Lectures on
Descartes’ First Three Meditations
Copyright © 2015 Bruce W.
Hauptli
1. Introduction to
Descartes’ Meditations (1641):
Descartes lived from 1596 to 1650.
Between 1618 and 1621 he pursued a study of mathematics which resulted in
the discovery and formulation of what we now call “analytic geometry”—that
branch of mathematics which relates the algebraic and geometric studies.
The “Cartesian Coordinate System” which you were taught in High School
gets its name from him. He also did
important work in the field of optics, and his
Meditations on First Philosophy was
published in 1641.
To put his philosophy in perspective we should note that as philosophers
seek to clarify our concepts and viewpoints one of the problems they regularly
encounter is the question of justification.
The area of philosophy called
epistemology is especially concerned with the
justifiability of our knowledge
claims. In his
Theaetetus Plato approaches the
question of justification by asking “How
we can tell whether we are dreaming or awake?” Remember that we rarely take
“dream reports” as indicative of the true character of reality, while we far
more frequently (but, of course, not always) take “awakened reports” as
indicative of true states of affairs.
The “dreaming” question, like all philosophical questions seems trivial,
yet its deceptive simplicity belies the complexity which arises as one tries to
answer it.
Since we base most of our
knowledge claims upon our sensory
experience, if we can not tell whether our experiences are the fluff of
dreams or the reports of the senses when we are awake, it seems that the
experiences we rely upon may not be very reliable ones.
No one, for example, would write their chemistry lab reports on the basis
of last night’s dreams.
Well, how
do we tell whether we are awake or
asleep? If we can’t tell which
state we are in, can we place any reliability, credence, or worth in the
reports?
When the foundations of our knowledge claims are unclear
some philosophic work is necessary.
Descartes undertakes the project of trying to find a
firm foundation for our knowledge
claims. He does this because, in
part, of the times in which he lives.
As we have seen, the Medieval period marked a significant departure from
the Ancient one—thinkers like St. Anselm maintained that reason must take its
cues from certain truths of faith.
They held that philosophy is important as we try to come to understand what we
antecedently believe (through faith).
Ancient thinkers like Plato, by contrast, held that we should believe
what we can rationally establish.
Thus contrast Plato’s Socrates’ statement that “I am the kind of man who listens
only to the argument that on reflection seems best to me” [Crito,
46b] with Anselm’s desire to come to understand what he antecedently believes.
The Modern period (which we have already encountered with our reading of
selections from Hobbes’ Leviathan) is
characterized by an immense “faith” in our ability to rationally uncover
universal and general truths about the world—it is, then a return to the
philosophical view of the Ancients.
As such a return, however, it is conditioned by the loss of both the feelings of
security and of certainty which the Medieval period provided with its
“faith-based” foundation. This loss
did not occur because of the development of a clear-cut and widely-accepted
“replacement” methodology however.
The methodology of the new empirical sciences was still under development in
Descartes’ time.
Thus skepticism and
relativism loomed large.
With the Renaissance, the rediscovery of the Greek skeptical texts
encouraged this feeling of insecurity while eating away at the faith which
grounded the Medieval period. It
became clear that there were “high” cultures which were not grounded on the sort
of faith and belief which were at the core of Medieval civilization.
Obviously the problem of justifying a standard of knowledge (or of
reality, or of morality) did not arise as long as there was an unchallenged
criterion, but in an age of intellectual revolution these problems are thrust
into prominence.
Descartes agrees with Galileo that the “book of nature” is written in the
language of mathematics—he believes the world was created according to some
“simple” mathematical formulae. His
ability to hook together geometry and algebra reinforced this view.
He wants to firmly ground his knowledge claims, and thus wants to
establish that they are truly beyond
doubt—that they are
certain. There are several
different senses of certainty (psychological certainty, logical certainty, and
metaphysical certainty), and it is the latter which Descartes wants.
Descartes believes he can show that there is one claim which legitimately
has this degree of surety—his cogito
argument (his famous “I think, therefore I am”—or “cogito,
ergo sum”) gives us this level of certainty.
