Supplement to Final Class Fall 2021 For
Hauptli’s MSC Course “Plato vs
Dewey”
Copyright © 2021 Bruce W. Hauptli
I. Introduction For
Today—Whose “Faith,” “Faith In What,
& Why “Faith?”
Does he think that all human
beings have this “faith?”
Clearly not! His unending
“historical” looks at Western civilization make it clear that his views of
inquiry, metaphysics, human nature, and valuation are not the views found
previously in our civilization.
Does he think that everyone
today (either his or our time) have this faith?
Again, clearly not! He talks
about earlier America and current America and how there are “robber barrons”
“fascists”,” Marxists,” and other view which disparage democracy and “commoners’
views, as Westbrook points out, Dewey completely understood that many
American social theorists believed that
…widespread political
participation was not only not a necessary feature of democracy, it was also not
a desirable feature. They argued
that increased political participation by incompetent citizens might undermine
the stability of liberal-democratic regimes by unleashing irrational passions
and encouraging demagoguery, thereby destroying the peacefuI competition of
responsible elites which was at the heart of a realistic democracy.
Widespread apathy was thus seen by some as a
functional feature of an effective
democratic polity. Participatory
ideals were useful primarily for purposes of legitimation and for ensuring elite
responsibility but were not to be taken seriously as ideals.[1]
Dewey explicitly and forcefully
rejected such views and championed a
moral democracy which required
his “common faith” that we can life of free inquiry which is pursued in a social
setting of similarly-minded individuals.
When this faith is present individuality can prosper and democracy can
exist. Living
an “associated” life with others which conforms to such a model involves a moral
commitment to oneself and to others which instantiates a democracy.
As he says in his “Creative Democracy—The Task Before Us:”
I did not invent this faith.
I acquired it from my surroundings as far as those surroundings were
animated by the democratic spirit.
For what is the faith in democracy in role of consultation, of
conference, of persuasion, of discussion, in formation of public opinion, which
in the long run is self-corrective, except
faith in the capacity of the
intelligence of the common man to respond with commonsense to the free play of
facts and ideas which are secured by effective guarantees of free inquiry, free
assembly and free communication.
I am willing to leave to upholders of totalitarian states of the right
and the left the view that faith in the capacities of intelligence is utopian.
For the faith is so deeply embedded in the methods which are intrinsic to
democracy that when a professed democrat denies the faith he convicts himself of
treachery to his profession.[2]
When Dewey says “Democracy is a
way of life controlled by a working
faith in the possibilities of human nature.
Belief in the Common Man is a
familiar article in the democratic creed,”[3]
he is neither availing himself of an “appeal to faith” nor referencing some
“established creed.” Instead he is
[optimistically, even in light of the Fascist and Communist challenges of the
day--1939] maintaining that
democratic government can provide for a
moral social order which is not in the service of any external authority, but
instead fosters both individual and social development.
For Dewey the chief obstacle for such a life arises when groups of
individuals (examples: castes, classes, races, sexes, material wealth groupings,
or “cultural wealth” groupings) isolate themselves from one another and seek to
exploit others. Against these
divisive forces, as we have seen, Dewey marshals his “faith”—one he did not
invent, but acquired from his cultural surroundings:
Is it just his “fellow
travelers” who have this “faith?”
Is it “common” enough for him?
Again, no! He wants to
maintain many have inherited it from their enculturation, few have it on the
basis of having “reflectively inquired” into it.
Here arises his distinction between “wants,’ ”desires,” and “values,” on
the one hand and “valuations” and ideals” on the other hand.
His claim that this “faith” is
necessary for democracy arises
out of such critical reflection,” as does democracy’s status as an “ideal!”
II. An Important
Criticism of Dewey:
Critics of Dewey from George Santayana [1925] to Richard
Rorty [1982] have maintained there is an inconsistency between Dewey’s
“naturalistic methodologies” and his presumed “basic principles,” or
“unrecognized metaphysical commitments.”[4]
Whether we are considering his discussions of the
process of inquiry (whether
ordinary, scientific, or moral”) his view that there are no fixed starting
points, first principles, unchanging essences, or final truths or goods seems
undercut by his view that the world and human experience are plastic, unchanging
and “natural” rather than “transcendental”).
