What Is Philosophy?
Copyright © 2023 Bruce W. Hauptli
It is often surprising to non-philosophers that
philosophers should find it difficult to answer this question.
Nonetheless, the very question “What is philosophy?” is
itself a philosophical question!
To help us gain an initial understanding of the philosophical
enterprise I will quickly discuss three views of the nature of philosophy
(two of which, I will argue, are deficient).
1. The
“Wondering” Conception of Philosophy:
...the question, why a particular species of animal
exists, is answerable by zoology, but the question, why anything at all
exists, cannot be answered by any science....the question whether a
particular scientific argument is valid can be settled by reference to the
accepted standards of...validity, but the question whether the standards
themselves ought to be accepted cannot be settled in any such way.[2]
Parmenides [~500 B.C.E.] said nothing can move.
Yet he traveled and knew he traveled around
Plato [~427-~347 B.C.E.] held that no particular thing can
be really white, or round, or
human...that only whiteness is really white....In another and better world,
he said, such ‘universals’ exist on their own, unmixed with space, time, or
each other....Yet Plato was a particular thing himself, of course, and was
human too....[6]
Philosopher’s theories, then, are often so exceedingly
strange that we are obligated to postulate some non-rational cause, in order
to explain the philosophers’ believing them.[7]
Later in his book, Stove summarizes his criticism of
the “wondering” characterization of philosophy by saying that “...philosophy
typically begins in
pseudo-wonder....”[8]
His complaint is that the wondering of
many (or most) philosophers seems
idle. That is, without a
clear-cut goal (or end-in-view), it seems to be little more than
day-dreaming.[9]
The “second” conception of philosophy, which I will now discuss, can
help us see what is “missing” from the first one.
2. The “Enduring
Questions” Conception of Philosophy:
To get at what the “wondering conception” leaves off,
let me ask you this question:
Is the discipline of philosophy famous for answering its questions or
resolving its wonderings?
While individual philosophers are, of course justly
famous for their own particular “answers” to the questions which they
address in any introductory course in philosophy students easily come to see
the inadequacy of several famous “answers.”
[10]
Certainly, then, the answer to the above question has to be a
resounding “No!” In many cases,
the same questions are debated anew with each generation.
What, then, is it that makes this discipline famous (or infamous)?
We could contend that philosophy is famous for its questions.
This leads us to what I will call the “enduring questions” conception
of philosophy. To understand it,
we will need to distinguish two sorts of questions (or problems):
Removable questions are
those that can be firmly and finally answered or resolved).
Here I have in mind such questions as “What is the boiling point of
water,” or “How can we vacuum-pack potato chips?”
Enduring questions, on the
other hand, are questions that have not been, or perhaps can not be, firmly or finally resolved.
-According to this conception of philosophy, these questions arise for all of us (they arise for each individual, generation, society, or culture) because we are the sorts of creatures we are, and because of the nature of the world, or environment, which we inhabit. Examples of such questions include:[11]
--questions about our
relationship to others (about our
moral responsibility, political and social obligations, etc.);
--questions about “nature”
(about the existence of a deity, the fundamental character of reality, the
relationship of minds and bodies, the existence of a rationale for the
world, etc.);
--questions about our
cognitive abilities (about the
consequences of human fallibility, the distinction between science and
pseudo-science, the justification of our knowledge claims, etc.); and
--questions about ourselves
(about the nature of personal identity, the meaning of our lives, etc.).
The “enduring questions conception” of philosophy holds that
philosophers are concerned with asking and answering such enduring
questions. While this is partially
the case, we must note that
theologians, novelists, and science fiction writers (as well as many
others) also raise and endeavor to answer such questions.
Thus, it is not the questions themselves (nor the endeavoring to
supply answers to them) which constitutes what is unique or special about
the philosophic enterprise.