He will go on to justify much of human knowledge (including knowledge of
a deity) and to develop a dualistic metaphysics.
He would beat the skeptics at their own game: his procedure is to doubt
everything tinged with any doubt (to reject everything which he can) until he
finds something which can not be doubted.
With this claim he will have a foundation upon which other knowledge
claims may rest securely. Descartes
wants to do more than refute skepticism however.
He wants to show that the foundation which he “uncovers” is one which can
be built upon, and this means he must get
beyond subjectivity. Here his
proof of the existence of a deity comes in—the argument he develops for the
existence of an all-powerful, all-knowing, and benevolent deity provide him with
the intellectual tool to move with certainty beyond knowledge of subjectivity.
Thus far this introduction to has covered only the “epistemological”[1]
aspects of Descartes’ thought, and it is already too long.
The Meditations are as
well-known and important for their “metaphysical”[2]
content as they are for their epistemological content however, and we need to
understand this before we look at the text.
The general introductory story regarding Descartes’ metaphysics maintains
that he offers a “dualistic metaphysic”
which offers a picture of reality as bifurcated into two distinct categories of
“things:” the mental and the
physical.
To see the difference between
these two categories of reality, begin by considering your “visual field” (the
images you experience when you pay attention to your visual experience.
Concentrating on this “field,” try and answer the question “Where, in
physical space, does this visual field reside?”
Is it to be located in the brain?
Descartes holds that “physical things” all have one central
characteristic: they are extended (or have some shape or other).
While they can change their shapes (surely this is what we want to do
when we visit our health clubs), they always have some shape or other.
According to Descartes, however, “mental things” are not correctly
characterized as having a shape.
Instead, they are characterized as having experience.
Descartes holds that the mental and physical are distinct categories of
things, and any thing must be one or the other (but not both).
This “dualistic picture” of Descartes’ metaphysics is right as far as it
goes, but he actually holds that there are
three distinct kinds of things.
In addition to physical objects (also called “extended things” by him),
and mental objects (also called “minds,” or “selves” by him), there is also a
deity.
Strictly speaking, this “thing” is not physical or mental (at least not
in the senses discussed thus far).
The minds and objects discussed thus far are all
finite in nature, and the deity which
he discusses is infinite.
Mention of Descartes’ deity, however, seems to take us right back to the
“picture” of the world offered by the Medieval world-view!
It is important to note, however, that while he was a Catholic, the deity
he discusses in the Meditations is better seen as a “god of the philosophers“[3]—this
deity fulfills a particular role, and this role is what is important not any
“personalistic” characteristics of the deity.
For Descartes, the deity will provide a causal and explanatory terminus
(and end for all questions of causation and justification), but this deity will
be bereft of most of the Medieval adornments.
It is also
important to note that from the “modern” view-point of Descartes, the most
appropriate way to approach any inquiry—including one about a deity it to follow
the a chain of deductive reasoning.
The goal is to come to know things,
and it should be clear, is not to be developed by examining texts or consulting
religious or scriptural authorities.
Instead, it is to be had by rationally examining the “book of nature.”
To see this clearly, however, we must turn to the text itself.
2. The First
Meditation:[4]
533 Goal—he desires to establish
firm knowledge in the sciences.
Type of doubt—he recommends that
we doubt whatever is not indubitable or entirely certain—even what is only
slightly tinged or possibly tinged!
It is general—he doesn’t doubt
each proposition but, rather, doubts them in groups.
Sometimes, he notes, the senses
mislead us!
-But, perhaps, sometimes the
senses don’t—when we are “close” to the object, etc.
The dreaming argument: But I do
dream: “I have been deceived in sleep by
similar perceptions.”
-534 Surely “simples” are
true whether one is awake or dreaming?
That is, whether my experiences are dreaming or awakened ones, surely the
“simple components” of the experiences (those out of which the “complexes” are
formed) provide me with a solid (and valid) base of knowledge claims.
