Lecture Supplement on Barry Stroud’s “Understanding Human Knowledge In General”[1] [1989]
Copyright © 2013 Bruce W. Hauptli
Stroud contends that while a long-standing tradition in epistemology leads to the belief that we either don’t know the sorts of things we think we know, or that we can’t quite fully see how what we take ourselves to “know” can, really, count as knowledge. That is
308 …what we seek in epistemology [is]…to try to understand human knowledge in general, and to do so in a certain special way….I want to raise the possibility that, however much we came to learn about this or that aspect of human knowledge, thought, and perception, there might still be nothing that could satisfy us as a philosophical understanding of how human knowledge is possible.
Of course, if this is the case, then we end up in a skeptical position! However, we need to ask whether this is skepticism as it is traditionally construed. If we are to understand Stroud’s argument we will need to become clear on a number of points first:
In his Meditations on First Philosophy [1641], Rene Descartes tries to conquer skepticism by beating the skeptics at their own game—he doubts everything until he finds something that is impossible to doubt (his own existence as a “thinking thing”), then he examines what it is about this knowledge claim which inures it from skepticism (its “clarity and distinctness”), and, finally, he tries to establish that all such ideas are known (because his deity guarantees them).
Descartes’ argument is generally considered to be unsuccessful as it has to ground some knowledge claims in others, which require yet others; resulting either in a vicious regress or an arbitrary stopping point. Neither of these, of course, leaves one really free of skepticism.
Stroud points out that if one only wants an account of some particular sort of knowledge (e.g., knowledge of the external world, other minds, the past, etc.), such an appeal to truths of a “higher epistemic priority” will do just fine—one can rescue that kind of knowledge from skepticism by appealing to another sort of knowledge. Given that we want a “general account of all human knowledge,” however, clearly this will not do!
In
contemporary epistemology, Descartes is considered an “internalist”—for
our purposes, “...a theory
of justification is internalist if
and only if it requires that all the factors needed for a belief to be
epistemically justified for a given person be
cognitively accessible to that
person, internal to his cognitive
perspective; and a theory is
externalist, if it
allows that at least some of the justifying factors need not be thus accessible,
so that they can be external to the
believer’s cognitive perspective, beyond his ken.”[2]
Many contemporary epistemologists adopt an “externalist” position
contending that this will avoid Descartes’ problems.
A motivating factor in the adoption of this view is our belief that
children and animals have perceptual knowledge, but are not able to engage in
“Cartesian epistemological justificatory regress.”
Stroud
contends that externalism,
not just internalism,
falls prey to our epistemological desire for a
“general account of all human knowledge.”
In short, were Descartes to adopt externalism (and forbear from trying to
ground his appeal to higher order claims, principles, and truths) and
321 …if
his theory is true [that his deity guarantees the truth of his clear and
distinct ideas] he will know the things he thinks he knows.
But he is, in addition, a theorist of knowledge.
He wants to understand how he knows the things he thinks he knows.
And he cannot satisfy himself on that score unless he can see himself as
having some reason to accept the theory that he…can recognize would explain his
knowledge if it were true.
Here, Stroud suggests, we come up to the most important “dimension” of the generality which epistemologists seek (one which shows the problem whether one champions an internalism or an externalism):
316 we want an account that explains how human knowledge in general is possible, or how anyone can know anything at all in a certain specified domain. The difficulty arises now from the fact that we as human theorists are ourselves part of the subject-matter that we theorists of human knowledge want to understand in a certain way. If we merely study another group and draw conclusions about only them, no such difficulty presents itself. But then our conclusions will not be completely general. They will be known to apply only to those others, and we will be no closer to understanding how our own knowledge is possible. We want to be able to apply what we find out about knowledge to ourselves, and so to explain how our knowledge is possible.
Whether one takes the internalists’ first-person perspective, or the third-person perspective of the externalists, if one’s goal is to explain how anyone has knowledge; then one can not be satisfied with appeal to “higher level” knowledge or with an appeal to theories which, if true, would explain individuals’ knowledge.
The Text:
Stroud maintains that:
307-308 what we seek in philosophical theory of knowledge is an account that is completely general in several respects. We want to understand how any knowledge at all is possible—how anything we currently accept amounts to knowledge. Or, less ambitiously, we want to understand with complete generality how we come to know anything at all in a certain specified domain.
-308 in the case of material objects, we want to know how we know anything about these objects;
-in the case of other minds, we want to know how we know anything about these objects;
-in the case of induction, we want to know how we know anything about the future.
311 The problem here is one of generality. We can know what Smith thinks by asking him about his cognitive activities, but that gives us “knowledge” of another mind by presupposing knowledge of that very mind. In short, this can not be generalized for all “other minds!”
Descartes’ First Meditation shows us that we have too little to go on to allow us to have perceptual knowledge (similarly for knowledge of other minds).