3. The
“Dialectical” Conception of Philosophy:
In place of the “wondering” and “enduring questions”
conceptions of philosophy, finally, I wish to offer what I will call the
“dialectical conception.” Rather
than concentrating on the origins
or objectives of the philosophical
enterprise (the wondering and answering), this conception draws our
attention to the particular
methodology which philosophers employ as they respond to the
wonders, questions, and problems.[12]
Now it should be noted that for many individuals (at many times),
any sort of response or answer to an enduring question will be
satisfactory. After all if we
have pressing questions, we often need to adopt some responsive stance [any
stance] quickly. In the long
run, however, the dialectical conception of philosophy emphasizes that we
will be best served by (and we often desire)
critical or rational responses to
these questions. It is here that
philosophy has a distinctive role to play:
according to the dialectical conception, philosophers seek
to develop, critically examine, and
rationally defend answers or responses to the sorts of questions (and
wonders) noted above. In short,
philosophy is here conceived of as a
critical enterprise.
‘Dialectic’[13]
(in the sense in which I am using it here [in the “Socratic” as opposed to
the usage of Aquinas, Hegel, or Marx)[14]
consists of rational argument—it is the enterprise
of meeting arguments with
arguments:
-dialectical advancement, development, and critical
examination of our rational responses to the enduring questions helps to
ensure that the responses which we offer are meaningful, that their
implications are clear, that they fit together in a meaningful whole (a
consistent world-view), that they are adequate, and that they are rationally
justified.
-Toilet Paper Roll Example: (the “perennial
question” as to which way it should roll off the roll, and the “rational”
response regarding “outward” and patterned paper).
Of course, the problems or questions we will be concerned with are
more “serious.”
--Imagine someone asks “what is the right way for toilet
paper to roll off the holder—out from the wall or turning in toward the
wall?” I respond “out, because
that way the pattern can be seen.”
An argument! Imagine the
individual replies “but what if the toilet paper is not patterned?”
My argument has met a counter-example, and if I am being
“dialectical’ (philosophical) I need to relinquish my thesis, respond
successfully to the argument or modify my thesis.
This quick example displays the core nature of the dialectical
process.
A passage from James Rachels’
The Elements of Moral Philosophy summarizes this conception of
philosophy nicely:
A reasoned dialectic is completed when the participants
rationally accept an argument, explanation, or problem- resolution.
Here we can see a parallel between philosophic dialectic and science:
why do we feel that the sciences and medicine have
progressed during the last two thousand years?
Do we know the truth in science or medicine?
Might our present answers be wrong?
Avoiding past
mistakes and resolving (better than they did) past problems.
Philosophers may claim the same success!
Neither science nor philosophy arrives at an answer that is final
but, rather, each finds an endpoint in
a critical and tentative rational agreement amongst the participants.
What happens if other participants join in or if new considerations
arise later? The dialectic is
again taken up! This is why
philosophical arguments are often characterized as “perennial”—they
arise anew for each age as each group of individuals carries on the
dialectic and assesses the answers of its ancestors.
To many this suggests that philosophers will never solve any of the
problems (or answer any of the questions), and this leads them to think that
the contrast between philosophy and science is not at all favorable to
philosophy. After all, the
scientists are able to reach broad intersubjective consensus as to whether
or not a scientific question is answered or a scientific problem is
resolved. In his “Thomas Kuhn,
Rocks and the Laws of Physics,” Richard Rorty offers a discussion which may
help mitigate such a critique:
the trouble is that intersubjective agreement about who
has succeeded and who has failed is easy to get if you lay down criteria of
success in advance [and, he suggests, this is what scientists are able to
do]. If all you want is fast
relief, your choice of analgesic is clear (though the winning drug may have
unfortunate belated side effects).
If you know that all you want out of science is accurate prediction,
you have a fast way to decide between competing theories (though this
criterion by itself would, at one time, have led you to favor Ptolemaic over
Copernican astronomy). If you
know that all you want is rigorous demonstration, you can check out
mathematicians’ proofs of theorems and award the prize to the one who has
proved the most (although the award will then always go to a hack, whose
theorems are of no interest).
But intersubjective agreement is harder to get when the criteria of success
begin to proliferate, and even harder when those criteria themselves are up
for grabs [as they are, he suggests, in philosophy].[16]
I believe that a “successful” reading of any
philosophical text will comprise the asking and answering of the following
four questions:
1. “What is being argued here?”