Can’t I suppose that dream images still represent the world somewhat?
That is, may I suppose that there are simples like the elements in a
picture (that the structure of the painting may be all wrong, as it were, but
that the elements in it actually correspond or represent?).
“Be that as it may, there is
fixed in my mind a certain opinion of long standing, namely that there exists a
God who is able to do anything and by whom I, such as I am, have been created.
How do I know that He did not bring it about that there is no earth at
all, no heavens, no extended thing, no shape, no size, no place, and yet bring
it about that all these things appear to me to exist precisely as they do now?
Moreover, since I judge that others sometimes make mistakes in matters
that they believe they know most perfectly, may I not, in like fashion, be
deceived every time I add two and three or count the sides of a square, or
perform an even simpler operation, if that can be imagined?”
-That is, how do I know that any
claims about the “simple” elements of experience are valid?
I will suppose an “evil genius” who is at once exceedingly potent and
deceitful, and who employs all his artifice to deceive me.
-Note that the sense of ‘evil’
here is epistemic, not moral or theological!
535 I will be a skeptic and
suspend judgment on all claims.
3. The Second
Meditation:
535 Doubt...until I shall
find something that is certain.
535-536
The
Cogito:
-What of “I walk therefore I
am?”
-What if Hamlet says “I
think therefore I am”?
-What of Jorge Luis Borges’
“The Circular Ruins,”[5]
or Lewis Carroll’s Through the
Looking-Glass?[6]
-Occurrent
vs. substantial conceptions of the
self.
-Indubitability—three
senses: psychological, logical, and metaphysical.
536
Sum res cogitans: but I do not yet know with sufficient clearness what I
am, though assured that I am.
-What, then, did I formerly
think I was?
--A “rational animal”—this
leaves us with two questions to answer (“What is rationality?” and “What is an
animal?”) and we have no way of getting started here.
--Body:
Can I affirm that I possess any one of the attributes of which I have lately
spoken as belonging to the nature of body?
After attentively considering them in my own mind, I find none of them
that can properly be said to belong to myself.
--Soul:
nutrition, walking (locomotion), perception?
--Thinking:
I am a thinking thing.
536-537 My knowledge that I
am a thinking thing is not dependent on things which are not certain.
-Is this the case?
-Memory and occurrent
conception of the self: Christopher Nolen’s movie
Memento [2000]—without short-term
memory, we get a very different “self!”
Of course there is also “long-term” memory, and other sorts!
Moreover, does memory entail any sort of certainty?
-Personal identity and
Theseus’ ship—my “updated case would have one imagine a ship (Theseus’) which is
rebuilt plank by plank (with the original planks saved and then reassembled
according to the original plan. The
question is: “Which of the resultant ships is Theseus’ ship?”
537 Nonetheless, Descartes
concludes that he knows he is an enduring thing—a
substance:
-“For it is so obvious that
it is I who doubt, I who understand, and I who will, that there is nothing by
which it could be explained more clearly.
But indeed it is also the same “I” who imagines; for although perhaps, as
I supposed before, absolutely noting that I imagined is true, still the very
power of imagining really does exist, and constitutes a part of my thought.
Finally, it is this same “I” who senses or who is cognizant of bodily
things as if through the senses….”
537-539
Wax experiment: something extended.
-538 I know the wax by my
reason—not by senses or imagination!
-539 Each time I know the
wax, I know myself better (than I know the wax).
I readily discover that
there is nothing more easily or clearly apprehended than my own mind—we know our
minds better than we know our bodies.
4. Preparation
for the Third Meditation:
Building a
bridge from the “subjective world” to the “objective world.”
Note: The demon is the troll
under the bridge!
He seeks the identification of a characteristic of
some ideas which assures they
represent.
Dark Pool
Analogy: if you are swimming alone in a dark pool and you feel something
brush your leg, it is natural to reach the (alarming) conclusion that you are
not alone.
