
in The
Journal of Hellenic Studies v. 100 (1980),
pp. 38-59, p. 43; emphasis added.
[26]
Ibid.,
pp. 47-48, emphasis added.
[27] Martha
Nussbaum,
The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in
Hellenistic Ethics, op. cit., pp. 53-54.