Supplement for the Fifth
Class
Copyright © 2023 Bruce W.
Hauptli
I. Questions From
Last Time.
II. Chapter
Five: Distributing Primary Schooling:
127-128 According to Gutmann the principle of
nondiscrimination serves as a guide to answering the question “how
should primary education be distributed:” it suggests
the ideal of equal educational
opportunity for all. But
elaboration is needed regarding what
resources should be committed to this educational project (rather than to
other projects), how should these
resources be distributed amongst children, and
how should children be distributed
between schools?
Interpreting Equal Educational Opportunity:
128 She discusses three responses
to these “distribution problems:”
129-131
maximization: devote sufficient so as
to maximize the life chance of all future citizens
129 The hidden weakness of
maximization is what may be called the problem of moral ransom.
The rule offers us something morally valuable on the implicit condition
that we give up everything else we value.
131 …democratic citizens should
be free not only to set priorities among all the goods that expand educational
opportunity, but also to choose between educational opportunity and all the
other goods that it excludes.
131-134
equalization: distribute the
resources so that the life chances of the least advantaged children are raised
as far as possible toward those of the most advantaged
132 To equalize educational
opportunities, the state would have to intrude so far into family life as to
violate the equally important liberal ideal family autonomy.
133 …many differences in
educational achievement can be eliminated only by eradicating the different
intellectual, cultural, and emotional dispositions and attachments of children
134 The democratic truth in
equalization is that all children should learn enough to be able not just to
live a minimally decent life but also to participate in the democratic processes
by which individual choices are socially constituted.
A democratic state, therefore,
must take steps to avoid these inequalities that deprive children of educational
attainment adequate to participate in the political processes.
134-136
meritocracy: distribute the resources
in proportion to children’s demonstrated natural ability and willingness to
learn
135 Rewarding dessert is a
reasonable way to distribute educational resources above the threshold level,
but surly not the only reasonable way.
136-139 In The Democratic
Standard Stated she pulls together the best elements from the three
responses to the “distribution problem:”
136 The standard of democratic
distribution developed so far can be formulated more precisely as two
principles. Call the first the
democratic authorization principle.
It recognizes the mistake in maximization by granting authority to
democratic institutions to determine the priority of education relative to other
social goods. Call the second the
democratic threshold principle.
It avoids the mistake in both equalization and meritocracy by specifying
that inequalities in the distribution of educational goods can be justified if,
but only if, they do not deprive any child of the ability to participate
effectively in the democratic process (which determines, among other things, the
priority of education relative to other social goods).
138 What constitutes a just
distribution of democratic education not only may vary among different
democratic societies but also may change quite significantly over time in the
same society.
To illustrate how her
distribution principle works, Gutmann turns to two specific distribution
problems: financing public schools and educating the disadvantaged.
139-148 Financing Public Schools:
139-147 Gutmann points out that
for a variety of reasons most of the funding for primary education in the United
States comes from State and Federal sources.
This presents significant problems for local democratic control of
primary education. Of course the
States, and the Federal government, need to allocate funding that provides an
adequate level for all school districts while allowing local districts the
ability to provide additional resources. This
leaves the question “What level of
ability or set of accomplishments should count as adequate?
According to her the commonly applied standard is
functional literacy:
147 …having he intellectual
capacity to get a job and to make a decent living for oneself and one’s family.”
This understanding…is simultaneously too weak and too strong to serve as
a democratic standard of adequacy.
It is too weak insofar as many Americans have the capacity to make a decent
living but not the capacity to understand the political issues that structure
their future choices and the future choices of their society.
Many high school students…lack the prerequisites for effective political
participation. Such skills may be
necessary, but they are surely not sufficient for being able to participate
effectively in American politics.
By democrat norms, they are functionally illiterate.
A more democratic definition of
functional literacy requires high school students to have the intellectual
skills and information that enable them to think about democratic politics and
to develop their deliberative skills and their knowledge through practical
experience.
147-148 So here, at the end of
the section on Financing Public [Secondary] Schools within the Chapter on
Distributing Primary Schooling, Gutmann identifies 148 “the
main problem with primary schooling today” is
not that it does enable high-school graduates to get good jobs
…but that
it does not prepare students for democratic citizenship.