The “Anthropology
Example:”[7]
find a tribe which has a drawing of a complex machine, or an advanced metal
object:
tells us something about the
level of development of the tribe.
They must have such machines (or the imagination necessary to conceive of them),
or the ability to make, trade, or otherwise acquire such objects.
degrees of reality and how this
applies to ideas.
-formal
reality of an idea—a “lower level” than the formal reality of minds, since
ideas are dependent upon minds);
-objective
reality of an idea—the
referential content (or representational capacity) of the idea.
The Causal
Principle:
ex nihilo nihil fit[8]
(Descartes believes it and the principle are equivalent.
Aristotelian analysis of
causation: the efficient cause explains the
existence of a thing, while the
formal cause explains the nature of
that thing.
Cause, reason, and
explanation.
Together the causal
principle, the idea of the degrees of reality of ideas (objective reality), the
idea of a deity and Descartes’ knowledge that he does not have the power to
cause this idea yield the proof that this deity exists!
5. The Third
Meditation:
539 Those modes of
consciousness exist in me—substance vs.
attribute, and attribute vs. mode.
There is nothing that gives
me assurance of the cogito’s truth except
the clear and distinct perception of what I affirm.
Can I generalize this finding (can I say that all that I perceive
clearly and distinctly is true)?
What did I clearly and
distinctly “perceive” before? The
tendency to believe that besides the ideas, there were “external things” which
these ideas represented (the problem of representationalism).
539-540 Conflict between the
“metaphysical doubt,” on the one hand, and the “cogito”
and “clear and distinct ideas,” on the other.
Here we encounter Descartes’ “epistemological schizophrenia.”
540 Ideas alone (without a
representational claim) are not
false.
Falsity arises only with the
representational claim.
Ideas are generally
considered to be innate, adventitious
(caused from without), or factitious
(I cause them).
We must inquire into the
grounds for the representational claim of our ideas:
-540-541 Could the
representational claim of my ideas be grounded in the fact that I am
taught the representational nature of my
ideas by nature? Here, “...all
I have in mind is that I am driven by a
spontaneous impulse to believe this, and not that
some
light of nature is showing
me that it is true. These are two
very different things. For whatever
is shown me by this light of nature, for example that from the fact that I
doubt, it follows that I am, and the like, cannot in any way be doubtful.
This owing to the fact that there can be no other faculty that I can
trust as much as this light and which could teach that these things are not
true. But as far as natural
impulses are concerned....”
-541 Could the
representational claim be justified by the fact that various of my ideas are
not dependent upon my will? “I
may have powers I don’t know of....”
-Moreover, even if the ideas
“proceed from” objects, “...it is not a necessary consequence that they must be
like them.”
541-542
Causal Principle:
Dependency of
attributes/modes on substances; dependence of finite upon infinite substance:
Everything which exists has a cause, or
ex nihilo nihil fit.
-Efficient and total
cause—idea that the cause must be “explanatory” as well as “efficient”—it must
not only have the power, but also the reason, to bring about the effect:
--cause of a things
existence—efficient cause.
--542 cause of a thing’s
nature or character—formal cause.
-Cause of idea must be at
least real enough to cause this sort of idea (e.g., one which has this sort of
object—objective reality=representative capacity).
-Degrees of reality as it
applies to ideas.
-Objective
reality—representational capacity.
-Formal (actual)
reality—nonideational reality (reality which is not representative but, rather,
actual). Our ideas have formal
reality as modes of thought—as such, of course, they are neither true nor false
however. It is their objective
reality which is in question, then, here.
--Anthropology example:
Bernard Williams notes that if we find a primitive tribe which has a picture of
a complex machine, this tells us something about the level of development of the
tribe. They must have such machines
or the imagination necessary to conceive of them.
Higher order understanding exhibited by the picture betokens a higher
order of cultural development.[9]
“...in order that an idea
may contain this objective reality rather than that, it must doubtless derive it
from some cause in which is found at least as much formal reality as the idea
contains objective.”
