Supplement For Second Class :
Preface, Introduction, and States and Education
Copyright © 2023 Bruce W.
Hauptli
Please read Gutmann’s Preface, Introduction, and
Chapter One: States and Education.
You might also find my contrast between “indoctrination “and “education”
interesting in
“Education,
Indoctrination, and Academic Freedom.”
We spent most of the first class discussing democracy and
education and didn’t get to the prepared supplements and the text. I
mentioned some of the things covered in my
A
Quick Introduction to “Deliberative Democracy “ and Democratic Education
and I recommend reading it, but will not cover it in class.
Questions about it are, of course,
appropriate!
I. Questions and concerns from the last class.
II. Discussion of Gutmann’s
“Preface to The Revised Edition” and “Introduction: Back to Basics:”
xii-xiii A guiding principle of
deliberative democracy is
reciprocity among free and equal individuals: citizens and their accountable
representatives owe one another justifications for the laws that collectively
bind them. A democracy
is deliberative to the extent that citizens and their accountable
representatives offer one another morally defensible reasons for mutually
binding laws in an ongoing process of mutual justification.
To the extent that a democracy is not deliberative, it treats people as
objects of legislation, as passive
subjects to be ruled, rather than as citizens who take part in governance by
accepting or rejecting the reasons they and their accountable representatives
offer for the laws and policies that mutually bind them.
Deliberative
democracy underscores the importance of
publicly supported education that develops the capacity to deliberate among
all children as future free and equal citizens.
The most justifiable way of making mutually binding decisions in a
representative democracy—including decisions not to deliberate about some
matters—is by deliberative decision making, where the decision makers are
accountable to the people who are most affected by their decisions.[1]
Well, must she insist on
“all students? “Should
she? Both here, and as we discuss
her ideas in this course, we will have to consider whether parents, perhaps even
“groups,” “have a right” to offer an alternative education.
Here we will also have to wonder whether a “competing” [democratic]
responsibility outweighs such a right.
In their Democracy and
Disagreement: Why Moral Conflict Cannot Be Avoided In Politics, and What Should
Be Done About It Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson maintain that making
deliberative democracy work requires that each
citizen must treat every other citizen reciprocally—that
is as a political equal worthy of respect.
When this attitude is present, each “side” in a disagreement can work
deliberatively to address, and potentially resolve the issue.
Even where this is not successful, it can yield understanding:
the
principles of accommodation are based on a value that lies at the core of
reciprocity and deliberation in a democracy—mutual respect.
It is what makes possible cooperation on fair terms.
Like toleration, mutual respect is a
form of agreeing to disagree.
But mutual respect demands more than toleration.
It requires a favorable attitude toward, and constructive interaction
with, the persons with whom one disagrees.
It consists in an excellence of
character that permits a democracy to flourish in the face of fundamental
moral disagreement. This is a
distinctively deliberative kind of character.
It is the character of individuals who are morally committed,
self-reflective about their commitments, discerning of the differences between
respectable and merely tolerable differences of opinion, and open to the
possibility of changing their minds or modifying their positions at some time in
the future if they confront unanswerable objections to their present point of
view.
Mutual respect not only helps
sustain a moral community in the face of conflict but also can contribute toward
resolving the conflict.[2]
In the first citation Gutmann
initially talks about a democracy being deliberative “to the extent
that,” but the subsequent “universality “of the requirements for a
democratic education for all children and that all citizens
have “a deliberative character” are seemingly extreme.
Here we will have to ask whether she is describing “an ideal” or whether
she is offering a “practical proposal” and either “most,” “many,” “a majority,”
or “a large minority” would be sufficient.
One possibility here is that Gutmann (and Thompson) might want to contend
that in our quasi-democracy too much emphasis has been placed on
“rights “ and almost no emphasis has been laid on
“responsibilities. “ I
develop this sort of idea in my
Hate Speech and Democratic Responsibility: Rights, Civility, and Responsibility
contending that responsibilities are more basic and can outweigh (years ago I
would have said ‘trump “) rights.
Back to Gutmann:
xiv Democratic Education offers a principled defense
of schooling whose aim is to teach the skills and virtues of democratic
deliberation within a social context where educational authority is
shared among parents, citizens, and professional educators.
11 The most
distinctive feature of a democratic theory of education is that it makes a
democratic virtue out of our inevitable disagreement over educational
problems. The democratic virtue,
too simply stated, is that we can publicly debate educational problems in a way
much more likely to increase our understanding of education and each other than
if we were to leave the management of the schools, as Kant suggests, “to depend
entirely upon the judgment of the most enlightened experts.
“The policies that result from
our democratic deliberations will not always be the right ones, but they will be
more enlightened—by the values and concerns of the many communities that
constitute a democracy—than those that would be made by unaccountable
educational experts.
What does she mean by “democratic virtue?”
How is it different from moral virtue,
religious virtue, cultural
virtue....