It is important to note that
she does not develop what is involved
in (147) “…requiring high-school students to have the intellectual skills and
information that enable them to think about democratic politics and to develop
their deliberative skills and their knowledge through practical experience.”
We will return to this discussion on pp. 273-281 as we address adult
illiteracy, and in the “Conclusion: The Primacy of Political Education” (pp.
282-291).
148-159 Educating The Disadvantaged:
The second “distribution problem”
she discusses is whether 148 “for those students who are socially or
biologically handicapped, it might be impossible for states to provide enough
schooling to enable them to each he threshold, or so expensive as to call into
question the moral requirement to bring all handicapped children up to the
threshold.”
148-152 She discusses two cases,
Rebecca Paul, an economically disadvantaged first grade student with
disciplinary problems who receives no special services, and Amy Rowley a deaf
first grade student who receives extraordinary special services.
150 Amy’s parents took their
contention that even more resources should be provided to their daughter to the
Supreme Court which ruled against the core additional demand.
151 “What is striking about
Rebecca’s case…is not how much her school must spend to educate her, but how
little her school can do to overcome her problems…[and] reminds us that
democratic states cannot rely upon schools alone to help children reach the
threshold of learning.”
Clearly the distribution
principles require that both students
receive special services.
152-159 Gutmann discusses several
studies of the difference spending alone makes, and points out that the severity
of the handicap (whether physical or behavioral) certainly needs to be
considered. She goes on to discuss
legislation and regulations relating to handicapped education.
160-169 Integrating Schools:
160 She begins this discussion by
noting that children are each other’s educational resources, and that school
integration has been an important topic which is relevant to the “distribution
of students.”
Her lengthy discussion of efforts
in the last half century leads to a discussion of the role of courts in the
situation, and their role in a democratic society and democratic education (a
topic she says deserves a book in and of itself).
168-169 The democratic value of
community suggests that judges not impose unnecessary orders on local districts,
but he evidence of effective desegregation suggests that only the most
thoroughgoing plans are likely to succeed in achieving the democratic value of
integration. In this tension
between the values of local community and racial integration lies perhaps the
greatest dilemma of democratic education in our time.
Critics and supporters of desegregation alike agree that “moving children
around like checkers will not in itself improve matters.”
169-170 But if not integrating
schools guarantees bad results, then judge imposing thoroughgoing plans can help
reconstitute more democratic communities.
170-171 The Demands of Democratic Opportunity:
170 Democratic standards require
neither that the “inputs” nor the “outputs” of education be equalized.
We need not spend the same amount on very child’s education nor produce
equal educational results among children or groups of children.
The democratic interpretation of
equal educational opportunity requires instead that all educable children learn
enough to in the democratic process.
171 The demands of the threshold
principle are considerable: states should take greater responsibility for
financing primary education or for making more effective use of existing
resources; the content of education should be reoriented toward teaching
students the skills of democratic deliberation; and the federal government
should give local schools more money for educating handicapped children.
III. Chapter Six:
The Purposes of Higher Education:
173 Schooling does not stop serving democracy, however,
when it ceases to be compulsory—or when all educable students reach the
democratic threshold. Its purposes
change. Higher education should not
be necessary for inculcating basic democratic virtues, such as toleration,
truth-telling, and predisposition to nonviolence.
I doubt whether it can be. If
adolescents have not developed these character traits by the time they reach
college, it is probably too late for professors to inculcate them….
174-175 Control of the creation of ideas—whether by a
majority or a minority—subverts the ideal of
conscious social reproduction at the
heart of democratic education and democratic politics.
As institutional sanctuaries for free scholarly inquiry, universities can
help prevent such subversion. They
can provide a realm where new and unorthodox ideas are judged on their
intellectual merits; where the men and women who defend such ideas, provided
they defend them well, are not strangers but valuable members of a community.
Universities thereby serve democracy as sanctuaries of nonrepression.
In addition to creating and funding universities, democratic governments
can further this primary purpose of higher education in two ways: by respecting
what is commonly called the “academic freedom” of scholars, and by respecting
what might be called the “freedom of the academy.”