His rejection of Greek philosophy, Roman Christian thought, Medieval
theological views, rationalism, empiricism, and idealism, all ae motivated by
his pragmatic instrumentalism, Yet
this requires a specific take upon the changing world, human nature and
naturalism—one which seems to go beyond
what his methodology would legitimate.
The same inconsistency seems to arise in his
metaphysics where his criticism of
dualism, essentialism, foundationalism, transcendentalism, and other
metaphysical commitments and advocacy of a naturalistic orientation seem to
leave similarly leave him with a commitment beyond what his preferred
methodology would legitimate.
Similarly in value theory,
his rejection of teleology, final causation, and transcendentalism and advocacy
of a naturalistic view of human nature, consummatory experience, valuation, and
ideals seems to promote a fixed and unchanging view unsupported by his
naturalistic commitments and his “faith.”
In our last class a version of this sort of critique emerged in our
discussion. We will look at it more
carefully today as it is an excellent example of what I called an “internal
philosophical critique.”
While Rorty
discusses, and substantially agrees with the criticism mentioned above, in his
“Globalization, the Politics of Identity and Social Hope” [1999] he also
maintains that:
willingness to accept the liberal goal of maximal room for individual variation,
however, is facilitated by a consensus that
there is no source of authority other
than the free agreement of human beings.
This consensus, in turn, is facilitated by the adoption of philosophical
views about reason and truth of the sort which are nowdays thought of as
symptoms of ‘postmodern scepticism’ but which I think of as just good old
American pragmatism.
The core of Dewey’s thought was an
insistence that nothing—not the Will of God, not the Intrinsic Nature of
Reality, not the Moral Law—can take precedence over the result of
agreement freely reached by members of a
democratic community. The
pragmatist claim that truth is not correspondence to the intrinsic nature of
something that exists independently of our choice of linguistic descriptions is
another expression of this insistence.[5]
Of course, there
are other, “external,” critiques we
must note and consider:
most
notably, for purposes of our class, Plato’s view of the ideal state/individual
and his criticism of democracy
the
view that democracy is only “better than the other forms of government which
humans have come up with,” but this does not make it “ideal”
the
view that democracy is good because it allows for the nonviolent changing of
rulers when citizens are unhappy (a view which does not need to be committed to
a “Deweyan faith,” a view that democracy is good, that it promotes human
progress or development—indeed it is compatible with a view that human nature is
fundamentally corrupt (and allows for “throwing the bums” when their corruption
becomes intolerable (but has no promise that these bums would be replaced by
“better” rulers)
the
above mentioned criticism offered by “social elites” which holds that democracy
must be guided by the highly educated—for example John Stuart Mill believed that
highly educated citizens should have more votes than lesser educated individuals
(who, presumably, would have more votes than uneducated individuals)
…..
[1] Robert
Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy,
(Ithaca: Cornell U.P., 1991), p. 545.
[2] John
Dewey, “Creative Democracy—The Task Before Us,”
was first read at a dinner in honor of Dewey in
New York on 10/20/1939, then published in
John
Dewey and the Promise of America Progressive
Education Booklet No. 14 (Columbus: American
Education Press, 1939), and reprinted
The Later
Works, v. 14.
The selections we are discussing appears
in John
Dewey: The Political Writings, ed. Debra
Morris and Ian Shapiro (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1993), on pp. 242-243, and emphasis (bold)
has
sometimes been added to the passages
[3]
Ibid.,
pp. 242.
[4]
Cf.,
George Santayana, “Dewey’s Naturalistic
Metaphysics,”
Journal
of Philosophy v. 25 (1925), pp. 673-688, and
Richard Rorty, “Dewey’s Metaphysics,”
New
Studies in the Philosophy of John Dewey, ed.
Steven M. Cahn (Hanover: Univ. Press of New
England, 1977), pp. 45-74,
reprinted in in his
Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-1980)
(Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1982),
pp. 72-89.
[5] Richard
Rorty, “Globalization, the Politics of Identity
and Social Hope,” in his
Philosophy and Social Hope (London: Penguin,
1999), pp. 229-239, pp. 238-239.
The essay originally appeared as “Global
Utopias, History and Philosophy” in
Cultural
Pluralism, Identity and Globalization, ed.
Luiz Soares (Rio de Janiero: UNESCO/ISSC/EDUCAM,
1996), pp. 457-469.
Go to Midcoast Senior College Webpage
File revised on 11/01/21