2. “What are the stages of the argument?”
3. “Were good reasons presented for the thesis?”
4. “Why
is it being argued?”
It is not as easy as it might seem to ask, and answer,
these questions! But if you are
to understand what a philosopher says, you must know what is being argued,
what steps there are to the argument, why it is being argued, and whether or
not the arguments are adequate.
6. Regarding The
“Interpretations” Presented in this Course:
It is necessary to note that in this course I will be
presenting you with interpretation
of the thought of several philosophers.
The introductions and interpretations I will provide are meant to be
just that however. I am also
asking you to read the thinkers
themselves, and I want you to form your
own considered views about their
theories. My interpretations and
introductions are intended as aids to this latter process.
Here the remarks of another philosopher, Richard McKeon, are
appropriate. McKeon makes this
statement in his “Preface” to his edition
of The Basic Works of Aristotle:
...some aid is needed, however, and therefore a method of
reading Aristotle’s works is suggested in the
Introduction by a brief statement
of the interrelations and continuity of his doctrines.
The reader is advised to treat this interpretation skeptically until
and unless he can find it confirmed in his own reading of the text, for it
is useful only as a device by which to permit Aristotle to speak for
himself. The achievement of
Aristotle can be discovered only by reading and rereading his works, and the
appreciation of that achievement depends quite as much on the deepened sense
of value and the precision of criteria which he inculcates as on the
materials he treats.[17]
McKeon and I want you to develop your own appreciation
and interpretation of the thinkers we are exposing you to, and our remarks
are meant to facilitate that rather than to be taken as some privileged set
of observations and interpretations.
While the
philosophical enterprise revolves around argumentation, philosophical
argumentation must be distinguished from rhetorical argumentation.
Wikipedia says:
rhetoric
is the art of persuasion, which along with grammar and logic (or
dialectic …), is one of the three ancient arts of discourse.
Rhetoric aims to study the capacities of writers or speakers needed
to inform, persuade, or motivate particular audiences in specific
situations. Aristotle defines
rhetoric as “the faculty of observing in any given case the available means
of persuasion” and since mastery of the art was necessary for
victory in a case at law; or for passage of proposals in the assembly; or
for fame as a speaker in civic ceremonies; he calls it “a combination of the
science of logic and of the ethical branch of politics.”
Rhetoric typically provides heuristics for understanding,
discovering, and developing arguments for particular situations, such as
Aristotle's three persuasive audience appeals: logos, pathos, and ethos.
The five canons of rhetoric or phases of developing a persuasive
speech were first codified in classical Rome: invention, arrangement, style,
memory, and delivery.
From Ancient Greece to the late
19th century, rhetoric played a central role in Western education in
training orators, lawyers, counselors, historians, statesmen, and poets.[18]
The phrase I
used above, “meeting arguments with arguments,” may be misunderstood (and
the characterization of philosophy which I have just offered may be
misconstrued) if we think of arguments simply as disagreements
amongst individuals, as simply purposed toward persuasion, or as
stylized debates where individuals seek primarily to “score points”
against one another. Aristotle
cites (above) winning in court, passing legislation, and seeking fame as a
speaker, but rhetoricians can also simply enjoy spirited competition with
friends, or may seek to “win a judged contest.”
Generally rhetoricians seek to inform, persuade, or entertain an
audience.
Just as one must understand the
rhetorician’s goal if one is to understand their activity, the
end-in-view of a philosophical dialectic must be understood if we are to
understand the philosophical argument.
Unfortunately, as you might expect, philosophers disagree as to the
end-in-view of the philosophical enterprise.
Here are four of the many differing goals of philosophizing which
have been advanced by various philosophers over the centuries from Plato's
time to today.
(a) Rational Understanding and Truth: many traditional philosophers
contend that philosophy seeks rational
understanding (that is, “truth supported by reason”).
They claim that we can attain this sort of understanding only if we
develop a coherent system of critically-considered theories (or responses).
