Note Official Exam Time: Friday, May 1,  7:30a.m.—9:30a.m. 

Second Paper Assignment is now here, immediately following the syllabus

First Paper assignment is now here, immediately below the syllabus.

Scroll down for Chronology Part I; Locke’s First Treatise; Madison on “Property;” Kenneth Henley, Religious Toleration and Freedom of Conscience; Chronology Continued (through Hume); Kenneth Henley, Hume’s "Wilt Chamberlain Argument" and Taxation; Kenneth Henley, Hume’s Deflationary Theory of Allegiance, Chronology Continued through Federalist Papers, Montesquieu & Madison on Separation of Powers

 

PHM 4430 Topics in Philosophy of Law: Philosophy of the U.S. Constitution

Dr. Kenneth Henley. Office:  DM 344B Phone: 305-348-3346. Office Hours: Mon.,Wed., & Fri. 8:00-8:50 & 10:00-10:50. Website: http://faculty.fiu.edu/~henleyk

Texts: 1. John Locke, Political Writings, ed. David Wootton (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2003). ISBN 0-87220-676-9  2. David Hume, Political Writings, ed. Stuart D. Warner & Donald W. Livingston (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994). ISBN 0-87220-160-0.  3. Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, & John Jay, The Federalist Papers. Ed. Clinton Rossiter. Signet Classic  2003 (Any complete edition is acceptable.).  4. Akhil Reed Amar, The Bill of Rights: Creation and Reconstruction (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998) ISBN 0-300-08277-0.  5. The Declaration of Independence  6. The Constitution of the United States of America

Course Objectives: 1. To provide an understanding of the principles of legal, political, and moral philosophy underlying the U.S. Constitution and the Declaration of Independence. 2. To provide an understanding of the historical context of the developing philosophy of the U.S. Constitution  3. To improve skills of reasoning and argument:  searching for consistency and coherence, clarifying questions, ferreting out presuppositions, weighing reasoning and evidence, and exploring alternative accounts of disputed concepts.  4. To improve writing skills.

Requirements:  THIS COURSE IS NOT DELIVERED ONLINE NOR BY E-MAIL. Class attendance is required; students should anticipate no more than 4 unexcused absences.  Students must read the assignment before coming to class. Class attendance, participation and discussion are important, and may make a difference in the course grade if the student’s final average is on the borderline between two grades. Two approximately 6-page papers are required. Dates, topics and guidelines for the papers will be given in class and posted on my website.  While the most important dimension is the quality of the reasoning and philosophical understanding, grades on papers also reflect all elements of writing: grammar, punctuation, sentence and paragraph structure, clarity of expression, and essay structure. There will be a comprehensive final examination. Each paper and the final examination will count as 1/3 of the final average for the course. Note that a student cannot pass without completing all work.

Jan. 12, 14, 16 Wootton, “Introduction” to Locke, pp. 7-122; Locke, from First Treatise, pp. 242-59

Mon., Jan. 19 University Closed—Martin Luther King, Jr. Holiday

Jan. 21, 23 Locke, Second Treatise, pp.261-327 (through Chap. 9, section 131)

Jan. 26, 28, 30 Locke, Second Treatise, pp. 327-87 (Chap. 10-end)

Feb. 2, 4, 6 Locke, A Letter Concerning Toleration pp. 390-436.

Feb. 9, 11, 13 Warner & Livingston, Introduction to Hume vii-xxvi; Hume, selections from Treatise pp. 1-73, selections from 2nd Enquiry pp. 80-97

Feb. 16, 18, 20 Hume, “Of the Original Contract,” “Of Superstition and Enthusiasm,” “Of Passive Obedience,”

Feb. 23, 25, 27 “Of the Origin of Government,” “Of Parties in General,” “Of the Independency of Parliament”

Mar. 2, 4, 6 Hume, “Of the Rise and Progress of the Arts & Sciences,”  “Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth,” “That Politics may be reduced to a Science”

Spring Break  March 9-13

Mar. 16, 18, 20 Federalist 1-36

Mar. 23, 25, 27 Federalist 37-66

Mar. 30, Ap. 1, 3  Federalist 67-85

Ap. 6, 8, 10 Amar, The Bill of Rights: Creation and Reconstruction,  pp. pp. xi-118

Ap. 13, 15, 17  Amar, pp. 119-230

Ap. 20, 22 Amar, 231-307

Ap. 24 Review

Comprehensive Final Exam: Note Official Exam Time: Friday, May 1,  7:30a.m.—9:30a.m.  Students must provide their own Blue-Books.

 

Second Paper

Due: Mon., April 20 at the beginning of class

Length: approximately 6 pages

Topic: Choose one of the following topics within Hume, Federalist Papers, or Akhil Reed Amar.

 

A. Hume

1. Why does Hume consider enthusiasm more favorable to liberty than superstition? Do you agree?

 

2. In “Of the Original Contract,” what is Hume’s argument that it is of no use to trace the duty of allegiance to the duty of fidelity (promise-keeping)? Is this argument sound?

 

3. In “Of Parties in General,” why does Hume consider factions of principle especially dangerous, and, among factions of principle, religious factions the most dangerous of all? Do you agree?

 

4. On Hume’s view, the rules of justice (with property rules the paradigm) ultimately serve everyone's interests, so it might seem that government would be unnecessary in order to achieve conformity with the rules. What feature in human nature makes government necessary to achieve conformity with justice? Do you agree with this account? (You must use both the essay “Of the Origin of Government” (pp. 194-97) and the section of the Treatise also titled “Of the Origin of Government” (Book III, Part II, Section VII, pp. 47-51).

 

5. Explain Hume’s account of a perfect (i.e., complete) commonwealth. Is such a governmental structure, at least in its broad outlines, acceptable?

 

6. Hume writes, “It is, therefore, a just political maxim, that every man must be supposed a knave: Though at the same time, it appears somewhat strange, that a maxim should be true in politics, which is false in fact.” And he argues that we must find ways to make it “the interest, even of bad men, to act for the public good.” Explain what Hume means and the implications for the wise structure of government. Do you agree? (You must use at least “Of the Independency of Parliament” and “That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science.”)

 

B. Federalist Papers

Following are the paper topics in the Federalist Papers with an indication of some important numbers; of course, other papers are relevant to each topic. Any of these topics would be an acceptable focus. You would not, of course, be able to discuss all of the relevant numbers. Indeed, a paper might analyze and offer a critical response to one very important number (such as Number Ten or Number Fifty-One), or to several.

Human Nature (1, 6, 10, 15, 49, 50, 51, 57)

The Need for an Energetic Sovereign Union (2, 3, 4, 15, 17, 23, 25, 37, 80)

Factions, the Extended Republic, and Refining Representation (9, 10, 14, 35, 50, 51, 60)

The Nature of Republican Government (22, 37, 38, 39, 48, 49, 50, 51, 55, 57)

Separation and Blending of Powers (9, 38, 47, 48, 50, 51)

The Representative Nature of the House of Representatives (35, 52, 59, 60)

Slaves and Representation (54)

The Senate's Role  (62, 63, 64)

The President, The Legislature, and the Military (24, 25, 26, 34, 41, 63, 67, 68, 69, 70)

The Compound Republic and Dual Sovereignties (16, 17, 20, 37, 39, 44, 45, 46, 50, 51, 52, 53, 59, 82)

The Judiciary and the Supremacy of Federal Law (16, 22, 39, 44, 78, 80, 81, 82)

 

Section C:

Explain and discuss the basic structure of Akhil Reed Amar’s account of the development of the Bill of Rights from Creation to Reconstruction. How does Refined Incorporation make the full narrative coherent?

 

 

First Paper

Due: Wed., Feb. 25th at the beginning of class

Length: approximately 6 pages

Topic   Choose one of the following general topics. Do not attempt to answer all of the listed questions in such a short paper. Focus on one or perhaps two related questions within the general topic. In addition to exposition and interpretation of Locke, provide some argued response of your own.

You must use my “Writing a philosophy paper…” hand-out (also on my website).

 

1. Locke’s Account of the State of Nature

What are the relations between persons in the state of nature?

What is the content of the law of nature?

In the state of nature, what is the fundamental property that every man has?

In what sense are all equal in Locke's state of nature?

2. Locke’s Account of External Property

How is property (in the sense of external possessions) acquired in the state of nature?

What are the initial limits to the acquisition of property in the state of nature?

How does the agreement to use money affect the acquisition of property?

How are the original limits on property acquisition affected by an individual’s use of his abilities to improve the productivity of resources?

3. Locke’s Account of Civil Government

What are the inconveniences in the state of nature that lead to the compact of society?

What is the end (in the sense of goal or purpose) of government?

What are the terms of the original contract of society? What is given up by individuals to society?

Can the original contract of society be less than unanimous?

What is tacit consent and what extent of authority over the individual does it create?

How is the contract of government formed? Can it be less than unanimous?

How is government limited?

What justifies resistance to the government?

4. Locke on Toleration

Can Locke’s statement that “everyone is orthodox to himself” be reconciled with his assertion that there is “but one truth, one way to heaven”?

How does Locke distinguish between Civil Interests and the Care of Souls?

According to Locke, what is a Church?

What are Locke’s main arguments for toleration?

Why are Catholics and atheists not to be tolerated?

 

 

Background for Locke, Toleration & Constitutional Theory: Chronology

1517  Martin Luther posts the 95 Theses on the door of the castle church at Wittenberg, Saxony (1815 absorbed into Prussia; now eastern Germany)

1520  Luther excommunicated

1534  King Henry VIII of England severs ties to Rome: The Act of Supremacy

1536  Pilgrimage of Grace:   A popular uprising in Northern England against the abolition of the monasteries, inclosures of common lands, high taxes and rents, claiming loyalty to King Henry VIII, but opposing the persecution of Catholics. After a temporary accomodation followed by renewed resurgence, the uprising was put down and many were hanged.