Academic Freedom and Freedom of the Academy:
175 [Academic freedom is] ...best
understood as a special right tied to the particular office of scholar, similar
in form (but different in content) to the particular rights of priests, doctors,
lawyers, and journalists. The core
of academic freedom is the freedom of scholars to assess existing theories,
established institutions, and widely held beliefs according to the canons of
truth adopted by their academic disciplines without fear of sanction by anyone
if they arrive at unpopular conclusions.
Academic freedom allows scholars to follow their autonomous judgment
wherever it leads them provided that they remain within the bounds of scholarly
standards of inquiry.
The proviso of remaining within the bounds of scholarly standards is
sometimes overlooked, but it is necessary to justify the social office that
scholars occupy….
176 Control of the educational
environment within which scholarship and teaching take place is the form of
academic freedom most neglected by its democratic defenders.
The historical reason for this neglect is not difficult to discern.
Whereas German universities were generally self-governing bodies of
scholars who made administrative decisions either collegially or through
democratically elected administrators, American universities (with few
exceptions) are administered by lay governing boards and administrators chosen
by these boards. Therefore, while
the scholar’s right of academic freedom in the German context could readily be
extended to a right collectively to control the academic environment of the
university, the academic freedom of faculty in the American context had to be
used as a defense against the university’s legally constituted (lay)
administrative authority.
177 Scholars and universities
that claim academic freedom against interference with their intellectual and
institutional pursuits must also acknowledge duties that accompany the right.
177-181 Gutmann elaborates on the
democratic purposes that academics and academic institutions ground these
freedoms.
Educating Officeholders:
181-184 Colleges and universities
also serve as “gatekeepers” to many of the most valuable social offices,
particularly in the professions.
Their role here, however, is not strictly peaking utilitarian (justified by its
social and economic utility).
Professional associations, think tanks, and research centers can similarly
foster and support professional development.
However (184) “universities serve democracy best when they try to
establish an environment conducive to creating knowledge that is not immediately
useful, appreciating ideas that are not presently poplar, and rewarding people
who are—and are likely to continue to be—intellectually but not necessarily
economically productive.”
Fostering Associations of Freedom:
189-190 Gutmann cites Derek Bok
(President of Harvard University, 1971-1991), who contends that the ideal
mutiversity would “avoid undertaking tasks that other organizations can
discharge equally well” and commit itself to supplying only those demands for
knowledge that are consistent with “the preservation of academic freedom, the
maintenance of high intellectual standards, the protection of academic pursuits
from outside interference, the rights of individuals affected by the university
not to be harmed in their legitimate interests, [and] the needs of those who
stand to benefit from the intellectual services that a vigorous university can
perform.”[1]
190-193 While, ideally, a college
or university would be a self-administered democratic community committed to
democratic education and the free scholarly inquiry, she recognizes that most
American institutions fall far short of such a model, but (193) “to the extent
that there is an ideal [collegiate] community, it is one whose members are
dedicated to free scholarly inquiry and who share authority in a complex pattern
that draws on the particular interests and competencies of administrators,
faculty, students, and trustees,.
This ideal serves a critique of autocratically governed universities that do Is
not secure the academic freedom of their faculty, but it also leaves room for a
variety of university communities to flourish, all of which are dedicated to
academic freedom but each of which support a different set of intellectual and
social commitments.”
193 A diversity of such
institutions provides a solid future for a deliberative democracy!
IV. Chapter Seven:
Distributing Higher Education:
Nondiscrimination:
195 [footnote] ...Justice
Frankfurter’s often-quoted summary of the “four essential freedoms” of
universities in Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 US 234 at 263: “It is the
business of a university to provide that atmosphere which is most conducive to
speculation experiment and creation.
It is an atmosphere in which there prevail ‘the four essential freedoms’
of a university—to determine for itself on academic grounds who may teach,
what may be taught, how it shall
be taught, and who may be admitted to study.”
Of course, the nondiscrimination
principle applies to university admissions, but relevant qualifications
and equal consideration are important factors in admissions.