311 This apparent dilemma is a familiar quandary in traditional epistemology. I think it arises from our completely general explanatory goal. We want to explain a certain kind of knowledge, and we feel we must explain it on the basis of another, prior kind of knowledge that does not imply or presuppose any of the knowledge we are trying to explain.
Unlike Unger, Stroud does not believe the problem is the “quest for certainty.”3 We could respond to questions about knowledge of other minds by appealing to behavior, or to questions about knowledge of objects by appealing to sense data; but when the problem is “generalized,” this strategy falls apart! If skepticism is to be avoided we will need to know about the connections between behavior and minds, or between sense data and objects!
312 Some epistemologists try to avoid the problem by appealing to postulates or principles. But:
313 we would be left with the further question whether we know that that ‘principle’ is true, and if so, how. And all the rest of the knowledge we wanted to explain would then be hanging in the balance, since it would have been shown to depend on that ‘principle.’
In short, here a regress arises. Trying to talk about two sorts of “knowledge,” to avoid the problem, however, merely postpones the problem. If the principles are independent of what depends upon them, that doesn’t explain why they are known! Thus appeal to an a priori principle to explain a posteriori knowledge will only “help” if we can legitimate the appeal to the a priori principles.
315 Some contemporary epistemologists think that the problem here is with the “internalist” presumption—the view that to know p, one must know that one knows p. They offer an externalist account of knowledge holding:
315 …no independent or a priori support is needed on the part of the knower. All that is needed is that a certain proposition should be true; the person doesn’t have to know that it is true in order to know the thing in question.
316 [This view] explain[s] knowledge in terms of conditions that are available from an ‘external,’ third-person point of view, independent of what the knower’s own attitude towards the fulfillment of those conditions might be. It is not all smooth sailing. To give us what we need, it has to come up with an account of knowledge or reasonable belief that is actually correct—that distinguishes knowledge from knowledge in the right way.
Here, Stroud suggests, we come up to the most important “dimension” of the generality which epistemologists seek:
316 we want an account that explains how human knowledge in general is possible, or how anyone can know anything at all in a certain specified domain. The difficulty arises now from the fact that we as human theorists are ourselves part of the subject-matter that we theorists of human knowledge want to understand in a certain way. If we merely study another group and draw conclusions about only them, no such difficulty presents itself. But then our conclusions will not be completely general. They will be known to apply only to those others, and we will be no closer to understanding how our own knowledge is possible. We want to be able to apply what we find out about knowledge to ourselves, and so to explain how our knowledge is possible.
That is, the Cartesian approach yields a “regress,” and the “externalist” approach would avoid the regress by not requiring that we “move up a level”—instead all we need to do is to be in the appropriate situation in terms of our knowledge claims. But a Descartes who adopted externalism would be an unsuccessful epistemologist (as are all externalists, according to Stroud) because:
319
until he finds some reason to believe his theory [that his deity guarantees the
truth of his clear and distinct ideas] rather than some other, he
cannot be said to have explained how he
knows the things he knows….if his theory is true [that his deity guarantees
the truth of his clear and distinct ideas] he will know the things he thinks he
knows. But he is, in addition, a
theorist of knowledge. He wants to
understand how he knows the things he thinks he knows.
And he cannot satisfy himself on that score unless he can see himself as
having some reason to accept the theory that he…can recognize would explain his
knowledge if it were true.
Stroud
contends that this view also falls prey to our epistemological desire for a
“general account of all human knowledge.”
In short, were Descartes to adopt externalism (and forbear from trying to
ground his appeal to higher order claims, principles, and truths) and
321 …if
his theory is true [that his deity guarantees the truth of his clear and
distinct ideas] he will know the things he thinks he knows.
But he is, in addition, a theorist of knowledge.
He wants to understand how he knows the things he thinks he knows.
And he cannot satisfy himself on that score unless he can see himself as
having some reason to accept the theory that he…can recognize would explain his
knowledge if it were true.
322-323 Overall summary.
[1]
Barry Stroud, “Understanding Human Knowledge In
General,” in
Knowledge
and Skepticism, Marjorie Clay and Keith
Lehrer, eds. (Boulder: Westview, 1989), pp.
31-50.
The essay is reprinted in
Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology,
Sven Bernecker and Fred Dretske, eds. (N.Y.:
Oxford U.P., 2000), pp. 307-323, and these notes
are referenced to the reprint edition.
[2] Laurence BonJour, “Externalism/Internalism,” in A Companion to Epistemology, eds. Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), pp. 132-136, p. 132. This work is on reserve in the Green Library.
3 Cf., Peter Unger, “A Defense of Skepticism,” Philosophical Review v. 80 (1971), pp. 198-219.
File revised on 09/05/2013.