1541  John Calvin institutes a Protestant theocracy in Geneva

1545  Council of Trent convenes for its first of many long periods: the Counter Reformation response of Catholicism to the Protestant challenge is underway under Pope Paul III and the new, learned Society of Jesus (the Jesuits). Many internal reforms and also renewed militancy against Protestants.

1553-58  Mary Tudor (Mary I) returns England to the Roman fold. Persecution of Protestants, including many burnings at the stake.

1557  First Covenant of the Scottish Protestants

1560  led by John Knox, Scottish Parliament endorses Calvinist Presbyterianism

1558  Elizabeth I restores the Church of England, under the temporal authority of the Crown.  Penal Laws against Roman Catholics. English Puritans and other Dissenters also prohibited from meeting. Plots, real and alleged, to place Elizabeth's Catholic cousin, Mary, Queen of Scots in her place.

1567  after forced abdication of the Catholic Mary Queen of Scots, her infant son James VI becomes King of Scotland. Presbyterian Church becomes official in Scotland.  Various regents during his minority, and then factions.  Eventually in 1586 James allies himself with the Protestant Elizabeth of England, whose heir presumptive he is.

1553  Michael Servetus (Miguel Serveto) condemned under Calvin and burned for denying the Trinity

1562-79  Protestant Netherlands fights for independence from Spain

1562-98  The Wars of Religion in France (the Huguenot Wars)  French Protestants (Huguenots) fight against Catholics.

1572  Massacre of St. Bartholomew's Day.  Murder first of Huguenot leaders and then over subsequent months many others (about 70,000 throughout France)

1580-95  publication of Montaigne's Essays, expressing a subtle tolerance of attitude, and doubt regarding dogma. Montaigne emphasizes human fallibility.  Florio's English translation of 1603 is widely influential.

1581  Independence of the Netherlands (the Northern, Protestant provinces)

1587  Mary, Queen of Scots beheaded (her son James VI of Scotland calmly accepts this).

1598  Edict of Nantes (religious toleration) issued by King Henry IV of France (Henry of Navarre, who had been Huguenot leader and turned Catholic, saying "Paris is well worth a Mass.")

1603  at the death of Elizabeth, James VI of Scotland becomes James I of England--the union of the crowns under a Protestant king

1605  (Nov. 5--subsequently Guy Fawkes Day) Gunpowder Plot to blow up Parliament and James I as he was to open Parliament; conspiracy of English Catholics against the Protestant establishment and its severe suppression of Catholic practice. The Plot was discovered and the conspirators killed or executed. Even more severe suppression of Catholicism followed the plot.

1606  Sir Edward Coke becomes chief justice of Common Pleas (subsequently of King's Bench). As justice until 1616 and then member of Parliament, Coke champions the Common Law against royal prerogative and absolutist claims of the Stuart monarchs James I and Charles I.

1607  settlement of Jamestown, Virginia, first permanent English settlement in America

1620  The Pilgrims land on the Mayflower in Plymouth, Massachusetts

1628  Petition of Right (Coke prominent in drafting) sent by Parliament to Charles I:  no taxes without consent of Parliament, no arbitrary imprisonment (writ of habeas corpus), no quartering of soldiers, no martial law in peacetime. Accepted by Charles in order to get money from Parliament--but soon ignored

1629  Cardinal Richelieu (Louis XIII's chief minister) defeats Huguenots. Peace of Alais effectively ends political power of Huguenots, consolidating Catholicism in France

1630  John Winthrop leads first large Puritan migration to Massachusetts

1618-48  Thirty Years War, ending with Treaty of Westphalia, which, along with many territorial and power disputes, ended the worst of the religious warfare on the Continent.  Each prince to determine the religion of subjects; an attempt at some form of toleration--rulers could allow full toleration if they chose.  The Treaty of Westphalia is seen as the beginning of the modern system of sovereign territorial states.

1634  first settlers of Maryland, both Catholic and Protestant. Religious toleration of Catholics (foundational of the colony) contested by subsequent waves of Puritan immigration, eventually victorious after 1655

1642-8  English Civil War.  Complex and changing alliances, with religion one of several issues--including taxation and other means of raising money for the Crown.  The parliamentarians defeat Charles I, beheaded in 1649.  The Protestant rule of the Rump Parliament and Oliver Cromwell.

1658  Death of Oliver Cromwell.

1660  Restoration of the Monarchy. Charles Stuart called to England: Charles II

1666 Locke joins the entourage of Lord Ashley (eventually Earl of Shaftesbury), at first for medical advice.

1675 Having been Lord Chancellor, Shaftesbury now turns into the leader of the Whig opposition to Charles II. Locke goes on an extended trip to France, returning in 1679.

1678-9  The Popish Plot. Titus Oates fabricates a Jesuit plot to assassinate Charles II and thus have the Catholic James, Duke of York ascend to throne.  There are twists and turns, resulting in anti-Catholic hysteria throughout England.  Many innocent people, commoners and peers, were judicially murdered. Oates was eventually convicted of perjury in 1685. Shaftesbury (and Locke) exploit the hysteria to build sentiment for the exclusion of James, Duke of York from the succession.

1679-81  The Exclusion Crisis (attempt to exclude the Catholic James, Duke of York from the succession) ends with the defeat of Locke's patron the Earl of Shaftesbury and defeat of the Whigs's Disabling Bill. Charles II dissolves the 3rd Exclusion Parliament and resolves to rule in future without Parliament.

1682  Shaftesbury goes into exile in the Netherlands and soon dies.

1683  The Rye House Plot fails to assassinate Charles II and James in an attempt to place on the throne the Protestant Duke of Monmouth (illegitimate son of Charles II). Several Whig leaders executed, others go into exile in the Netherlands. Algernon Sidney was beheaded on 7 December, 1683. Whether or not involved in the Plot itself, Locke hurriedly departs for the Netherlands.

1683-9  Locke in exile in the Netherlands.

1685 Louis XIV revokes the Edict of Nantes--Catholic absolutism in France as in Spain.

1685  James II, openly Catholic, becomes King on death of Charles II.

1687 James II issues the Declaration of Indulgence, exempting Catholics from punishment under the laws, despite their validity.

1688  a son, James Francis Edward (eventually called "The Old Pretender") is born to Mary of Modena, second wife of James II, thus creating a Catholic succession (James's Protestant first wife Anne Hyde had two daughters--Mary and Anne).

1688 publication of Algernon Sidney’s Discourses Concerning Government—eventually very influential in American colonies

1688-9  The Glorious Revolution.  Tory Members of Parliament join with Whigs to invite the Protestant Mary and her husband the Dutch prince William of Orange to cross to England and take the Crown. James II and his Catholic family go into exile in France.

1689  The Bill of Rights (English), accepted by William and Mary as condition of their accession:  bars Catholic succession to throne; crown restricted regarding taxation, standing army, dispensing power over law--establishing a large degree of political supremacy for Parliament.

 

Locke's First Treatise of Government: notes & some quotations

K. Henley

Both the First and Second Treatises of Government appeared anonymously in 1689, shortly after the Glorious Revolution, the exile of James II in France, and Locke's return from exile in the Netherlands. A Letter Concerning Toleration also appeared anonymously in 1689. Locke never acknowledged authorship during his lifetime--but in his will he finally did, conferring upon them the immense prestige of the author of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, published in his name in 1690 and foundational for the Enlightenment.  The First Treatise was completed (though not published) in March of 1681 during the Exclusion Controversy, the attempt of Shaftesbury and his party (the origin of the Whigs) to exclude the Catholic James, Duke of York from the succession to Charles II.  The Second Treatise was also probably written in 1681, perhaps in June or later. According to Locke, much of the First Treatise was lost, but to bolster the Second Treatise Locke published the remaining attack on Filmer's use of the Bible to support the divine right of kings and hereditary rule.

The First Treatise is a direct response to Robert Filmer's Patriarcha (published posthumously in 1680, written apparently in 1642), which argued that kings had absolute authority as heirs of Adam, given rule by God Himself.

In the First Treatise, Locke proceeds in a rather messy and sometimes incoherent manner. Most of it consists of Biblical interpretation, demonstrating that Filmer's use of Scripture is misleading.  In addition to the main point of political philosophy--the rejection of inherited absolute political authority--the First Treatise also expresses Locke's insistence upon a rationally argued interpretation of Scripture and Christian teaching.  Just as political authority requires a reasoned foundation, so does religion--even when there is a sacred text.

 

Locke, First Treatise of Government

Chap. IX "Of Monarchy by Inheritance from Adam,", section 86: "....For the desire, strong desire of preserving his life and being having been planted in him as a principle of action by God himself, reason, which was the voice of God in him, could not but teach him and assure him, that pursuing that natural inclination he had to preserve his being, he followed the will of his maker, and therefore had a right to make use of those creatures which by his reason or senses he could discover would be serviceable thereunto.” (my emphasis). (section 87) : “This being the reason and foundation of Adam's property gave the same title, on the same ground, to all his children, not only after his death, but in his lifetime....and so Adam's sovereignty built on property, or, as our author [Filmer] calls it, private dominion, comes to nothing."