We should pause, here, to consider
how ancient the idea that education should be controlled by “experts.”
Think of Plato’s Republic and his views regarding education and democracy....
11-12 The primary aim of a democratic theory of education
is not to offer solutions to all the problems plaguing our educational
institutions, but to consider ways of resolving those problems that are
compatible with a commitment to democratic values.
A democratic theory of education provides principles that, in the face of
our social disagreements, help us judge (a) who should have authority to make
decisions about education, and (b) what the moral boundaries of that authority
are.
A
democratic theory is not a substitute for a moral ideal of education.
In a democratic society, we bring our moral ideals of education to bear
on how we raise our children, on who we support for school boards, and on what
educational policies we advocate.
But we cannot simply translate our own moral ideals of education, however
objective they are, in to public policy.
Only in a society in which all other citizens agreed with me would my
moral ideal simply translate into a political idea.
Really, she doesn’t want to
offer solutions? What does she mean
by “considering ways of resolving problems that are
compatible with a commitment to
“democratic values?”
Is her commitment to democratic
values more “basic,” or fundamental than to her “moral values?”
Does she believes her commitment is one all individuals share?
Does she believe all her fellow citizens share it?
Do you see elements of pragmatism
in her view? Could there be a
connection here to John Dewey’s A Common
Faith.
Going back to the final sentence
in the Gutmann cite, would it be enough for all the citizens to agree with her,
or would she also want them to have done so deliberatively?
13 A democratic society is responsible for educating not
just some but all children for citizenship.
Remember the earlier discussion
about ‘all.’
14 A democratic theory of education recognizes the
importance of empowering citizens to make educational policy and also of
constraining their choices among policies in accordance with those policies—of
nonrepression and nondiscrimination—that preserve the intellectual and social
foundations of democratic deliberations.
A society that empowers citizens to make educational policy, moderated by
these two principled constraints, recognizes the democratic ideal of education.
16 Authority over education is the theoretical issue that
organizes this book. The central
question posed by democratic education is: Who should have authority to shape
the education of future citizens?
III. Chapter One: States and Education:
In this chapter Gutmann discusses the educational theories
of Plato, John Locke, and John Stuart Mill distinguishing between: “The Family
State,” “The State of Families,” “The State of Individuals,” and “A Democratic
State.”
22-28 her discussion of
The Family State focuses on Plato’s
view that the ideal state is one ruled by philosophical experts [philosopher
kings]” who exercise absolute paternalistic control over the citizens and the
education future citizens. Plato
contends that “the ignorant many” are wholly unsuited for rule, and that the
philosophical rulers may tell “noble lies” to the citizens to maintain political
control because it is in the interests of the citizens who are incapable of
knowledge—and thus cannot rule. For
Plato democracy is a terrible form of government.
Gutmann’s discussion concludes:
28 the family sate attempts to
constrain our choices among ways of life and educational purposes in a way that
is incompatible with our identity as parents and citizens.
In its unsuccessful attempt to do so, it successfully demonstrates that
we cannot ground our conception of a good education merely on personal or
political preferences. Plato
presents a forceful case for resting educational authority exclusively with a
centralized state, a case grounded on the principle that knowledge should be
translated into political power. But
even the Platonic case is not sufficiently strong to override the claims of
parents and citizens to share in social reproduction, claims which I return in
defending a democratic state of education.
28-33 her discussion of
The State of Families characterizes
them as ones that place (32) “…educational authority exclusively in the hands of
parents, thereby permitting parents to predispose their children, through
education, to choose a way of life consistent with their familial heritage.”
She considers John Locke, Thomas Aquinas, and Charles Fried exemplars of
this orientation and in the footnote on p. 29 cites the Irish Constitution’s
claim that “recognizes the family as he natural primary and fundamental group of
Society and as a moral institution possessing inalienable and imprescriptible
rights, antecedent and superior to all positive law” as clarification that civil
society is a collection of individual families each of which has full authority
over the education of future citizens.
32-33 States that abdicate all
educational authority to parents sacrifice their most effective and justifiable
instrument for securing mutual respect among their citizens.
The “pluralism” commonly identified with the state of families is
superficial because its internal variety serves as little more than an ornament
for onlookers. Pluralism is an
important political value insofar as social diversity enriches our lives by
expanding our understanding of differing ways of life.
To reap the benefits of social diversity, children must be exposed to
ways of life different from their parents and—in the course of their
exposure—must embrace certain values, such as mutual respect among persons, that
make social diversity both possible and desirable.
33-41 She discusses John Stuart
Mill who embraces The State of
Individuals which (34) “…responds to the weakness of both the family state
and the state of individuals by championing the dual goals of
opportunity for choice and
neutrality among conceptions of the
good life. A just educational
authority must not bias children’s choices among good lives, but it must provide
every child with an opportunity to choose freely and rationally among the widest
range of lives.”