542 If some idea is such
that I can’t cause it—then I am not
alone. Dark Pool Analogy: if you
are swimming alone in a dark pool and you feel something brush your leg, it is
natural to reach the (alarming) conclusion that you are not alone.
I have various ideas—I could
cause them.
543 There remains, then, the
idea of god.
The proof that I am not the cause of it.
-Positive and negative
conception of the deity.
-543-544 Perhaps I am god?
No, not even potentially! (Were I so, I would have made me different—no
doubts!).
-544-545 Could I, and my
idea, have been created by a lesser deity—still need god to cause this positive
idea!
-A
god—why not many? Not a committee
because of the simplicity and relatedness of the conceptions.
[A camel is a horse made by a committee].
The idea of god is
innate in me.
545 This deity can not be a
deceiver. “For it is manifest by
the light of nature that fraud and deception depend on some defect.”
-Note that here, again, we
have and appeal to the “light of nature”—what legitimates such an appeal?[10]
6. The Argument for his Deity’s Existence In
Outline:
This proof presupposes
his cogito (his “proof of himself”),
as well as his ideas (see below), and his “knowledge” of his “finitude”
(especially his character as a doubter).
It presupposes the
existence of the idea of an all-powerful, all-knowing, and all-good
infinite (and perfect) being.
It also presupposes
the “Causal Principle.”
-Clarify how this principle
applies to ideas (formal vs.·representative
reality [or objective reality]).
If there is an idea I don’t
cause, I am not alone.
-Finite substance/infinite
substance and idea of a deity.
-Positive and negative
infinity and idea of a deity.
-Nothing short of a deity
could cause (ultimately) the idea of a deity.
-I am not a potential
deity or in the process of becoming an actual one.
-This idea could not be the
result of the work of a “committee.”
Therefore, the deity exists,
as only it could cause this idea.
“The light of reason” shows
that “deception is an imperfection.”
-Another presumption!
-About “the light of reason”
generally.
7. Comparison
and contrast With Anselm’s Argument:
Anselm is concerned to prove
necessary existence, while Descartes
just wants to prove existence. The
difference between ontological and causal proofs here is a difference in the
philosophers’ purposes, their types of premises and arguments, and in their
conclusions.
Anselm begins with
“essences” and metaphysical truths, while Descartes begins with doubt and self.
Anselm begins with faith
which he tries to understand, Descartes wants to establish the existence of the
deity from human understanding alone to provide a ground for “science” and human
knowledge of the world.
8. Problems
with Descartes’ Argument for Skepticism:
(A) Universal Deception:
The senses sometimes mislead
usàperhaps
they always do;
some
paintings are forgeriesàperhaps
they all are.[11]
Gilbert Ryle: “I must say a
little about the quite general argument from the notorious limitations and
fallibility of our senses to the impossibility of our getting to know anything
at all by looking, listening and touching.
A country which had no coinage
would offer no scope to counterfeiters.
There would be nothing for them to manufacture or pass counterfeits of.
They could, if they wished, manufacture and give away decorated disks of
brass or lead, which the public might be pleased to get.
But these would not be false coins.
There can be false coins only where there are coins made of the proper
materials by the proper authorities.
In a country where there is a
coinage, false coins can be manufactured and passed; and the counterfeiting
might be so efficient that an ordinary citizen, unable to tell which were false
and which were genuine coins, might become suspicious of the genuineness of any
particular coin that he received.
But however general his suspicions might be, there remains one proposition which
he cannot entertain, the proposition, namely, that it is possible that all coins
are counterfeits. For there must be
an answer to the question ‘Counterfeits of what?’”[12]
J.L. Austin “...it is
important to remember that talk of deception only makes sense against a
background of general non-deception.
(You can’t fool all of the people all of the time.)
It must be possible to recognize a case of deception by checking
the odd cases against the more normal ones.”[13]
(B) Dreaming:
G.E. Moore: “...can he
[Descartes] consistently combine this proposition that he knows that dreams have
occurred, with his conclusion that he does not know that he is not dreaming?