Section 103: "...."Fatherly power, I easily grant our author, if it will do him any good, can never be lost, because it will be as long in the world as there are fathers; but none of them will have Adam's paternal power, or derive theirs from him; but every one will have his own, by the same title Adam had his, viz., by begetting, but not by inheritance or succession, no more than husbands have their conjugal power by inheritance from Adam.  And thus we see, as Adam had no such "property," no such "paternal power" as gave him sovereign jurisdiction over mankind, so likewise his sovereignty built upon either of these titles, if he had any such, could not have descended to his heir but must have ended with him." Section 101: “…the law of nature , which is the law of reason…” (my emphasis)

Chap. XI, "Who Heir?" Section 154: "This I cannot but observe, in authors who, it is visible, write not for truth, how ready zeal for interest and party is to entitle Christianity to their designs, and to charge atheism on those who will not without examining submit to their doctrines and blindly swallow their nonsense."

 

James Madison on “Property”

“Property: This term in its particular application means ‘that dominion which one man claims and exercises over the external things of the world, in exclusion of every other individual.’ In its larger and juster meaning, it embraces every thing to which a man may attach a value and have a right; and which leaves to every one else the like advantage. In the former sense, a man’s land or merchandize, or money is called his property. In the latter sense, a man has a property in his opinions and the free communication of them. He has a property of peculiar value in his religious opinions, and in the profession and practice dictated by them. He has a property very dear to him in the safety and liberty of his person. He has an equal property in the free use of his faculties and free choice of the objects on which to employ them. In a word, as a man is said to have a right to his property, he may be equally said to have a property in his rights. Where an excess of power prevails, property of no sort is duly respected. No man is safe in his opinions, his person, his faculties, or his possessions. Where there is an excess of liberty, the effect is the same. tho’ from an opposite cause. Government is instituted to protect property of every sort; as well that which lies in the various rights of individuals, as that which the term particularly expresses. This being the end of government, that alone is a just government, which impartially secures to every man, whatever is his own....Conscience is the most sacred of all property; other property depending in part on positive law, the exercise of that, being a natural and unalienable right. To guard a man’s house as his castle, to pay public and enforce private debts with the most exact faith, can give no title to invade a man’s conscience which is more sacred than his castle, or to withhold from it that debt of protection, for which the public faith is pledged, by the very nature and original conditions of the social pact.”

James Madison, “Property,” National Gazette, March 29, 1792, in James Madison, Writings (New York: The Library of America, 1999) pp. 515-16.

 

Religious Toleration and Freedom of Conscience

Kenneth Henley (Copyright)

 

The dimensions and degrees of governmental involvement with religion:

1.      Penal law used against those judged heretics (or infidels as well in some forms of persecution).  Even individual belief within the family and home are a matter of governmental regulation. In some legal systems apostasy (renouncing the religion one was born into or converted to) is punishable by death.

2.      “Unorthodox” group religious practices prohibited.

3.      Domestic matters such as marriage depend upon the individual’s religion, which is a recorded matter of legal status.

4.      Religious test required for holding various offices or for entering professions or participating in various institutions.

5.      A particular religion established as the religion of the state.

6.      Governmental involvement in furthering the teaching and inculcation of religious belief of some particular, sectarian kind.

7.      Governmental involvement in furthering the teaching of a highly generalized religious belief, for instance, belief in a creator God and divine providence.

8.      The use of religious language and ceremonies (particular or general) during public governmental functions.

9.      A strict exclusion of every kind of religious entanglement with government, even highly general ceremonial language during public governmental functions.

10.  Governmental authority used to create and maintain a strictly secular public sphere, restricting the free exercise of religion in the process. (e.g., contemporary France).

 

These dimensions can be combined in various ways.  For instance, there might be an established state religion (and naturally also ceremonial use of that religion) without other governmental involvement. There might be ceremonial religious language during governmental functions with no further entanglement, or such religious language might connect with governmental involvement with teaching some kind of religious belief.

Note that #10 involves the use of governmental authority in a way that arguably invades the religious liberty of individuals. The combination of prohibiting a governmental  establishment of religion while guaranteeing free exercise of religion (First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution) is an attempt to protect individual religious liberty even in the public sphere, while maintaining separation between government and religious institutions.

 

 

Chronology Continued (through Hume)

1640-70’s  The British slave economy is instituted, based on sugar and rum in the Caribbean: Jamaica, Barbados. Slavery still not important on the mainland of North America (where at first impoverished boys & indentured servants from Britain did the manual labor), but the use of slaves is gradually increasing on the mainland too                                  

1687  Isaac Newton publishes the Principia.  The Enlightenment spirit of confidence in reason, which pervades the first three-quarters of the 18th century, has as its original sources Newton and Locke (primarily because of Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding, published in 1690 under his name)

1689  The Glorious Revolution  (see first part of Chronology)

1680-1750  immense growth of the slave economy of the British colonies in the Caribbean and North America, with great numbers of Africans subjected to slavery for the sugar and tobacco plantations (and the cultivation of other crops in the Southern colonies); death and suffering as they are transported, treated as units of production on the plantations

1701     The Act of Settlement ensures a Protestant succession to Anne, heiress apparent, by excluding the large number of Catholic heirs to the throne in favor of Sophia of Hanover (daughter of Charles I’s sister)

1702                                                         William III dies, his sister-in-law Anne ascends

1704            Locke dies while Lady Masham (daughter of the Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth) reads the Psalms

1707  The Act of Union: The United Kingdom as a single government comes into being with the governmental Union of Scotland and England, voted by both Parliaments (previously the union was only of the Crowns, not of government). Scots Members are to sit in the Westminster Parliament, no separate Scots Parliament (until devolution under Labor government of Tony Blair).  Includes an Established Presbyterian Church in Scotland, with toleration of episcopacy.

1711  David Hume born in Edinburgh. Reared at the family home “Ninewells” in Berwickshire. A strict Scottish Presbyterian family

1711-12 The Spectator, periodical published by Joseph Addison and Richard Steele.  Commentaries and journalism, viewpoint opposed to partisan spirit and all forms of fanaticism and fervor.  Subsequently influential on the Founders, especially Madison whose father possessed the 8-volume set.

1713 publication of the Fourth Edition of the Two Treatises of Government, first to have Locke’s name, containing revisions and additions from a copy corrected by Locke; also included in 1714 Works

1714                               Anne dies. George, Elector of Hanover becomes King George I.

1715   (“The 15”) Jacobite uprising in Scotland and the North of England to place James II’s son, James the Old Pretender on the throne. French support fails to materialize, and the uprising fails.  Tory party, which had experienced a resurgence, is seriously weakened by its flirtation with Jacobitism.

1720-3  John Trenchard and Thomas Gordon (anonymously) publish Cato’s Letters (144 of them) in the London Journal, opposing all forms of domination and tyranny, arguing for freedom of conscience, freedom of speech, and government by consent.  Cato’s Letters were widely available in the colonies in bound volumes—well known to all the Founders.

1720-42  period of greatest power of the Whig leader Sir Robert Walpole (often called in retrospect the first prime minister—but the office did not really yet exist in our sense)  Whigs consolidate power, become committed defenders of the interests of the landed classes.

1739-40 David Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature published

1745  (“The 45”) The Scots Highland Clans rally to another Jacobite uprising, this time led by  Bonnie Prince Charlie (the Young Pretender), the son of the Old Pretender and grandson of James II. The uprising has early success in Scotland, and Jacobite forces progress into England.  Pressed back into Scotland, in 1746 at Culloden, near Inverness, the Jacobites are defeated in bloody battle (first use of the combination of bayonet and long-gun, by the Hanoverian troops.)  Bonnie Prince Charlie flees back to France (and eventually a dissolute life in Rome).  Cruel repression of the Highland clans follows—but many Highlanders (and Lowlands Scots) join the British army in the next decades. Lowland Scotland becomes the home of non-political innovation.

1740’s-c. 1790  The Scottish Enlightenment:  In the cities of Edinburgh, Glasgow, and Aberdeen academies and reading clubs flourish, a turning away from revelation to reason and experience.  Francis Huthcheson (Irish, but Professor at Glasgow), James Watt, Adam Smith, Adam Ferguson, David Hume:  technology, invention, commerce, science, philosophy, economics. The most influential on the American Founders were David Hume and his close friend Adam Smith.

1742-76  David Hume publishes Essays Moral and Political (eventually, after expanding, entitled Essays Moral, Political, and Literary) in many editions, adding and varying the contents over the years through 11 editions (all of these editions were popular),  An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding in 1748 (originally titled Philosophical Essays Concerning Human Understanding), An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals in 1751 (accessibly written but at first not much read), Political Discourses in 1752 (very popular, then incorporated into Essays), and History of England in 6 volumes between 1754 and 1762 (immensely popular). (The Treatise of Human Nature had been largely ignored when published in 1739.)

 

 

 

 

Forthcoming in Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Copyright Canadian Journal of Philosophy

 

Hume’s "Wilt Chamberlain Argument" and Taxation

Kenneth Henley

Florida International University

 

Abstract

Robert Nozick addresses the idea of egalitarian redistribution in an argument standardly considered original: the "Wilt Chamberlain Argument."  However, this argument (without reference to Wilt Chamberlain) is found in David Hume’s An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, first published in 1751. Placing this argument within a Humean and Hayekian, rather than a Lockean or Kantian, perspective radically changes its import for issues of economic justice. Rather than vindicating the radical individualism of Nozick and other libertarians, applied to our circumstances using Hume’s conventionalist and evolutionary account of justice, Hume's Wilt Chamberlain Argument vindicates moderate redistribution constrained by the rule of general laws and the goal of fostering innovation and industriousness.