Such a coherent system of critically held theories is often called a
“world-view”—these philosophers don’t claim that philosophers seek to
master the many particular truths which are true of the world (the number of
grains of sand on the beach, the age of the highest mountain, the exact
amount of one’s check-book balance), instead a coherent set of extremely
general truths are sought. Here
rational understanding is not sought because it facilitates some other goal,
instead it is seen as intrinsically valuable (or the search for it is
conceived of as an intrinsically valuable activity).[19]
In a similar vein, Robert Nozick contends that philosophy should be
directed toward providing explanations: “many philosophical problems are ones of understanding
how something is or can be possible.
How is it possible for us to have free will, supposing that all
actions are causally determined?”[20]
(b) The Happiness of the Rational Life: some philosophers contend that
human beings can not be happy (or
lead the good life) unless we
develop critically-considered rational responses to the wonders and enduring
questions noted above (or a critically considered overall world-view).
Here it is happiness which is claimed to be intrinsically valuable,
and philosophy is conceived of as a necessary means toward its attainment.
While criticism is, of course, emphasized here, it is valued for what
it can get us (happiness or the good life).
Often this view is raised not by talking about criticism but, rather,
by talking about the “intellectual virtues”—it is claimed that the “life of
reason” is the only truly fulfilling life for human beings.
(c) Rational Understanding and Worship: still other philosophers contend
that the end-in-view of philosophy is the understanding (and proper worship)
of a deity. These philosophers
contend that the appropriate end for man is philosophical understanding of a
deity (that such rational understanding is our primary purpose, obligation,
and the only appropriate form of worship for a rational creature).
(d) The Empowerment of Individuals via
Reason: finally, for my introductory purpose here, some philosophers contend that the goal of
philosophizing is the empowerment of individuals via the liberation of their
thought, culture, and lives from the prejudice and provincialism which
culture, upbringing, and convention instill in us all.
For example, Martha Nussbaum maintains that the “...pursuit of
logical validity, intellectual coherence, and truth delivers
freedom from the tyranny of custom and
convention, creating a community of beings who can take charge of their own
life story and their own thought.”[21]
Nussbaum cites Epicurus who says that:
empty is that philosopher’s argument by which no human
suffering is therapeutically treated.
For just as there is no use in a medical art that does not cast out
the sicknesses of bodies, so too there is no use in philosophy, unless it
casts out the suffering of the soul.”[22]
As noted above, the rhetoricians had their students
study logic and argumentation to help them become more facile in arguing for
(or against) whatever these students happened to want to argue for (or
against). The critical
orientation that the dialectical conception of philosophy champions is,
similarly, “plastic” in that it allows for a variety of ends which one might
pursue with this methodology.
The dialectical methodology is uncompromising, however, in its
adherence to the ideal of rationality—it
is to be used to offer others (and to help oneself find)
rationally-persuasive responses to enduring problems or questions.[23]
Where the dialectical methodology in philosophy is pursued without
keeping the enduring questions in sight, it is perverted from one of its
primary controlling factors.
Similarly, when philosophy focuses on the questions while loosing sight of
the dialectical arguments, it is perverted from the other of its primary
controlling influences. In his
Pragmatism: An Open Question,
Hilary Putnam says that:
philosophy which is all argument feeds no real hunger;
while philosophy which is all vision feeds a real hunger, but it feeds it
Pablum.[24]
In a fuller version of this page I have one further section "Concluding Thoughts on Distinguishing and Characterizing Philosophy" which discusses John Dewey's conception of philosophy (which emphasizes the activity of criticism of values) and also offers an initial critique of the presumption that there is a single "essence" which could adequately capture the nature of philosophizing.
[1]
Cf.,
Plato,
Theaetetus 155 d, trans. F.M. Cornford, in
The Collected Dialogues of Plato, eds. Edith Hamilton and Huntington
Cairns (Princeton: Princeton U.P., 1961);
and Aristotle,
Metaphysics Book I: Chapter 2; 982,
trans. W.D. Ross, in
The
Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard
McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941).
[2] David Pears,
Ludwig
Wittgenstein (Middlesex: Penguin, 1969),
p. 13.
[3]
Ibid.,
emphasis added to citation.
[4] That is, “under
the aspect of eternity”, or “in its
essential or universal form or nature,” or
“from the outside.”