197-202 Academic ability
is important, but ability to contribute to the academic life of the community
is almost equal importance. Here
creativity, perseverance, emotional maturity, aesthetic sensibility motivation
to learn, interest in improving the community (both the institution and the
larger one), leadership ability, and capacity to work well with others are all
important factors to consider in admitting students (and others) into the
university community. In addition
artistic, economic, racial, sexual, and cultural factors are relevant in
constituting such a community.
202-203 Test scores and grade
records can not reflect well these factors.
Thus, she maintains, while academic qualifications are the primary
factor, many of these other factors are ones which universities may properly
consider.
203-204 As these factors are
being weighted and evaluated it is important that “(203) “…similar cases be
treated similarly.”
Racial Discrimination:
204-218 Gutmann addresses discrimination for and against
blacks, and use of quotas:
204-207 First she considers
fundamentalist colleges which might discriminate against black students because
of Biblical commands. Mentioning
Catholic institutions which might discriminate against non-Catholic students,
and women’s colleges which discriminate against male students, she concludes
that a “purely” racial discrimination against black students violates the
non-discrimination principle.
207-211 She considers two
hypothetical cases where admissions places are “set aside for racial
minorities:”
210 Why, then, is there so much
public resistance to preferential admissions…for blacks?
The simplest, and I thinks strongest, explanation is historical: we have
learned from our history to be suspicious of racial classifications because they
have been used almost exclusively to subvert rather than to support democratic
justice.
210-211 This danger I mitigate by
(a) making preferential treatment the result of a series of autonomous decisions
by universities rather than of centrally imposed governmental policy, and (b)
requiring the procedures of all universities to satisfy the standards of
nondiscrimination. This would mean
that every year, the admissions committees of every university would have to
defend their preferences not only for blacks but also for alumni children,
athletes, and farm boy form Kansas above otherwise more qualified applicants.
It also means that as our society becomes more egalitarian and the
experience of being black becomes less relevant to the educational and social
purposes of universities, the case that members of admissions committees make
for preferring black applicants over more academically qualified white applicant
will become weaker.
211-218 Finally she discusses
admissions quotas. I will skip over
this discussion.
Compensatory College Education:
218-222 Gutmann notes that “many students today suffer,
through no fault of their own, from a sorely inadequate primary education.”
221 Gutmann contends that if a university admitted such students into a
remedial program which raised their educational that qualified them for regular
admissions such a policy would not be inappropriate.
Funding Higher Education:
222-222 Given the expense of
providing a higher education, universities may discriminate amongst qualified
applicants according to their ability to pay for the education, though they may
also subsidize expenses for qualified admitted students.
But it is rare a university could
provide scholarships or all admitted students.
222-231 Gutmann notes that in the
case of public universities, governments could do more to improve access for
students at public universities—and that it is even more permissible for them to
provide subsidies for economically disadvantaged students’ costs.
However her discussion draws attention
to distinguishing the “economic costs and benefits” of higher education from the
“democratic benefits” of such education.
This leads her to:
230 consider the question of the
extent to which democratic governments should subsidize private along with –or
instead of—public universities. To
answer this question, we must consider whether a purely public, a purely
private, or a mixed system of universities would best serve the democratic
purposes of higher education. If—as it
appears to be the case, at least in this country—private universities are better
able to resist political sources of repression…while public universities are
better able to resist private sources of discrimination, such as resistance by
trustees and alumni to admitting qualified Jews, blacks, and women, then
democratic governments have good reason to support a mixed system of higher
education, where both private and public universities flourish….A principled
pluralism in higher education depends on respecting the autonomy of private and
public universities if but only if they serve their democratic purposes.
Although higher education is not a necessary good for every citizen in
our society, it is still necessary that it be distributed in a nondiscriminatory
manner.
A democratic policy of funding universities cannot rest solely—or even
primarily—on a calculation of the economic costs and benefits of higher
education….
[1]
Derek Bok,
Beyond
the Ivory Tower: Social Responsibilities of the
Modern University (Cambridge: Harvard UP,
1982), pp. 76-77.
Midcoast Senior College Website
Email: hauptli@fiu.edu
Last revised on 03/27/23