 

In Anarchy, State, and Utopia Robert Nozick[1] builds an edifice of individual property entitlements upon a Lockean and Kantian foundation:[2] property of all kinds belongs by right to individuals who have acquired it without violating the rights of others, and any redistribution violates the separate personhood of individuals, treating them as mere means to achieve a social goal. In developing his view, Nozick addresses the idea of egalitarian redistribution in an argument standardly considered original: the "Wilt Chamberlain Argument."[3]  However, this argument (without reference to Wilt Chamberlain) is found in David Hume’s An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals,[4] first published in 1751. Placing this argument within a Humean and Hayekian, rather than a Lockean or Kantian, perspective radically changes its import for issues of economic justice. Rather than vindicating the radical individualism of Nozick and other libertarians, applied to our circumstances using Hume’s conventionalist and evolutionary account of justice, Hume's Wilt Chamberlain Argument vindicates moderate redistribution constrained by the rule of general laws and the goal of fostering innovation and industriousness.

Nozick bases his account of property on individual rights: “Individuals have rights, and there are things no person or group may do to them (without violating their rights).”[5] These rights are not derived from positive law, rather they are moral constraints (“side-constraints”[6]) upon all human actions, individual or collective. From this basis the coercive power of the state is subjected to a severe criticism, starting with an account of the state of nature (pre-governmental society) that derives from John Locke. The transition from the state of nature to institutions of government must be accomplished without violating any individual rights, and this requires stages of voluntary protective associations culminating in a dominant protective agency in a geographical territory.[7] Nozick argues that only a minimal state can be justified, for the rights of individuals will be violated by any more extensive use of coercion by the state. The minimal state is limited to protecting individual rights against force and fraud and enforcing voluntary contracts. Coercing individuals to help other individuals, for instance through redistributive taxation, violates individual rights.

The framework of Nozick’s Wilt Chamberlain argument builds upon the distinction between end-result principles of economic justice and patterned distributions of property, on the one hand, and Nozick’s entitlement theory of property, on the other hand.[8] End-result principles specify an outcome as constitutive of a just distribution, regardless of which individuals occupy which slots in the distribution. Utilitarian and egalitarian views are examples of end-result principles. A patterned distribution maintains the array of property along the lines of some favored characteristic, such as moral merit, contributing to social utility, or need. End-result and patterned accounts run afoul of the side-constraints established by individual rights, for achieving and maintaining the result requires governmental coercion of individual economic activity, going well beyond the coercion allowed in the minimal state. In contrast, Nozick’s entitlement theory respects side-constraints. An individual is fully entitled to property if and only if her acquiring that property does not violate any individual rights. The resulting distribution of property among individuals is irrelevant, and although there will be some strands of pattern (for instance, those who offer products or services valued by others will tend to acquire wealth) there need not be an overall pattern. Nozick’s account is “historical”: the only thing relevant is the historical narrative of how a particular individual comes to possess a particular thing. It should be noted that the history in question is not a history of the development of conceptions of justice or of legal regimes regarding property in various societies—the correct conception of justice in Nozick has no history. An individual is entitled to what she acquires in accordance with principles of initial acquisition, transfer, and rectification.[9] The principle of transfer allows transfer of property by exchange, contract, or gift. The principle of rectification establishes methods for correcting violations of individual rights that occurred in the history of the property’s acquisition. As he acknowledges,[10] Nozick does not provide a complete account of any of the principles, and the principle of initial acquisition has unique problems. Of course, violence and other violations of the rights of others are ruled out. But it is not clear how acquisition is accomplished. Nozick raises objections to Locke’s account of acquisition by mixing one’s labor with what is to be taken, but leaves it an open question whether these objections can be met.[11] After an elaborate discussion of the “Lockean proviso”[12]—there must be “enough and as good left in common for others” when appropriating that which is previously unowned—Nozick concludes that a free market will not violate the Lockean proviso and “the proviso will not play a very important role in the activities of protective agencies and will not provide a significant opportunity for future state action.”[13] Thus Nozick seeks to block a potential argument from the Lockean proviso for some form of redistribution.

The Wilt Chamberlain argument is an imaginative counterexample to any end-result or patterned conception of distributive justice--“justice in holdings” in Nozick’s terminology,[14] for Nozick rejects the implications of the phrase “distributive justice,” which seems to imply that property is distributed by some authority or initial owner. Imagine an end-result or pattern, for instance equality (but any redistributive pattern comes under the argument), and then consider the case of a particular talented athlete, Wilt Chamberlain in Nozick’s now dated text. The athlete enters into a contract to receive a set amount of money from the ticket price of home games, and this extra fee is actually deposited into a separate box by each person attending home games. The talented athlete gets a lot of money this way, and so the favored end-result or pattern (for instance, equality) is upset. Nozick explains,

 

The general point illustrated by the Wilt Chamberlain example…is that no end-state principle or distributional patterned principle of justice can be continuously realized without continuous interference with people’s lives….To maintain a pattern one must either continually interfere to stop people from transferring resources as they wish to, or continually (or periodically) interfere to take from some persons resources that others for some reason chose to transfer to them. (…Why not have immediate confiscation?)[15]

 

Hume’s Wilt Chamberlain argument, without the athlete, has a radically different framework. Hume rejects Locke’s natural rights theory of property along with the contract theory of government. Hume insists that “the sense of justice and injustice is not deriv’d from nature, but arises artificially, tho necessarily from education, and human conventions.”[16]  Hume is here contrasting ‘natural’ and ‘artificial’ (in the sense of ‘produced through human artifice or contrivance’). In his distinctive sentimentalist version of virtue theory, there are natural virtues (such as generosity, benevolence, gratitude, and kindness toward children) and artificial virtues (such as justice, promise-keeping, and allegiance). Natural virtues have a basis in sentiments found in human nature, prior to any sense of morality. The artificial virtues are also indirectly dependent on human sentiments (most importantly self-interest), but there are no prior particular sentiments associated with each particular artificial virtue.

“Justice” in both Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature and An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals only concerns property. Annette Baier has recently argued that Hume subsequently expanded his conception of justice to include much in addition to property and even used natural equity to provide critical distance from rules currently in force.[17] But in the Treatise justice is an artificial virtue regarding property, depending upon conventions that develop slowly in society, without prior design. These conventions of justice further long-term enlightened self-interest by providing constraints on immediate motives of self-interest and avidity—the unplanned upshot is a plan of mutual advantage.[18] Hume’s account of promise-keeping follows the same pattern. Hume explains the way conventions of promise-keeping evolve because they serve the mutual advantage of individuals, securing to each what is in his interest.[19] “Afterwards a sentiment of morals concurs with interest, and becomes a new obligation upon mankind. This sentiment of morality, in the performance of promises, arises from the same principles as that in the abstinence from the property of others. Public interest, education, and the artifices of politicians have the same effect in both cases.”[20] Unlike natural virtues such as benevolence, there need be no affective component directed toward either the beneficiary of the conduct or the particular action (except as an instance of rule-following). The affective component of justice and fidelity is directed toward the rules themselves: through conditioning an affective attachment to the rules arises to support the underlying private and public interests.

Hume narrates a kind of speculative history of the gradual development of property, from simple possession validated by informal convention to full protection of property under the rule of law. Government and magistracy fill out the bare-bones of justice and execute its requirements. For my project regarding a Humean perspective on taxation, it is important that Hume sees government as providing a benefit going beyond justice: “But government extends farther its beneficial influence; and not contented to protect men in those conventions they make for their mutual interest, it often obliges them to make such conventions, and forces them to seek their own advantage, by a concurrence in some common end or purpose….Thus bridges are built; harbours opened; ramparts rais’d; canals formed; fleets equip’d; and armies disciplin’d; every where by the care of government....”[21] Government uses coercion to remedy the short-sightedness of individuals and to co-ordinate their efforts in needed public endeavors, where otherwise “each seeks a pretext to free himself of the trouble and expence, and wou’d lay the whole burden on others.”[22]

The second Enquiry drops the grand taxonomy of natural versus artificial virtues, but in substance the distinction remains, and justice retains its conventional and invented status, in contrast with, for instance, benevolence and generosity. We are born (or immigrate) into a particular legal system, with complex rules establishing justice in property. Although the conjectural history of justice in the Treatise is largely dropped in the Enquiry,[23] Hume’s account still places justice regarding property within a historical, evolving framework. As Knud Haakonssen has perspicuously explained, “…Hume’s theory is of such a design that it fairly clearly points out the place of history, without itself being a historical theory….”[24]

Some of the general, abstract property rules are, Hume notes, in a sense “Laws of Nature,”[25] for they are such obvious ways of bringing stability to property that they are found in some form in all human societies: “stability of possession, its translation by consent, and the performance of promises” are fundamental artifices “antecedent to government.”[26] But in every society much more detailed rules are gradually developed, with much that is either a local variant or even arbitrary. In societies with government and the rule of law, conventions harden into complex, highly legalistic rules. Hume emphasizes the contingent and invented features of property:

 

What is a man’s property? Any thing, which it is lawful for him, and for him alone, to use. But what rule have we, by which we can distinguish these objects? Here we must have recourse to statutes, customs, precedents, analogies, and a hundred other circumstances; some of which are constant and inflexible, some variable and arbitrary. But the ultimate point, in which they all professedly terminate, is, the interest and happiness of human society. Where this enters not into consideration, nothing can appear more whimsical, unnatural, and even superstitious, than all or most of the laws of justice and of property.[27]

 