Can anybody possibly know that dreams have occurred, if, at the time, he
does not himself know that he is not dreaming?
If he is dreaming, it may be that he is only dreaming that dreams have
occurred; and if he does not know that he is not dreaming, can he possibly know
that he is not only dreaming that dreams have occurred?
Can he possibly know therefore that dreams have occurred?
I do not think that he can; and therefore I think that anyone who uses
this premise and also asserts the conclusion that nobody ever knows that he is
not dreaming, is guilty of an inconsistency.”[14]
9. Problems
With the Second Meditation:
(A). Multiple personalities and the
cogito.
(B). In his
Tragic Sense of Life, Miguel de Unamuno offers the following critique of
Descartes:
the defect of
Descartes’...[argument] lies in his resolution to empty himself of himself, of
Descartes, of the real man, the man of flesh and bone, the man who does not want
to die, in order that he might be a mere thinker—that is, an abstraction.
But the real man returned and thrust himself into his philosophy....
The truth is sum, ergo cogito—I
am, therefore I think, although not everything that is thinks.
Is not conscious thinking above all consciousness of being?
Is pure thought possible, without consciousness of self, without
personality?[15]
(C). What right of his to the statement that he is
a thinking substance?
(D). What of his right to talk about a continuing
substance—the problem of multiple selves.
[1] That is,
the elements dealing with his “theory of
knowledge”—his views on knowledge,
justification, and certainty.
[2] That is,
for his views about the fundamental nature of
(or characteristics of) reality.
[3] For
clarification of the distinction between the
sort of deity discussed by philosophers and the
deity as many conceive it, cf., Anthony Kenny,
The God
of the Philosophers (Oxford: Oxford U.P.,
1979).
[4] The notes
are to Donald A. Cress’ translation of Descartes
Meditations on First Philosophy [1641]
which was published in 1993, as reproduced in
Classics of Western Philosophy (seventh
edition), ed. Steven Cahn (Belmont: Wadsworth,
2012), pp. 533-546.
[5] Cf.,
Jorge Luis Borges, “The Circular Ruins,” in
The Light
Fantastic, ed. Harry Harrison (N.Y.:
Scribners, 1971).
[6] Cf.,
“Chapter IV. Tweedledum and Tweedledee,” in
Louis Carroll,
Through
The Looking Glass [1871], in
The
Annotated Alice: Alice’s Adventures in
Wonderland and Through the Looking Glass,
ed. Martin Gardner (N.Y.: Meridian, 1963), pp.
229-244.
[7] This
example is discussed in detail in Bernard
Williams, in his
Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry
(Harmonsworth: Penguin, 1978), pp. 138-142.
[8] That is,
“nothing is created from nothing.”
[9] Cf.,
Bernard Williams,
Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, op. cit.,
p. 139.
[10] Cf.,
John Morris, “Descartes’ Natural Light,”
Journal
of the History of Philosophy v. 11 (1973),
pp. 169-187.
[11] Cf.,
Jay Rosenberg,
The
Practice of Philosophy (Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice Hall, 1984), pp. 15-17.
[12] Gilbert
Ryle,
Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1960),
pp. 94-95.
[13] J.L.
Austin,
Sense and Sensibilia (Oxford: Oxford U.P.,
1962), p. 11.
Cf., also Anthony Kenny, Descartes: A
Study of His Philosophy (New York: Random House,
1968), p. 25.
[14] G.E.
Moore, “Certainty,” in his Philosophical
Papers (London George Allen & Unwin, 1959),
pp. 227-251, p. 249.
Cf., “Can I Know That I Am Not
Dreaming?,” by D. Blumenfeld and J.B.
Blumenfeld, in Descartes: Critical and
Interpretive Essays, ed. Michael Hooker
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins U.P., 1978), pp.
234-235.
[15] Miguel
de Unamuno, Tragic Sense of Life, trans.
C.J. Flitch (N.Y.: Macmillan, 1921), p. 34.
File revised on 04/15/2015.