35 Her criticism of this
orientation builds on the claim that “…the capacity for rational choice requires
that we place some prior limitations on children’s choices.
To have a rational sense of what we want to become, we need to know who
we are; otherwise our choices will be endless and meaningless.”
37 She contends that “the same
argument that holds against the family state holds against the state of
individuals: being right is not a necessary or sufficient condition because
parents and citizens have a legitimate interest (independent of their
“rightness”) in passing some of their most salient values on to their children.”
Going on to say in the next paragraph “why must freedom be the sole end
of education, given that most of us value things that conflict with freedom?
We value, for example, the moral sensibility that enables us to
discriminate between good and bad lives.
A well-cultivated moral character constrains choice among lives at least
as much as it expands choice.”
39
We disagree over the relative value of freedom and virtue, the
nature of the good life, and the elements of moral character.
But our desire to search for a
more inclusive ground presupposes a common commitment that is, broadly speaking,
political.
We are committed to collectively
re-creating the society that we
share. Although
we are not collectively committed to any particular set of
educational aims, we are committed to
arriving at an agreement on our
educational aims (an agreement that could take the form of justifying a diverse
set of educational aims and authorities).
Who is included in her ‘we’?
She wrote in 1987 and 1999, and I think she clearly believe it applies
today—but is this true of all of us, most of us, a majority of us, …?
The importance of this question needs to be emphasized, as is evidenced
by the current situation in Florida.
Of course, in February of 2023 any discussion of “states and education “is going
to suggest a discussion of the situation in Florida.
41-47 Finally, she advances
A Democratic State of Education in
contrast to the other conceptions:
42 the broad distribution of
educational authority among citizens, parents, and professional educators
supports the core value of democracy: conscious social reproduction in its most
inclusive form. Unlike a
family state, a democratic state recognizes the value of parental
education in perpetuating particular conception of the good life.
Unlike a state of families, a
democratic state recognizes the value of professional authority in enabling
children to appreciate and to evaluate ways of life other than those favored by
their families. Unlike a
state of individuals, a democratic
state recognizes the value of political education in predisposing children to
accept those ways of life that are consistent with sharing the rights and
responsibilities of citizenship in a democratic society.
A democratic state is
therefore committed to allocating educational authority in such a way as to
provide its members with an education adequate to participating in democratic
politics, to choosing among (a limited range of) good lives, and to sharing in
the several sub-communities, such as families, that impart identity to the lives
of its citizens.
44 …a democratic state must aid
children in developing the capacity to understand and to evaluate competing
conceptions of the good life and the good society.
The value of critical deliberation among good lives and good societies
would be neglected by a society that inculcated in children uncritical
acceptance of any particular way or ways of (personal and political) life….To
integrate the value of critical deliberation among good lives, we must defend
some principled limits on political and parental authority over education,
limits that in particular require parents and states to cede some educational
authority to professional educators.
One limit is that of
nonrepression.
45
A second principled limit on legitimate democratic authority, which also
follows from the primary of democratic education, is
nondiscrimination.
An important background point here
is a contrast between the pluralistic view under consideration and Plato’s view
that there is only one good life for human beings—a life n accord of the
dictates of deductive philosophical wisdom—and if individuals can not attain the
level of philosophical knowledge needed to understand this life, they needed to
have this good life imposed upon them.
The idea that there is only one good life has been deeply ingrained in
Western Culture (whether the discussion is regarding morality or the good life
more generally), though Plato’s particular view has never gained the wide
acceptance he hoped for.
46-47 In the chapters that follow, I treat the theory just
sketched as a guide to moral reasoning rather than as a set of rigid rules from
which we can logically derive public policies.
The theory of democratic education builds upon a critique of most
influential existing theories rather than upon a closed system of self-evident
axioms,….It makes no claim to being a logically tight system of axioms,
principles, and conclusions that flow from them….The distinctive virtue of a
democratic theory of education is that its principles and conclusion are
compatible with our commitment to share the rights and the obligations of
citizenship with people who do not share our complete conception of the good
life. To the extent that Americans
share (or insist on living in a way that requires us to share) this commitment,
a democratic theory of education commands our allegiance.
[1] Amy
Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton:
Princeton U.P., [1987] 1999), p. xii-xiii.
Emphasis (bold and italics) have been
added and will be added often to subsequent
citations.
All further citations to this work in
this and the ensuing supplements will be begin
with the page number as this one did, but will
have no further footnotes.
[2] Amy
Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and
Disagreement: Why Moral Conflict Cannot Be
Avoided In Politics, and What Should Be Done
About It (Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1996), pp.
79-80.
Emphasis [bold] added to the passage.
For a quick characterization of
deliberative democracy see my
“A Quick Introduction To Deliberative Democracy
and Democratic Education.”
Midcoast Senior College Website
Email: hauptli@fiu.edu
Last revised on 03/20/23