And yet, despite the similarity to religious superstitions, the rules of property are to be inviolably observed, for unlike religious superstition, society cannot subsist without justice in property, with all the varying local details of property rules.[28] These rules include detailed positive law concerning stability of possession: present possession (which can fully determine property only at the beginning of society), occupation, prescription (long possession), accession (when imagination annexes as property what is connected to something already owned), and succession (inheritance).[29] Even the transfer of property by consent requires detailed practices specified by positive law. “The giving of stone and earth represents the delivery of a mannor. This is a kind of superstitious practice in civil laws, and in the laws of nature, resembling the Roman Catholic superstitions in religion...lawyers and moralists have run into like inventions...and have endeavor’d by these means to satisfy themselves concerning the transference of property by consent.”[30] We are not to omit consideration of the interest of human society, and even the observance of arbitrary rules promotes that interest until those rules are changed. Justice regarding property varies, and may be changed by law.[31]

The rules regarding property that are in place in a particular society must be rigidly implemented. The rule of law (governance by law, not men) requires that only general and impersonal rules be allowed to determine matters of property. Property rules are unnaturally “universal and perfectly inflexible.”[32] There must be “strict observance”[33] of “general inflexible rules” establishing “sacred and inviolable” property.[34] The content of specific property rules does not reference any goal such as promoting utility or benefitting those in need. It is the maintenance of the whole system of rules that promotes mutual advantage (private and public utility). For instance, loans must be repaid, even if the creditor is a rich miser and the debtor and his family will become impoverished. As Hume notes,

 

A single act of justice is frequently contrary to public interest; and were it to stand alone, without being followed by other acts, may, in itself, be very prejudicial to society….Nor is every single act of justice, consider’d apart, more conducive to private interest, than to public….But however single acts of justice may be contrary, either to public or private interest, ‘tis certain, that the whole plan or scheme is highly conducive, or indeed absolutely requisite, both to the support of society, and the well-being of every individual. ‘Tis impossible to separate the good from the ill. Property must be stable, and must be fix’d by general rules….And even every individual person must find himself a gainer, on balancing the account; since, without justice, society must immediately dissolve, and every one must fall into that savage and solitary condition, which is infinitely worse than the worst situation that can possibly be suppos’d in society.[35]

 

Each particular act of a natural virtue such as benevolence is like a stone added to a wall, contributing on its own to the building of happiness. Justice, in contrast, is like a vault—only the whole scheme, not individual parts, serves the purpose of promoting mutual advantage.[36]

This conventionalist account of justice in property is the setting for Hume’s “Wilt Chamberlain” argument in the second Enquiry.[37] Hume imagines a rational being with no knowledge of human nature designing a property regime. One possibility would be to assign property according to virtue or merit, but this would require a god-like insight into each individual’s desert, and there are varying standards of merit even so. Equality then might seem to this rational, but ill-informed, designer the best rule of justice. Hume notes that utopian schemes such as those of the Levellers during the English Civil War took this view. In a striking application of, it seems to me, the idea of declining marginal utility, Hume acknowledges that inequalities “rob the poor of more satisfaction than we add to the rich, and that the slight gratification of a frivolous vanity, in one individual, frequently costs more than bread to many families and even provinces.”[38]  Yet despite such unfortunate results of abandoning equality, once knowledge of human nature is taken into account, a regime of equality cannot be maintained, and even attempting it would risk impoverishment of the society and even tyranny:

 

Render possessions ever so equal, men’s different degrees of art, care, and industry will immediately break that equality. Or if you check these virtues, you reduce society to the most extreme indigence….The most rigorous inquisition too is requisite to watch every inequality on its first appearance; and the most severe jurisdiction, to punish and redress it. …so much authority must soon degenerate into tyranny, and be exerted with great partialities….[39]

 

This is Hume’s “Wilt Chamberlain Argument.” Hume clearly understood the same point that Nozick came to see about 200 years later. But in Hume that point does not contribute to an argument for the minimal state or any other radically individualist norm. Hume locates the Wilt Chamberlain point within a conventionalist, evolutionary and pragmatic account of justice.

The passage I call “Hume’s Wilt Chamberlain Argument” has not gone unnoticed by commentators, although the comparison to Nozick seems to have escaped comment. Both David Miller[40] and Annette Baier[41] have placed the passage into their interpretations of Hume, but with very different views of Hume’s underlying point. Miller sees Hume’s point as entirely opposed to any attempt to foster equality. In contrast, Baier sees Hume as sympathetic to the goal of equality, but recognizing that the goal cannot be achieved without disastrous results. Baier’s interpretation of the crucial passage comports with her argument that Hume evinced a halting but developing concern for equity or fairness as a natural virtue, allowing for criticism of the established conventions and laws of justice.[42] In her view, Hume considered that equity required at minimum that an individual get what the conventions and laws dictate, but equity still provided a standard of criticism to further fairness by reform.

My project is to situate Hume’s insights in the passage within a Humean conventionalist, legalist, evolutionary account of Wilt Chamberlain’s (and our) society, contrasting Nozick’s use of these same insights within his individual natural property-rights framework. Baier’s emphasis on equity in Hume fits with an application to our society that burdens the rich through progressive taxation, constrained by promoting industry and innovation.

There is no entry for “Hume” in the index of Anarchy, State, and Utopia, and this makes sense on two counts. First, Hume was then treated almost entirely as an epistemologist and meta-ethicist, and his political philosophy was largely ignored, except for the attack on contract theory in his essay “Of the Original Contract,”[43] and his account of the circumstances of justice[44], for instance, as discussed in Rawls’s A Theory of Justice.[45] Secondly, Nozick’s Lockean (and to a lesser extent, Kantian) presuppositions hide even the possibility of confronting an account like Hume’s that refuses to treat ownership as a fundamental concept, without a social origin that evolves into the complexity of varying positive law.

And yet it is still puzzling that Nozick ignores Hume, for Nozick’s chief economist, rather than philosopher, is F. A. Hayek, and he was not a Lockean, but a Humean. Although Hayek is best known for his warning against the danger to liberty of adopting a centralized command economy,[46] and as a Nobel-laureate economist, he wrote extensively about social and political theory and the history of Western conceptions of liberty and the rule of law.

Hayek developed an account of the social evolution of justice that is Humean in its conventionalism and reliance on historical development. Hayek shares Hume’s rejection of natural rights accounts of justice, and thus is fundamentally different from the Lockean libertarians (such as Nozick), despite their attempts to gloss over the contrast.  Hayek considers the social evolution of “spontaneous order” the key to institutions of law and liberty in Western democracies.[47] Hume’s conception of conventions that arise antecedently to government, as individuals seek to promote their own interests, is echoed in Hayek’s idea of spontaneous order, and Hume is frequently invoked by Hayek.

Hayek’s essay on Hume’s legal and political philosophy[48] would have provided Nozick with all he needed to explain and, presumably, then offer a rebuttal to a Humean account. In this essay, Hayek emphasizes Hume’s empirical narrative of the gradual unfolding, without prior design, of the conventions regarding justice in property and the rule of law. He contrasts this non-rationalist, social evolutionary approach to “constructivist rationalism,” and notes that Locke was not untouched by such rationalism.[49] Unlike Lockean libertarian conservatives, Hayek--who refused the label “conservative”[50]--approved of using resources in an affluent society to support those in need, as long as that is done without disturbing markets, through procedures of representative democracy, and using proportional rather than progressive taxation.[51]

Let us consider the actual Wilt Chamberlain. He was born into a nation with laws, including very detailed and extensive laws regarding property. Applying Hume’s conventionalist, legalist, and evolutionary account to Chamberlain’s (and our) society, a modest degree of redistributive (though not leveling) taxation was long established as an element of justice. In the Enquiry shortly after his Wilt Chamberlain argument, Hume writes, “…all questions of property are subordinate to authority of civil laws, which extend, restrain, modify, and alter the rules of natural justice, according to the particular convenience of each community. The laws have, or ought to have, a constant reference to the constitution of government, the manners, the climate, the religion, the commerce, the situation of each society.”[52] Every opportunity available to Wilt Chamberlain was substantially affected by the surrounding economy and legal system, for it is impossible to consider one individual’s earning chances apart from the surrounding social and economic context. People cannot purchase any good or service except with what has relative worth (money in its varying buying power), and a society unable to fund star athletes with huge salaries might have someone in it with Wilt Chamberlain’s talents, but without the chance to pay him (indeed, without even the elaborate structure of professional sports and mass media). As he entered into his career, he found himself in a society with all the media and other structures that enabled the career, and he was under laws governing every aspect of property and income. Most relevant to the Wilt Chamberlain Argument, he was subject, equally to everyone else, to the tax laws. These laws did not seek to equalize property, but they did include progressive taxation (though mitigated by many major ways to shelter income from the top rates). When the actual Wilt Chamberlain earned a dollar, some part of it was already not his, but rather belonged to the government under which the very concept of a dollar had meaning and within whose laws property was established. Let us imagine that there are two boxes, the first marked “Wilt Chamberlain’s Net” and the second marked “Wilt Chamberlain’s Contribution to the National Budget” (or “from W.C. to the United States Treasury”). Each fan is required to bring quarters, and put three into the first box and one into the second. This reflects the fact that the taxpayer owes taxes ab initio and what one owes is not really one’s own.

Wilt Chamberlain would be making a larger contribution to the national budget even if taxation is not progressive, but rather proportional. In “Of Some Remarkable Customs,” Hume notes a historical example of laws changing from taking the same absolute amount from everyone to proportional taxation: “Thus Demosthenes, finding that ship-money was levied irregularly, and that the poor bore the same burden as the rich in equipping the gallies, corrected this inequality by a very useful law, which proportioned the expence to the revenue and income of each individual.”[53] As allowed by Athenian procedures, the resentful rich brought an unsuccessful criminal complaint against Demosthenes for the innovation. But why not take the same absolute dollar amount from each taxpayer, regardless of income (perhaps with a floor below which no tax is due)? Equal contribution can mean either equal absolute amount or equal percentage, as seen in Hume’s account of Demosthenes: bearing the same (an equal) burden is yet called an “inequality” by Hume, the correction of which is “a very useful law.” (Note Hume’s approval of reforming law.)