[5] David Stove,
The
Plato Cult (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1991), p. ix.
[6]
Ibid.,
pp. ix-x.
[7]
Ibid.,
p. x.
[8] David Stove, “‘I
Only Am Escaped Alone to Tell Thee:’
Epistemology and the Ishmael Effect,” in his
The Plato Cult,
op.
cit., pp. 61-82, p. 69.
Emphasis added to passage.
[9] Where one
substitutes ‘explanations’ for ‘wonders’ it
may seem that the appearance of day-dreaming
can be avoided.
We need to remember that explanations
must also be in service of some end however.
Individuals may offer explanations to
escape blame, to clarify causal connections,
to cover-up actions, to elaborate what they
take to be the truth, etc.
Unless a standard of explanation is
offered, little more “progress” toward what
an adequate conception of philosophy is will
be made here—magic, religion, statistics,
and chance are all appealed to by various
individuals as “explanations” for certain
phenomena.
[10] Thus
introductory students learn the deficiencies
of Plato’s conception of the state, Anselm’s
ontological argument, Descartes’ dualistic
conception of the self, and Kant’s moral
theory.
[11] This sample
“division” of the questions is not meant to
be exhaustive, nor does it perfectly
parallel the “standard” division of the
philosophic terrain into ethics,
metaphysics, epistemology, etc.
[12] Of course, as
the ensuing will show, the origins and
objectives may not be ignored by this
conception.
[13] Philosophers
use single quotes to surround a word when
they are
mentioning it rather than
using
it.
For example in the sentence “‘Long’
is a short word,” the word ‘long’ is
mentioned (discussed) while the word
‘short’ is
used!
[14] Aquinas’ method
was called “dialectical” because it
proceeded by first asking a specific
question; second his opponents’ objections
to his thesis (in regard to the question)
were stated; third he stated his own
position (beginning with “On the
contrary...”, or “I answer...”); and
finally, he replied to the objections which
were raised.
Hegel’s method consisted of the
statement of a thesis, then of an
anti-thesis, and then a “synthesis” was
developed.
Marx’s “dialectic” defies simple
characterization, but was central to his
“historical” and developmental conception.
[15] James Rachels,
The
Elements of Moral Philosophy (New York:
Random House, 1986), p. vi.
[16] Richard Rorty,
“Thomas Kuhn, Rocks and the Laws of Physics”
[1997], in
his
Philosophy and Social Hope (London:
Penguin, 1999), pp. 175-189, p. 180.
The essay originally appeared in
Common
Knowledge v. 6 (1997).
[17] Richard McKeon,
“Preface,” in
The
Basic Works of Aristotle,
op.
cit., pp. vii-x, p. ix.
[18] "Rhetoric,"
Wikipedia, accessed February 25, 2020.
The citations from Aristotle are from his
Rhetoric, Book I, Chapter 2, Section
1359.
[19] An
intrinsically valuable goal, or activity, is
one that is pursued for its own sake.
Such values are contrasted with
extrinsic values—here the goal or
activity is valued for what it will allow
one to achieve.
Health, for example, might be
intrinsically valuable (good-in-itself),
while wealth is usually conceived of as
extrinsically valuable
(good-for-what-it-can-get-us).
[20] Robert Nozick,
Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge:
Harvard U.P., 1981), p. 4.
Emphasis added to passage.
[21] Martha
Nussbaum,
The
Therapy of Desire (Princeton: Princeton
U.P., 1994), p. 5.
Emphasis added to the passage.
[22]
Ibid.,
p. 13.
[23] Of course, two
of the ends-in-view may require a
qualification of this statement.
The skeptical conception of
philosophy which sees philosophical
criticism aiming at the suspension of
belief, and the religious conception which
sees it as ending up in worship both
constitute “compromised” commitments to the
ideal of rationality.
But this is a complex story that
requires extended argument.
[24] Hilary Putnam,
Pragmatism: An Open Question (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1995), p. 23.
Email: hauptli@fiu.edu
I greatly appreciate comments and corrections--typos and infelicities are all too common and the curse of "auto-correct" plagues me!
Last revised: 09/24/23