After all, Nozick is correct that it is the voluntary decision of individual fans to pay extra to see Wilt Chamberlain play, and the extra money they give to him comes from their after-tax income, so, after contributing the same absolute amount in tax as everyone else, Chamberlain should be able to keep all the rest, avoiding double taxation. (This is similar to the view of those who assert that the estate tax constitutes double taxation.) The explanation of proportional taxation is given by F. A. Hayek:

 

…since almost all economic activity benefits from the basic services of government, these services form a more or less constant ingredient of all we consume and enjoy and that, therefore, a person who commands more of the resources of society will also gain proportionally more from what the government has contributed. More important…proportional taxation leaves the relations between the net remunerations of different kinds of work unchanged.[54]

 

It should be noted that Hayek’s argument can be converted into an argument for progressive taxation by indicating that the very rich gain not merely proportionally more from what government contributes in a particular society, but rather they gain extremely disproportionally more. But Hayek rejects progressive taxation, although a specific kind of tax such as the income tax may need to be graduated in order to compensate for the disproportionate impact of indirect taxes upon those with lower incomes. Hayek considers substantially progressive taxation a violation of the principle of equality under law.[55]  The point to consider for Nozick’s use of the Wilt Chamberlain Argument is that Hayek’s objection to progressive taxation is not based on Lockean conceptions of a natural right to property, but rather on a Humean concern that justice requires general rules that can be applied impartially. It is obscure why Hayek holds that progressivity necessarily involves the injustice of partiality or lack of generality, for although progressive taxation could be an element in a tax regime that fails to provide general rules that can be applied impartially, the failure would not be in virtue of the progressivity, but rather other features (e.g., extreme complexity and ad hoc provisions favoring special interests) making the incidence of taxation either unpredictable or so individualized as not to be law-like. Hayek’s own general account of taxation as consistent with liberty and the rule of general law seems to require only that the incidence of the tax be predictable.[56] And Hume’s view is similar: generality requires that law “regard alone some essential circumstances of the case, without taking into consideration the characters, situations, and connexions of the person concerned, or any particular consequences which may result….”[57] Framing law in terms of “some essential circumstances” will make its application predictable and not arbitrary. Hume criticized taxation in France because of “the expensive, unequal, arbitrary, and intricate method of levying them, by which the industry of the poor, especially of the peasants and farmers, is…discouraged….”[58] The inequality Hume means is partiality and unpredictability in application of the tax law by the French tax farmers. There is nothing in Hume’s account that precludes general tax laws that are progressive, when impartially applied.

From a Humean social evolutionary approach (pace Hayek), non-confiscatory, moderately progressive taxation can be seen as having been tested in various societies and found to be consistent with providing incentives for people to be industrious and use their talents in creative and innovative ways that benefit both themselves and society. Nozick’s Lockean natural rights approach to property does not allow him to accept even proportional taxation, at least as used to go beyond the confines of the minimal state.

In “Of Taxes,” considering excise and customs taxes, Hume argues that such taxes will, at least under some conditions and when not onerous, cause “the common people” to “increase their industry” so as to maintain their standard of living.[59] Taxation must not, however, be so onerous as to cause innervating despair. But in contrast Hume judges that “The best taxes are such as are levied upon consumptions, especially those of luxury; because such taxes are least felt by the people.”[60] As these almost opposing points about impacts of taxation on the common people illustrate, Hume had a complex perspective concerning economic classes and the emerging commercial society. He rejected the standard mercantilist view of the “Utility of Poverty,” which considered poverty as the necessary motivation for the poor to work.[61] And yet Hume did appeal to increased industry through need created by moderate taxation, and he did think that the enclosures would stimulate productivity both through improved agricultural methods and by casting the rural poor out of their low-level contentment into the urban workforce.[62] And Hume disapproved of giving to beggars, considering this short-sighted benevolence.[63] His view of these three matters seems to concede that need does have some role in motivating work. But again in contrast to his view of beggars, Hume affirmed an obligation to help the needy: “A rich man lies under a moral obligation to communicate to those in necessity a share of his superfluities.”[64]

Despite conceding some force to need-motivation, Hume’s main emphasis falls on the productivity-motivating roles of the desire for action and for acquiring sources of enjoyment, in addition to the obvious desire for gain. The desire for recognition and social approval based on one’s prosperity and the fineness of one’s possessions also motivates industrious activity, for on Hume’s view pride is generally a virtue, not a vice. So luxury (refinement in taste that is a source of admiration) is on balance socially beneficial.

Shifting attention concerning taxation from the present to Hume’s time requires focusing on excise taxes and what we now call sales taxes rather than income tax. This shift in focus enables us to see the weakness of Nozick’s assimilation of taxation to forced labor.[65]  Nozick is able to play on the idea of an hourly wage (he ignores the inconvenient existence of salaried workers) to argue that taxing a person is (or is analogous to) forcing that person to work for the time it takes to pay the tax. Hume favors taxing luxury goods because that impacts the bulk of people the least—thus Hume favors what Nozick considers an end-state principle of taxation. But the question of how many hours (or what kind) of labor is forced by the luxury tax seems inapplicable. The rich person buying the luxury may not do any kind of labor or work; he may have inherited wealth or property generating wealth. Hume approved of luxury, when not pursued to the detriment of duties and showing benevolence to others,[66] as a spur to industriousness and progress: “To imagine, that the gratifying of any sense, or the indulging of any delicacy in meat, drink, or apparel, is of itself a vice, can never enter into a head, that is not disordered by the frenzies of enthusiasm.”[67]  So his preference for luxury taxes was not based on puritanical sentiment, but rather on concern to burden the rich more than the poor—a kind of progressive taxation. So when Wilt Chamberlain or LeBron James buys a Rolex, a tiny bit of judicious progressive taxation would not be expected to weaken the work ethic. The same can be said of a bit of progressivity in an income tax in our society, with the question how steep the progression before undesirable effects occur a matter to be determined by experience. Although on Hume’s “Wilt Chamberlain” argument liberty and prosperity are inconsistent with maintaining equality of wealth, taxing the rich more than others is justified and consistent with both liberty and a commercial society that fosters industriousness.

I draw two conclusions from this inquiry, the first regarding the nature of property in liberal political theory. The contrast between Nozick and Hume is instructive in understanding two very different strands of classical liberalism (both distinct from welfare liberalism, for instance John Rawls): the Lockean strand that leads to individualist libertarianism with only a minimal state, and the Humean strand (also found in Hayek, openly indebted to Hume) that leads towards some version of modest liberalism, recognizing a role for the state that is larger than the minimal state, but limited by the need to maintain motivation for individuals to be productive and the working of commercial society with a free market. The “Wilt Chamberlain Argument” provides a point of entry into the debate, for the specific insight in this argument is precisely the same in both Hume and Nozick, but the significance of that insight varies radically depending upon the larger framework, Lockean natural property rights versus Humean conventionalism.

The second conclusion is about the difficulty of interpretation of Hume on property and taxation. Hume’s view, taken as a whole, is exceedingly complex. He seeks to reconcile elements that are in tension, even potentially contradictory. The most important of the elements are Hume’s insistence on rigid conformity to inflexible current legal rules regarding property in a particular society, his recognition that laws sometimes need to be reformed, his defense of commercial society (which requires motivation of industriousness), and his humane concern to help those in need. Any attempt to smooth over these disparate elements must be untrue to Hume’s thought.

 

 

Hume’s Deflationary Theory of Allegiance

Kenneth Henley

 

·         Hume argues that no account of allegiance can always provide a determinate answer to the question whether allegiance is owed to a particular regime by a particular person.

·         Hume’s deflationary theory seeks to explain why this disappointment is unavoidable—why there cannot be a robust theory that provides a decision in every case.

·         Allegiance is indeed virtuous, for it rests on self-interest and, through sympathy, upon social or public interests. There can be no government without allegiance, and government is needed in order to settle disputes and provide for public goods through cooperative endeavor.

·         But there can be no such thing as abstract allegiance—allegiance as a virtue of an actual person must have a particular object of allegiance. Although allegiance arouses approbation, the object of allegiance may be unfortunate and the actual allegiance may arouse disapprobation because the attachment is fanatical and defeats the purpose of  promoting utility.

Four Rejected Robust Accounts

1.   Religious Fanaticism: Divine Right or Appointed by God.

2.   Philosophical Fanaticism: Lockean Contract or Individual Consent.

3.   Philosophical Rationalism: Allegiance only to the particular regime that best promotes public interests.

4.   Passive Obedience: Allegiance regardless of the impact of the regime upon public interests.

Grounds for Rejecting the Robust Accounts

·         Neither human will nor human reason suffices for convergence and stability of allegiance.

Both fanatical accounts are voluntarist: will of God or will of individuals. There is no way to settle disagreements about the will of God, and individual wills cannot be expected to converge in a stable way over time.

The philosophical-rationalist account exaggerates the capacity of reasoning to settle such matters regarding particular outcomes in a way that allows for the needed consensus. Stability and shared allegiance are of greater importance than directly consulting social advantage to determine allegiance, for interminable disputes would result if we sought to use such a rational standard as interest, private or public. ’Tis interest which gives the general instinct; but ‘tis custom which gives the particular direction.” (T 3.2.10.4; SBN 556)

·         Passive obedience severs altogether the connection between particular allegiance and the underlying point of allegiance-in-general—to promote public interests by establishing a structure for dispute resolution and providing public goods.

 

The Principles for Deciding Allegiance

1.   Long possession

2.   Present Possession

3.   Conquest

4.   Succession

5.   Positive Laws

·         A plurality of principles cannot constitute a decision procedure unless there is never a conflict or there are rules for resolving conflicts.

·         There are conflicts, and there are no rules for resolving conflicts, even when Positive Laws purport to be determinative.

The Contrast with Fidelity (Promise-keeping)

·         Fidelity to promises facilitates cooperative endeavors among private persons by engendering mutual trust. Allegiance undergirds peace and order in the society as a whole. Both are advantageous, but neither works through the other. (T 3.2.8.6; SBN 544) Thus to base allegiance on promise is both to introduce a needless intermediate step and to misconstrue the separate moral sentiment of allegiance as a species of promise-keeping.

·         Unlike fidelity to promises, allegiance must take its object where it finds it, at least in the usual case: “We naturally suppose ourselves born to submission; and imagine, that such particular persons have a right to command, as we on our part are bound to obey.” (T 3.2.10.3; SBN 555)

The Contrast with Justice (regarding property)

·         The two artificial virtues of justice-regarding-property and allegiance share many features, including, of course, the basis in convention.

·         But justice can be made determinate within a particular community by shared conventions that give fine-grained and consistent general rules for deciding who has title to what property. Allegiance does not as readily lend itself to such determinacy, and in some circumstances there simply is no clear answer to the question who has title to allegiance.

 

Hume considers allegiance highly contingent when taken as including a particular object, and seeks to deflate its pretensions, diminishing fanatical strife. In general and usually, there is no comparable worry about justice regarding property, for within a stable regime that holds the allegiance of the citizens, property can be re-assigned and redistributed under the rule of law without the chaos of disputes about allegiance, which may lead to civil war. Thus Present Possession has a very different role in matters of property and questions of allegiance. Only if property disputes lead to widespread abandonment of allegiance would there be anything that could be called a fanaticism of justice regarding property.

 

Chronology Continued through Federalist Papers

 

1740’s through c. 1789   The French Enlightenment.  Building upon Descartes’s earlier philosophy of clear and distinct ideas and upon the confidence in reason fostered by Newton and Locke, the French philosophes foster critical inquiry and scientific progress:  Diderot, d’Alembert, Montesquieu, Helvetius, Voltaire, Rousseau.  The Encyclopedie published 1751-72.  For the American Founders, Montesquieu was the most important, but all were read and respected.

1748  Montesquieu publishes The Spirit of Laws, argues for separation of powers in government—influenced by Locke and by Montesquieu’s somewhat inaccurate understanding of the functioning of the English constitution. An important influence upon the Founders.

1732-1752  Benjamin Franklin publishes Poor Richard’s Almanack.  He also conducts scientific experiments and observations (most famously concerning electricity) and invents.  Franklin gains great fame in England and on the Continent as scientist, inventor, and paradigmatic American. During the period 1757-1775 he spent most years in England, representing various American colonial causes.

1763    French and Indian Wars end. Great Britain soon seeks to recoup some of its cost from the colonists and arrange for them to bear some of the expense for their defense.

1764    Tax on molasses and sugar—but this is seen by most as an indirect tax connected to admitted right of Parliament to control navigation and commerce among its dominions

1765    The Stamp Act passed by Parliament during George Grenville’s ministry. First direct tax imposed on colonists, applied to newspapers, pamphlets, advertisements, all legal papers.  Sons of Liberty organized to oppose the perceived abuse of power by Parliament.  James Otis, Sam Adams, and Patrick Henry attack the Act. Stamp Act Congress protested that the rights of Englishmen (the colonials) violated by taxing them without representation in Parliament.  Repealed in 1766, but Parliament declares its right to tax colonies.

1767 The Townshend Acts: taxed imports of paper, glass, lead, paints, and tea.  These the British considered “external” or “indirect” taxes, but this time the Americans do not accept the distinction. Massachusetts activists Sam Adams, John Dickinson and others agitate against the tax.  British troops sent to enforce collection and maintain order. Repealed in 1770, but with the tax on tea kept to maintain claim of right of Parliament to tax Americans.

1770   March 5: The Boston Massacre.  Under great provocation and in fear for their lives, British troops fire on a mob, killing five.  Used as a propaganda tool by the American patriots.  British soldiers are indicted for murder.  But although themselves opposed to the British policies, John Adams and Josiah Quincy brilliantly defend the soldiers tried for murder, vindicating the rule of law. (Six are acquitted and two convicted of manslaughter only.)

1773    Dec. 16: The Boston Tea Party.  Sam Adams, Paul Revere and others dress as Native Americans and at night throw tea (belonging to the East India Company) from three ships into Boston harbor.

1774    “The Intolerable Acts,” name given by colonials to 5 Acts of Parliament, 4 of them passed as punishment for the Boston Tea Party.  Port of Boston closed until restitution to East India Co. for lost tea; changes in royal charter of Massachusetts; quartering of troops without consent by colonial assemblies; royal officials in colonies given right to trial in England. The 5th Act was the Quebec Act, establishing a permanent administration in Canada, religious freedom (disturbing to the Protestant colonists because of fear of Catholic power), and extending Canadian boundaries (thus nullifying claims of the colonies).

1774    The First Continental Congress meets in Philadelphia.  Petitions of grievance sent to the King, ban on importation of British goods.

1774    To the Virginia Convention Thomas Jefferson presents A Summary View of the Rights of British America, arguing that the only tie to Britain is voluntary allegiance to the King; Parliament has no authority over America, he argues.

1775    April 19: Battles of Lexington and Concord.  Armed conflict begins.

1775    May 10: Second Continental Congress meets in Philadelphia. Continental Army created; John Adams is instrumental in having George Washington appointed commander in chief.

1776    January:  Thomas Paine (in America only two years) publishes Common Sense anonymously—“by an Englishman”--(though author soon known), arguing that Americans have no need for ties to Great Britain and every right to independence.

1776    John Adams publishes Thoughts on Government (in response to Paine’s omission of any account of what to build in place of the structure to be torn down), arguing for government by consent and aimed at the happiness of the people; independence of judiciary; the rule of law: government by law not men, “an empire of laws and not of men” (in James Harrington’s phrase); bicameral legislature as guard against usurpation of popular sovereignty by legislature

1776    May.  The 25-year old James Madison represents Orange County in the Virginia Convention (meeting in Williamsburg), which formally votes for independence.  Madison’s main contributions during the framing of the Virginia Declaration of Rights (eventually a model for the Bill of Rights) concern freedom of conscience.

1776    July 4:  The Declaration of Independence.  (David Hume dies in August.)

1775-1781  The War of Independence.  Beginning with the Battles of Lexington and Concord, Massachusetts (Apr. 19, 1775), and ending Oct. 19, 1781 at Yorktown, Virginia, where American (under Washington) and French (under Rochambeau) forces decisively defeat the British under Cornwallis (bottled up by the French fleet).  For much of the war the young, brilliant Alexander Hamilton had been of great service as Washington's secretary and aide-de-camp.  But he sought direct combat in 1781 and performed valiantly in the field at Yorktown.  Hamilton married into the influential Schuyler family of New York, practiced law, and became a member of the Continental Congress under the Articles of Confederation, which he early judged to be unacceptable as a basis for sustaining the Union.

1781  Articles of Confederation ratified by the holdout state, Maryland. (adopted by Congress in 1777).  A "league of friendship" for common defense and to conduct foreign affairs, with a weak central government; each state retained full sovereignty; voting in Congress by states; Congress itself combined executive & legislative functions, though a Committee of the States, with one delegate from each state, to sit as executive when Congress in recess.  Ratification required unanimity, and amendment would require agreement by Congress and the legislature of every state.  Articles had few of the features that Adams had argued for in Thoughts on Government

1783  Treaty of Paris of 1783. Formally recognizes the United States of America as a sovereign state and establishes the terms of peace among Britain as against France and Spain.  Preliminary articles between Britain and U.S. signed in 1782 (unchanged in final Treaty): John Adams, Benjamin Franklin, & John Jay achieve a great diplomatic victory for the new nation--very favorable boundaries.

1786-7  Shays's Rebellion: armed insurrection against state government by debt-ridden farmers in Western Massachusetts. State legislature had not responded to petitions to halt foreclosures, end imprisonment for debt, and issue paper money; high land taxes and economic depression had led to crisis.  Daniel Shays (former officer of the Continental Army) led insurgents (armed only with pitchforks) in Berkshire Hills & Connecticut Valley, preventing courts from sitting to judge debt cases; early in Sept., 1786, forced state Supreme Court to adjourn. Early in 1787, attacked federal arsenal, though easily repelled by Massachusetts militia. Shays fled to Vermont. Most were pardoned immediately, Shays pardoned in June of 1788.  Shays's Rebellion contributed to the pressure for a stronger national government (to avert the economic problems that led to the insurrection and to provide greater protection of property) and influenced the Massachusetts ratification convention.

1786   Annapolis Convention.  Called by Virginia to consider the regulation of commerce. Only 5 states sent representatives.  With the moderating influence of Madison, Alexander Hamilton composes an address to the states asking them to send delegates to Philadelphia in May 1787 to consider amending the Articles to strengthen the national government. This is extraconstitutional, but after 5 states have already selected delegates, Congress issues a resolution encouraging attendance. Shays's Rebellion was underway during this entire period, and played a role in the building consensus for the Philadelphia Convention.

1787  May 25-Sept. 17  The Constitutional Convention meets in Philadelphia. Only Rhode Island declines to send delegates. (However, New York eventually ceases to have a quorum of delegates when two leave in protest, leaving Alexander Hamilton as an individual delegate unable to cast his state's vote. So only 11 states send the Constitution for ratification to the 13.) Absent are John Adams (ambassador to Great Britain), Jefferson (ambassador to France), and Patrick Henry (elected but refused to serve, smelling a rat--became a vigorous opponent of ratification). Washington is elected president of the convention.

On May 29, Washington recognizes Virginia Governor Edmund Randolph, who presents the “Virginia Plan,” the work of James Madison. This plan set out the three separate powers and important structural features creating a strong national government to replace the Confederation. It also favors the larger states.

On June 15, William Patterson of New Jersey presents the “New Jersey Plan,” which favors the smaller states.

The aging Benjamin Franklin bestows his benign participation, helping to forge the compromises needed. James Madison of Virginia has the most impact, then Alexander Hamilton of New York and James Wilson (Scottish born) of Pennsylvania. Oliver Ellsworth and Roger Sherman, both of Connecticut, were very important. Gouverneur Morris chaired the committee of style, which produced the final text.  George Mason, primary author of the Virginia Declaration of Rights, refuses to sign, partly because of the lack of a Bill of Rights.  Illegally breaking with the amendment provisions of the Articles of Confederation, the proposed Constitution is to be submitted for ratification to popularly elected special Ratification Conventions in each state. Nine states are required for ratification.

1787  Oct. 27, 1787-May 28, 1788  The Federalist Papers. Alexander Hamilton decides to publish defenses of the proposed Constitution in newspapers to influence ratification in New York (where ratification seems very much in doubt). Writing under the name "Publius" he gains the cooperation of John Jay for the project, but Jay is soon wounded in a street riot.  Madison (in New York as member of Continental Congress) is recruited to replace Jay.  Jay wrote only 5 (4 of them early), Madison 29, and Hamilton 51.  After newspaper publication, the papers are immediately published in book form, two volumes (Hamilton wrote the final 8 to fill out the second volume). The Federalist was not successful in getting the people of New York to elect federalists to the New York Convention, and it had little influence during the Convention.  New York was prepared to reject the Constitution, but after the required 9th state ratified, it decided not to remain outside the Union.

 

Montesquieu and Madison on Separation of Powers

 

“In every government there are three sorts of power; the legislative; the executive, in respect to things dependent on the law of nations; and the executive, in regard to things that depend on the civil law.

By virtue of the first, the prince or magistrate enacts temporary or perpetual laws, and amends or abrogates those that have been already enacted. By the second, he makes peace or war, sends or receives embassies; establishes the public security, and provides against invasions. By the third, he punishes criminals, or determines the disputes that arise between individuals. The latter we shall call the judiciary power, and the other simply the executive power of the state.

The political liberty of the subject is a tranquility of mind, arising from the opinion each person has of his safety. In order to have this liberty, it is requisite the government be so constituted as one man need not be afraid of another.

When the legislative and executive powers are united in the same person, or in the same body of magistrates, there can be no liberty; because apprehensions may arise, lest the same monarch or senate should enact tyrannical laws, to execute them in a tyrannical manner.

Again, there is no liberty, if the power of judging be not separated from the legislative and executive powers. Were it joined with the legislative, the life and liberty of the subject would be exposed to arbitrary control, for the judge would then be the legislator. Were it joined to the executive power, the judge might behave with all the violence of an oppressor.

There would be an end of every thing were the same man, or the same body, whether of the nobles or of the people to exercise those three powers that of enacting laws, that of executing the public resolutions, and that of judging the crimes or differences of individuals.” Charles de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, vol. 1, trans. Thomas Nugent (London: J. Nourse, 1777), pp. 221-237, passim.

 

"Power being found by universal experience liable to abuses, a distribution of it into separate departments, has become a first principle of free governments. By this contrivance, the portion entrusted to the same hands being less, there is less room to abuse what is granted; and the different hands being interested, each in maintaining its own, there is less opportunity to usurp what is not granted. Hence the merited praise of governments modelled on a partition of their powers into legislative, executive, and judiciary, and a repartition of the legislative into different houses.

The political system of the United States claims still higher praise. The power delegated by the people is first divided between the general government and the state governments; each of which is then subdivided into legislative, executive, and judiciary departments. And as in a single government these departments are to be kept separate and safe, by a defensive armour for each; so, it is to be hoped, do the two governments possess each the means of preventing or correcting unconstitutional encroachments of the other." James Madison, "Government of the United States," National Gazette, Feb. 6, 1792, in James Madison, Writings, (New York: The Library of America, 1999), p. 508.

 

 

 



[1] Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books,1974).

[2] Nozick, Anarchy, 10-12, 30-33.

[3] Nozick, Anarchy, 161-64.

[4] David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Tom L. Beauchamp, ed., (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), 20-1 (Section 3, paragraph 26).

[5] Nozick, Anarchy, ix.

[6] Nozick, Anarchy, 28-35.

[7] Nozick, Anarchy, 15-25, 88-119.

[8] Nozick, Anarchy, 153-60.

[9] Nozick, Anarchy, 150-153.

[10] Nozick, Anarchy, 153.

[11] Nozick, Anarchy, 174-178.

[12] Nozick, Anarchy, 175-182.

[13] Nozick, Anarchy, 182.

[14] Nozick, Anarchy, 149-50.

[15] Nozick, Anarchy, 163.

[16] David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, L. A. Selby-Bigge, ed., (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1888), 483 (T.3.2.1.17).

[17] Annette C. Baier, The Cautious, Jealous Virtue: Hume on Justice (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press, 2010), 83-99.

[18] Hume, Treatise, 492 (T.3.2.2.13).

[19] Hume, Treatise, 522 (T.3.2.5.10).

[20] Hume, Treatise, 523 (T.3.2.5.12).

[21] Hume, Treatise, 538 (T.3.2.7.8).

[22] Ibid.

[23] Baier, Cautious, 80.

[24] Knud Haakonssen, The Science of a Legislator: The Natural Jurisprudence of David Hume and Adam Smith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 38.

[25] Hume, Treatise, 484 (T.3.2.1.19).

[26] Hume, Treatise, 541 (T.3.2.8.3).

[27] Hume, Enquiry, 23 (Section 3, paragraph 35).

[28] Hume, Enquiry, 24-25 (Section 3, paragraph 38-39).

[29] Hume, Treatise,  501-513 (T.3.2.3.1-3.2.3.11).

[30] Hume, Treatise, 515-516 (T. 3.2.4.2).

[31] Hume, Treatise, 528 (T.3.2.6.6).

[32] Hume, Treatise, 532 (T 3.2.6.9).

[33] Hume, Treatise, 526 (T 3.2.6.1).

[34] Hume, Treatise, 533 (T 3.2.6.10).

[35] Hume, Treatise, 497 (T.3.2.2.22).

[36] Hume, Enquiry, 97 (Appendix 3, paragraph 5). And see Jordan Howard Sobel, Walls and Vaults: A Natural Science of Morals (Virtue Ethics According to David Hume) (Hoboken, N.J., John Wiley & Sons, 2009), pp. 227-28.

[37] Hume, Enquiry, 19-21 (Section 3, paragraph 23-27).

[38] Hume, Enquiry, 20 (Section 3, paragraph 25).

[39] Hume, Enquiry, 20-21 (Section 3, paragraph 26)

[40] David Miller, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume’s Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), 66.

[41] Baier, Cautious, 62-63, 85.

[42] Baier, Cautious, 74-76, 81-82, 85.

[43] David Hume, Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, E. F. Miller, ed., (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1987), 465-87.

[44] Hume, Enquiry, 13-16 (Section 3, paragraph 1-13).

[45] John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971) 126-30.

[46] F. A. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1944).

[47] F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation, and Liberty, Vol I: Rules and Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,, 1973), 22-123.

[48] F.A.Hayek, “The Legal and Political Philosophy of David Hume,” in Hume: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed.V. C. Chappell (Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 1966), 335-60.

[49] Hayek, “Legal and Political,” 336.

[50] F.A.Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960), 397-411.

[51] F.A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty, vol. I: Rules and Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973), 141-42, and Hayek, Constitution, 306-23.

[52] Hume, Enquiry, 22 (Section 3, paragraph 34).

[53] Hume, Essays, 367.

[54] Hayek, Constitution, 315-16.

[55] Hayek, Constitution, 306-15.

[56] Hayek, Constitution, 143.

[57] Hume, Enquiry, 97 (Appendix 3, paragraph 6).

[58] Hume, Essays, 95.

[59] Hume, Essays, 343.

[60] Hume, Essays, 345.

[61] Edward Soule, “Hume on Economic Policy and Human Nature,” Hume Studies 26 (2000): 147; M.G. Marshall, “Luxury, Economic Development, and Work Motivation: David Hume, Adam Smith, and J. R. McCulloch,” History of Political Economy 32 (2000): 634; Andrew S. Skinner, “David Hume: Principles of Political Economy,” in The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. David Fate Norton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 223.

[62] Carl Wennerlind, “David Hume’s Political Philosophy: A Theory of Commercial Modernization,” Hume Studies 28 (2002): 258-59.

[63] Hume, Enquiry, 11 (Section 2, paragraph 18).

[64] Hume, Treatise, 482 (T.3.2.1.14).

[65] Nozick, Anarchy, 169-70.

[66] Ryu Susato, “Hume’s Nuanced Defense of Luxury,” Hume Studies 32 (2006):167-86.

[67] Hume, Essays, 268.